메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 5, Issue , 2004, Pages 323-360

From reason to self-realisation? Axel Honneth and the 'ethical turn' in critical theory

Author keywords

Axel Honneth; Critique; Reason; Recognition; Self realisation; The good

Indexed keywords


EID: 10844290982     PISSN: 14409917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1163/1568516042653585     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (21)

References (90)
  • 1
    • 0004130431 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA, MIT Press
    • "Philosophy, working together with the reconstructive sciences, can only throw light on the situations in which we find ourselves. It can contribute to our learning to understand the ambivalences that we come up against as just so many appeals to increasing responsibilities within a contracting space of possibility." Jürgen Habermas, Postmetaphysical Thinking, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1992, p. 146, translation altered. It is just this resignation to a 'contracting space of possibility' that concerns me.
    • (1992) Postmetaphysical Thinking , pp. 146
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 2
    • 0001905671 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Basil Blackwell
    • For an exemplary statement of this more pragmatic version of critical theory, see Thomas McCarthy's contribution to David Hoy and Thomas McCarthy, Critical Theory, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1994.
    • (1994) Critical Theory
    • McCarthy, T.1    Hoy, D.2    McCarthy, T.3
  • 3
    • 10844283305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critical theory after Habermas
    • 2005, Nikolas Kompridis, Guest Editor
    • Proposals for post-Habermasian models of critical theory by Jay Bernstein, James Bohman, Axel Honneth, Maeve Cooke, and Nikolas Kompridis are advanced in "Critical Theory after Habermas," a special issue of The International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. 11, no. 2, 2005, Nikolas Kompridis, Guest Editor.
    • The International Journal of Philosophical Studies , vol.11 , Issue.2 SPEC. ISSUE
    • Bernstein, J.1    Bohman, J.2    Honneth, A.3    Cooke, M.4    Kompridis, N.5
  • 4
    • 3142693842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Examples of this turn in recent critical theory are Martin Seel's Versuch über die Form des Glücks, Alessandro Ferrara's Reflective Authenticity, Christoph Menke's, Tragödie im Sittlichkeit, and Axel Honneth's The Struggle for Recognition.
    • Versuch Über Die Form des Glücks
    • Seel, M.1
  • 5
    • 0002410422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Examples of this turn in recent critical theory are Martin Seel's Versuch über die Form des Glücks, Alessandro Ferrara's Reflective Authenticity, Christoph Menke's, Tragödie im Sittlichkeit, and Axel Honneth's The Struggle for Recognition.
    • Reflective Authenticity
    • Ferrara, A.1
  • 6
    • 10844241384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Examples of this turn in recent critical theory are Martin Seel's Versuch über die Form des Glücks, Alessandro Ferrara's Reflective Authenticity, Christoph Menke's, Tragödie im Sittlichkeit, and Axel Honneth's The Struggle for Recognition.
    • Tragödie im Sittlichkeit
    • Menke, C.1
  • 7
    • 0004073426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Examples of this turn in recent critical theory are Martin Seel's Versuch über die Form des Glücks, Alessandro Ferrara's Reflective Authenticity, Christoph Menke's, Tragödie im Sittlichkeit, and Axel Honneth's The Struggle for Recognition.
    • The Struggle for Recognition
    • Honneth, A.1
  • 8
    • 84937318241 scopus 로고
    • The social dynamics of disrespect: On the situation of critical theory today
    • October
    • I shall be referring to the following texts: Axel Honneth, "The Social Dynamics of Disrespect: On the Situation of Critical Theory Today," in Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory, vol. 1, no. 2, October, 1994, p. 264. Axel Honneth, "Pathologies of the Social: The Past and Present of Social Philosophy," in ed. David Rasmussen, Handbook of Critical Theory, Oxford, Blackwell, 1996, pp. 369-398. Axel Honneth, Suffering from Indeterminacy, Assen, Van Gorcum, 2000. Axel Honneth, "Redistribution as Recognition: A Response to Nancy Fraser," in Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange, London, Verso, 2003.
    • (1994) Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory , vol.1 , Issue.2 , pp. 264
    • Honneth, A.1
  • 9
    • 10844266099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pathologies of the social: The past and present of social philosophy
    • David Rasmussen, Oxford, Blackwell
    • I shall be referring to the following texts: Axel Honneth, "The Social Dynamics of Disrespect: On the Situation of Critical Theory Today," in Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory, vol. 1, no. 2, October, 1994, p. 264. Axel Honneth, "Pathologies of the Social: The Past and Present of Social Philosophy," in ed. David Rasmussen, Handbook of Critical Theory, Oxford, Blackwell, 1996, pp. 369-398. Axel Honneth, Suffering from Indeterminacy, Assen, Van Gorcum, 2000. Axel Honneth, "Redistribution as Recognition: A Response to Nancy Fraser," in Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange, London, Verso, 2003.
    • (1996) Handbook of Critical Theory , pp. 369-398
    • Honneth, A.1
  • 10
    • 10844290524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Assen, Van Gorcum
    • I shall be referring to the following texts: Axel Honneth, "The Social Dynamics of Disrespect: On the Situation of Critical Theory Today," in Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory, vol. 1, no. 2, October, 1994, p. 264. Axel Honneth, "Pathologies of the Social: The Past and Present of Social Philosophy," in ed. David Rasmussen, Handbook of Critical Theory, Oxford, Blackwell, 1996, pp. 369-398. Axel Honneth, Suffering from Indeterminacy, Assen, Van Gorcum, 2000. Axel Honneth, "Redistribution as Recognition: A Response to Nancy Fraser," in Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange, London, Verso, 2003.
    • (2000) Suffering from Indeterminacy
    • Honneth, A.1
  • 11
    • 23844461578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Redistribution as recognition: A response to Nancy Fraser
    • Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, London, Verso
    • I shall be referring to the following texts: Axel Honneth, "The Social Dynamics of Disrespect: On the Situation of Critical Theory Today," in Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory, vol. 1, no. 2, October, 1994, p. 264. Axel Honneth, "Pathologies of the Social: The Past and Present of Social Philosophy," in ed. David Rasmussen, Handbook of Critical Theory, Oxford, Blackwell, 1996, pp. 369-398. Axel Honneth, Suffering from Indeterminacy, Assen, Van Gorcum, 2000. Axel Honneth, "Redistribution as Recognition: A Response to Nancy Fraser," in Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange, London, Verso, 2003.
    • (2003) Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange
    • Honneth, A.1
  • 18
    • 10844292466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The emancipatory process in which Habermas anchors the normative perspective of critical theory is not at all reflected as such an emancipatory process in the moral experiences of the subjects involved; for they experience an impairment of what we can call their moral experiences, that is, their 'moral point of view', not as a restriction of intuitively mastered rules of language, but as a violation of identity claims acquired in socialisation" (Honneth, "The Social Dynamics of Disrespect," p. 261). This claim is obviously contestable in so far as unwarranted restrictions upon the exchange of reasons can be experienced as violations of one's right to speak, one's right to defend and criticise claims. This is a morally unjustifiable exclusion from the public space of reason and justification. However, I am not interested in assessing the accuracy of Honneth's claim here, since the doubts I have about it are not my primary concern in this paper.
    • The Social Dynamics of Disrespect , pp. 261
    • Honneth1
  • 19
    • 0001778197 scopus 로고
    • The politics of recognition
    • ed. Amy Gutman, Princeton, Princeton University Press
    • Charles Taylor, "The Politics of Recognition," in Multiculturalism, ed. Amy Gutman, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1994, p. 25. Though Honneth may choose, rightly or wrongly, to disassociate his normative standpoint from the 'politics of recognition', he cannot deny that much of the initial appeal of his theory depends on the light it promises to shed on the very empirical phenomena from which he wishes to disconnect it.
    • (1994) Multiculturalism , pp. 25
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 23
    • 10044288778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition, p. 246. Fraser regards it as a moral variant of the epistemological 'myth of the given', Redistribution or Recognition, pp. 201-211.
    • Redistribution or Recognition , pp. 246
    • Honneth1
  • 24
    • 10044288778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition, p. 246. Fraser regards it as a moral variant of the epistemological 'myth of the given', Redistribution or Recognition, pp. 201-211.
    • Redistribution or Recognition , pp. 201-211
    • Fraser1
  • 27
    • 10844292263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Redistribution as recognition: A response to Nancy Fraser
    • It is this preoccupation with the contingent social struggles of the present that Honneth identifies as one of the two telling differences between his normative paradigm and that of Fraser's. See "Redistribution as Recognition: A Response to Nancy Fraser," in Redistribution or Recognition, pp. 114-134.
    • Redistribution or Recognition , pp. 114-134
    • Fraser1
  • 28
    • 33748942408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grounding recognition: A rejoinder to critical questions
    • For Honneth, "it is still a matter of the invariant dependence of humans on the experience of recognition, even though its forms and contours can become differentiated in the course of historical transformations" (Honneth, "Grounding Recognition: A Rejoinder to Critical Questions," in Inquiry, 45, 2002, p. 515).
    • (2002) Inquiry , vol.45 , pp. 515
    • Honneth1
  • 31
    • 10844272920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In my view, were Honneth to attempt to reforge those links, he would find that the critical claims of his theory of recognition would have to be weakened for those links to be strengthened.
  • 33
    • 0040366909 scopus 로고
    • trans. G. Frederick Hunter, Matthew S. Kramer, and John Torpey, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press
    • As Habermas and Horkheimer did before him, Honneth holds the chair in social philosophy at the University of Frankfurt. And as they were before him, Honneth is concerned with preserving social philosophy's identity and the universality of its statements. Thus, Honneth's concern about the state of social philosophy is hardly new. Already in 1931, Horkheimer described the state of social philosophy in a remarkably similar manner. Although Honneth does not refer to it (somewhat curiously), Horkheimer's essay, "Die Gegenwärtige Lage der Sozialphilosophie und die Aufgaben eines Instituts für Sozialforschung," begins just like Honneth's, singling out precisely the lack of firm disciplinary contours not only between branches of philosophy, but between all of the human sciences. For the English translation, see Between Philosophy and Social Science. Selected Early Writings, trans. G. Frederick Hunter, Matthew S. Kramer, and John Torpey, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1993, p. 1. Original in Max Horkheimer, Sozial-philosophische Studien. Aufsätze, Reden, und Vorträge 1930-1972, Herausgegeben von Werner Brede, Frankfurt, Fischer Verlag, 1972, p. 33.
    • (1993) Between Philosophy and Social Science. Selected Early Writings , pp. 1
  • 34
    • 10844232753 scopus 로고
    • Herausgegeben von Werner Brede, Frankfurt, Fischer Verlag
    • As Habermas and Horkheimer did before him, Honneth holds the chair in social philosophy at the University of Frankfurt. And as they were before him, Honneth is concerned with preserving social philosophy's identity and the universality of its statements. Thus, Honneth's concern about the state of social philosophy is hardly new. Already in 1931, Horkheimer described the state of social philosophy in a remarkably similar manner. Although Honneth does not refer to it (somewhat curiously), Horkheimer's essay, "Die Gegenwärtige Lage der Sozialphilosophie und die Aufgaben eines Instituts für Sozialforschung," begins just like Honneth's, singling out precisely the lack of firm disciplinary contours not only between branches of philosophy, but between all of the human sciences. For the English translation, see Between Philosophy and Social Science. Selected Early Writings, trans. G. Frederick Hunter, Matthew S. Kramer, and John Torpey, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1993, p. 1. Original in Max Horkheimer, Sozial-philosophische Studien. Aufsätze, Reden, und Vorträge 1930-1972, Herausgegeben von Werner Brede, Frankfurt, Fischer Verlag, 1972, p. 33.
    • (1972) Sozial-philosophische Studien. Aufsätze, Reden, und Vorträge 1930-1972 , pp. 33
    • Horkheimer, M.1
  • 35
    • 10844222346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The task of social philosophy: A reply to Axel Honneth
    • Cheryl Hughes and James Wong, Philosophy Documentation Center
    • For a more detailed discussion of Honneth's view of social philosophy see Nikolas Kompridis, "The Task of Social Philosophy: A Reply to Axel Honneth," eds. Cheryl Hughes and James Wong, Social Philosophy Today 17, Philosophy Documentation Center, 2002.
    • (2002) Social Philosophy Today , vol.17
    • Kompridis, N.1
  • 36
    • 10844258821 scopus 로고
    • Antike und moderne Ethik
    • Reclam, Stuttgart
    • In addition to the influence of object-relations theory, Honneth's approach also bears the influence of Ernst Tugendhat's paper, "Antike und moderne Ethik" in Tugendhat, Probleme der Ethik, Reclam, Stuttgart, 1984, pp. 33-56. In this paper, which has had a considerable influence on contemporary German philosophy, Tugendhat argues in favour of a "formal concept of psychological health."
    • (1984) Probleme der Ethik , pp. 33-56
    • Tugendhat1
  • 37
    • 10844239662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Honneth is not the first, nor the last, theorist who wants to have his cake and eat it too. Yet, I still find quite perplexing his interest in grounding social criticism in a formal theory of the good. Ostensibly, the theoretical attraction to ideas of the good is their motivating power. But in what can the motivating power of a formal theory of the good consist once it is stripped of any significant content? From Plato to MacIntyre and Taylor, it has been thought that the good has to appear in some appropriate form if it is to move us to act in this way or that. Honneth presents us with a conception of the good that must hide its face, a good that must sneak in its substantive content through the back door. Is all this subterfuge really necessary?
  • 38
    • 0003656652 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, See also pp. 495-522.
    • Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1989, pp. 62-75. See also pp. 495-522.
    • (1989) Sources of the Self , pp. 62-75
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 39
    • 0000727549 scopus 로고
    • Epistemological crises, dramatic narrative, and the philosophy of science
    • See Alasdair MacIntyre, "Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative, and the Philosophy of Science," The Monist 60, 1977, pp. 453-472, and Whose Justice? Whose Rationality? Notre Dame, Notre Dame University Press, 1988. And see Charles Taylor, "Explanation and Practical Reason," Philosophical Arguments, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1995, pp. 34-60, and Sources of the Self, pp. 3-110. Also, Nikolas Kompridis, "So We Need Something Else for Reason to Mean," International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. 8, no. 3, 2000, pp. 271-295.
    • (1977) The Monist , vol.60 , pp. 453-472
    • MacIntyre, A.1
  • 40
    • 0003392316 scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame, Notre Dame University Press
    • See Alasdair MacIntyre, "Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative, and the Philosophy of Science," The Monist 60, 1977, pp. 453-472, and Whose Justice? Whose Rationality? Notre Dame, Notre Dame University Press, 1988. And see Charles Taylor, "Explanation and Practical Reason," Philosophical Arguments, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1995, pp. 34-60, and Sources of the Self, pp. 3-110. Also, Nikolas Kompridis, "So We Need Something Else for Reason to Mean," International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. 8, no. 3, 2000, pp. 271-295.
    • (1988) Whose Justice? Whose Rationality?
  • 41
    • 0010083144 scopus 로고
    • Explanation and practical reason
    • Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press
    • See Alasdair MacIntyre, "Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative, and the Philosophy of Science," The Monist 60, 1977, pp. 453-472, and Whose Justice? Whose Rationality? Notre Dame, Notre Dame University Press, 1988. And see Charles Taylor, "Explanation and Practical Reason," Philosophical Arguments, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1995, pp. 34-60, and Sources of the Self, pp. 3-110. Also, Nikolas Kompridis, "So We Need Something Else for Reason to Mean," International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. 8, no. 3, 2000, pp. 271-295.
    • (1995) Philosophical Arguments , pp. 34-60
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 42
    • 84966931138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alasdair MacIntyre, "Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative, and the Philosophy of Science," The Monist 60, 1977, pp. 453-472, and Whose Justice? Whose Rationality? Notre Dame, Notre Dame University Press, 1988. And see Charles Taylor, "Explanation and Practical Reason," Philosophical Arguments, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1995, pp. 34-60, and Sources of the Self, pp. 3-110. Also, Nikolas Kompridis, "So We Need Something Else for Reason to Mean," International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. 8, no. 3, 2000, pp. 271-295.
    • Sources of the Self , pp. 3-110
  • 43
    • 10844233867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So we need something else for reason to mean
    • See Alasdair MacIntyre, "Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative, and the Philosophy of Science," The Monist 60, 1977, pp. 453-472, and Whose Justice? Whose Rationality? Notre Dame, Notre Dame University Press, 1988. And see Charles Taylor, "Explanation and Practical Reason," Philosophical Arguments, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1995, pp. 34-60, and Sources of the Self, pp. 3-110. Also, Nikolas Kompridis, "So We Need Something Else for Reason to Mean," International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. 8, no. 3, 2000, pp. 271-295.
    • (2000) International Journal of Philosophical Studies , vol.8 , Issue.3 , pp. 271-295
    • Kompridis, N.1
  • 47
    • 0003976110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, p. 5; also see, pp. 1-23. I have developed the normative implications of this idea in Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future, Evanston, Northwestern University Press, 2004.
    • The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity , pp. 5
    • Habermas1
  • 48
    • 10844273085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evanston, Northwestern University Press
    • Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, p. 5; also see, pp. 1-23. I have developed the normative implications of this idea in Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future, Evanston, Northwestern University Press, 2004.
    • (2004) Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory between Past and Future , pp. 1-23
  • 50
    • 0004251932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example: Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, Gadamer's Truth and Method, Heidegger's Being and Time, Dewey's The Quest for Certainty, Charles Taylor's critique of naturalist epistemology and ontology, and Habermas' critique of the philosophy of consciousness are at once an internal critique of philosophy and a critique of society and culture.
    • Philosophical Investigations
    • Wittgenstein1
  • 51
    • 0004225610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example: Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, Gadamer's Truth and Method, Heidegger's Being and Time, Dewey's The Quest for Certainty, Charles Taylor's critique of naturalist epistemology and ontology, and Habermas' critique of the philosophy of consciousness are at once an internal critique of philosophy and a critique of society and culture.
    • Truth and Method
    • Gadamer1
  • 52
    • 0003422445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example: Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, Gadamer's Truth and Method, Heidegger's Being and Time, Dewey's The Quest for Certainty, Charles Taylor's critique of naturalist epistemology and ontology, and Habermas' critique of the philosophy of consciousness are at once an internal critique of philosophy and a critique of society and culture.
    • Being and Time
    • Heidegger1
  • 53
    • 0004084516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example: Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, Gadamer's Truth and Method, Heidegger's Being and Time, Dewey's The Quest for Certainty, Charles Taylor's critique of naturalist epistemology and ontology, and Habermas' critique of the philosophy of consciousness are at once an internal critique of philosophy and a critique of society and culture.
    • The Quest for Certainty
    • Dewey1
  • 55
    • 10844264421 scopus 로고
    • Enzyklopädie der philosophischen wissenschaften
    • eds. E. Moldenhauer and K. Michelet, Frankfurt, Suhrkamp
    • Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften, volume 8, in G. Hegel, Werke, eds. E. Moldenhauer and K. Michelet, Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 1970, p. 84.
    • (1970) Werke , vol.8 , pp. 84
    • Hegel, G.1
  • 56
    • 0009091084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA, MIT Press
    • For this story see Tugendhat, Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1986; see also, Frederick Neuhouser, Fichte's Theory of Subjectivity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1990, pp. 117-166. According to Tugendhat, the key move away from Kant's view of autonomy was taken the moment Fichte jointly poses the following questions: "Who am I really?" and "Are the moral norms to which I'm evidently committed really mine?". As Tugendhat explains, "Kant does not yet mean by autonomy a self-determination of the person as a person or of the I as an I, but a self-determination of reason." Tugendhat, Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination, pp. 133-134. In Heidegger's Being and Time, the question of self-determination is treated initially as the question of the 'who' of everyday Dasein.
    • (1986) Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination
    • Tugendhat1
  • 57
    • 0004266106 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
    • For this story see Tugendhat, Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1986; see also, Frederick Neuhouser, Fichte's Theory of Subjectivity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1990, pp. 117-166. According to Tugendhat, the key move away from Kant's view of autonomy was taken the moment Fichte jointly poses the following questions: "Who am I really?" and "Are the moral norms to which I'm evidently committed really mine?". As Tugendhat explains, "Kant does not yet mean by autonomy a self-determination of the person as a person or of the I as an I, but a self-determination of reason." Tugendhat, Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination, pp. 133-134. In Heidegger's Being and Time, the question of self-determination is treated initially as the question of the 'who' of everyday Dasein.
    • (1990) Fichte's Theory of Subjectivity , pp. 117-166
    • Neuhouser, F.1
  • 58
    • 0009091084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this story see Tugendhat, Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1986; see also, Frederick Neuhouser, Fichte's Theory of Subjectivity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1990, pp. 117-166. According to Tugendhat, the key move away from Kant's view of autonomy was taken the moment Fichte jointly poses the following questions: "Who am I really?" and "Are the moral norms to which I'm evidently committed really mine?". As Tugendhat explains, "Kant does not yet mean by autonomy a self-determination of the person as a person or of the I as an I, but a self-determination of reason." Tugendhat, Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination, pp. 133-134. In Heidegger's Being and Time, the question of self-determination is treated initially as the question of the 'who' of everyday Dasein.
    • Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination , pp. 133-134
    • Tugendhat1
  • 59
    • 0003422445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this story see Tugendhat, Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1986; see also, Frederick Neuhouser, Fichte's Theory of Subjectivity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1990, pp. 117-166. According to Tugendhat, the key move away from Kant's view of autonomy was taken the moment Fichte jointly poses the following questions: "Who am I really?" and "Are the moral norms to which I'm evidently committed really mine?". As Tugendhat explains, "Kant does not yet mean by autonomy a self-determination of the person as a person or of the I as an I, but a self-determination of reason." Tugendhat, Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination, pp. 133-134. In Heidegger's Being and Time, the question of self-determination is treated initially as the question of the 'who' of everyday Dasein.
    • Being and Time
    • Heidegger1
  • 60
    • 0347378348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is the question for which Hegel's theory of recognition is the answer?"
    • For a detailed and compelling elaboration of this view, see Robert Pippin, "What is the Question for which Hegel's Theory of Recognition is the Answer?" European Journal of Philosophy, 8:2,2000, pp. 155-172.
    • (2000) European Journal of Philosophy , vol.8 , Issue.2 , pp. 155-172
    • Pippin, R.1
  • 61
    • 0037737586 scopus 로고
    • You can't get there from here: Transition problems in Hegel's phenomenology
    • ed. Frederick C. Beiser, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
    • Also illuminating is Pippin's "You Can't Get There from Here: Transition Problems in Hegel's Phenomenology," in The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, ed. Frederick C. Beiser, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993, pp. 52-85.
    • (1993) The Cambridge Companion to Hegel , pp. 52-85
    • Pippin1
  • 62
    • 10844252123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here, I'm deliberately following in the tracks of Honneth's Hegel interpretation in Suffering from Indeterminacy, in order to bring out what has been missed or neglected.
    • Suffering from Indeterminacy
    • Hegel, H.1
  • 64
    • 10844241385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To reinforce this point it is worth citing the whole Enzyklopädie formulation of freedom, particularly since it follows upon a formulation of the autonomy of thought (that is, of reason), the last part of which I also include: "In der Logik werden die Gedanken so gefaßt, daß sie keinen anderen Inhalt haben als einen dem Denken selbst angehörigen und durch dasselbe hervorgebrachten. So sind die Gedanken reine Gedanken. So ist der Geist rein bei sich selbst und hiermit frei, denn die Freiheit ist eben dies, in seinem Anderen bei sich selbst zu sein, von sich abzuhängen, das Bestimmende seiner selbst zu sein. In allen Trieben fange ich von einem Anderen an, von einem solchen, das für mich eine Äußerliches ist. Hier sprechen wir dann von Abhängigkeit. Freiheit is nur da, wo kein Anderes f̈r mich ist, das ich nicht selbst bin." Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften, volume 8, p. 84.
    • Enzyklopädie der Philosophischen Wissenschaften , vol.8 , pp. 84
    • Hegel1
  • 67
    • 10844252935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • According to Honneth, in modern societies practices of recognition have differentiated themselves into three spheres, the sphere of love, law, and achievement, within each of which the respective practices of recognition are ordered by a corresponding and distinct normative principle.
  • 70
    • 10844279792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • second emphasis my own
    • "What motivates individuals or social groups to call the prevailing social order into question and to engage in practical resistance is the moral conviction that, with respect to their own situations and particularities, the recognition principles considered legitimate are incorrectly or inadequately applied. It follows from this. . . that a moral experience that can be meaningfully described as one of 'disrespect' must be regarded as the motivational basis of all social conflicts' (Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition, p. 157, second emphasis my own).
    • Honneth, R.O.R.1
  • 77
    • 10044288778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "On the one hand, there can be an opening up of new personality-interests involving mutual recognition, leading to an increase in socially confirmed individuality; on the other hand, more personas can be integrated into already-existing conditions of recognition, leading to an expansion of the circle of mutually recognizing subjects" (Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition, p. 78). Compare Habermas: "Social individualization means, for the individuals, that the self-determination and self-realization that are expected of them presuppose a non-conventional sort of ego-identity. Even this identity formation can, however, only be conceived as socially constituted; it must therefore be stabilized in relationships of reciprocal recognition that are at least anticipated." Postmetaphysical Thinking, trans. William Mark Hohengarten, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1992, p. 184.
    • Redistribution or Recognition , pp. 78
    • Honneth1
  • 78
    • 0004130431 scopus 로고
    • trans. William Mark Hohengarten, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press
    • "On the one hand, there can be an opening up of new personality-interests involving mutual recognition, leading to an increase in socially confirmed individuality; on the other hand, more personas can be integrated into already-existing conditions of recognition, leading to an expansion of the circle of mutually recognizing subjects" (Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition, p. 78). Compare Habermas: "Social individualization means, for the individuals, that the self-determination and self-realization that are expected of them presuppose a non-conventional sort of ego-identity. Even this identity formation can, however, only be conceived as socially constituted; it must therefore be stabilized in relationships of reciprocal recognition that are at least anticipated." Postmetaphysical Thinking, trans. William Mark Hohengarten, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1992, p. 184.
    • (1992) Postmetaphysical Thinking , pp. 184
  • 80
    • 0010051913 scopus 로고
    • The new obscurity: The crisis of the welfare state and the exhaustion of utopian energies
    • trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen, Cambridge, MA, Cambridge University Press
    • See Habermas' "The New Obscurity: The Crisis of the Welfare State and the Exhaustion of Utopian Energies," in The New Conservatism, trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen, Cambridge, MA, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 50.
    • (1989) The New Conservatism , pp. 50
    • Habermas1
  • 82
    • 0003422445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson, New York, Harper and Row
    • Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson, New York, Harper and Row, 1962, p. 63. German original: Sein und Zeit, Tübingen, Max Niemeyer, 1986.
    • (1962) Being and Time , pp. 63
    • Heidegger, M.1
  • 83
    • 0003901725 scopus 로고
    • German original Tübingen, Max Niemeyer
    • Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson, New York, Harper and Row, 1962, p. 63. German original: Sein und Zeit, Tübingen, Max Niemeyer, 1986.
    • (1986) Sein und Zeit
  • 88
    • 38849157332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming
    • For a fully elaborated statement of this alternative, see, Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future, (forthcoming). For related statements see "The Normativity of the New," ed. Nikolas Kompridis, Philosophical Romanticism, London & New York, Routledge, 2005, and "The Transformation of Reason, Normative Change, and Social Criticism," International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. II, no. 2, 2005.
    • Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory between Past and Future
    • Kompridis, N.1
  • 89
    • 10844266101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The normativity of the new
    • London & New York, Routledge, 2005
    • For a fully elaborated statement of this alternative, see, Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future, (forthcoming). For related statements see "The Normativity of the New," ed. Nikolas Kompridis, Philosophical Romanticism, London & New York, Routledge, 2005, and "The Transformation of Reason, Normative Change, and Social Criticism," International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. II, no. 2, 2005.
    • Philosophical Romanticism
    • Kompridis, N.1
  • 90
    • 10844283499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The transformation of reason, normative change, and social criticism
    • 2005
    • For a fully elaborated statement of this alternative, see, Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future, (forthcoming). For related statements see "The Normativity of the New," ed. Nikolas Kompridis, Philosophical Romanticism, London & New York, Routledge, 2005, and "The Transformation of Reason, Normative Change, and Social Criticism," International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. II, no. 2, 2005.
    • International Journal of Philosophical Studies , vol.2 , Issue.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.