메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 72, Issue 4, 1999, Pages 839-855

Asking the right questions

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0347638436     PISSN: 08998086     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (13)

References (60)
  • 1
    • 8844233256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This paper has a secret co-author. Several weeks before I wrote it, I heard Robert Gordon complain that the debate over multidisciplinary law practice ("MDP") was completely ignoring the question of what effect MDP would have on the lawyer's role as a guardian of public norms. He expressed considerable bemusement about the neglect of this question in published discussions of MDP. That sounded right to me, and the present paper is my effort to raise in public the question that Gordon raised in conversation. Of course Gordon bears no responsibility for the way I have elaborated his question.
  • 2
    • 84866805675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ABA COMMISSION ON MULTIDISCIPINARY PRACTICE AND RELATED TRENDS AFFECTING THE PROFESSION ¶ 4 [hereinafter ABA REPORT]
    • It is already the case that two of the four biggest "law firms" in the world are accounting firms. ABA COMMISSION ON MULTIDISCIPINARY PRACTICE AND RELATED TRENDS AFFECTING THE PROFESSION ¶ 4 [hereinafter ABA REPORT].
  • 3
    • 0041811246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • King Arthur's March on Europe
    • June
    • John E. Morris, King Arthur's March on Europe, AM. LAW. 48, 53 (June 1998).
    • (1998) Am. Law. , pp. 48
    • Morris, J.E.1
  • 4
    • 0040917906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2, ¶ 2
    • ABA REPORT, supra note 2, ¶ 2.
    • Aba Report
  • 6
    • 8844230110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 93
    • Id. at 93.
  • 7
    • 0002049938 scopus 로고
    • A Sociologist Looks at the Legal Profession
    • This view was elaborated by the sociologist Talcott Parsons, but it may already be found in Tocqueville, and has been defended by such notable jurists as Louis Brandeis. See generally TALCOTT PARSONS, A Sociologist Looks at the Legal Profession, in ESSAYS IN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY 370 (1964); TALCOTT PARSONS, The Professions and Social Structure, in ESSAYS IN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY 34 (1964); 1 ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE, DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA 272-80 (Henry Reeve trans., Phillips Bradley ed., Anchor Books 1963) (1835);
    • (1964) Essays in Sociological Theory , pp. 370
    • Parsons, T.1
  • 8
    • 0002469581 scopus 로고
    • The Professions and Social Structure
    • This view was elaborated by the sociologist Talcott Parsons, but it may already be found in Tocqueville, and has been defended by such notable jurists as Louis Brandeis. See generally TALCOTT PARSONS, A Sociologist Looks at the Legal Profession, in ESSAYS IN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY 370 (1964); TALCOTT PARSONS, The Professions and Social Structure, in ESSAYS IN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY 34 (1964); 1 ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE, DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA 272-80 (Henry Reeve trans., Phillips Bradley ed., Anchor Books 1963) (1835);
    • (1964) Essays in Sociological Theory , pp. 34
    • Parsons, T.1
  • 9
    • 40449125443 scopus 로고
    • 1 (Henry Reeve trans., Phillips Bradley ed., Anchor Books 1963)
    • This view was elaborated by the sociologist Talcott Parsons, but it may already be found in Tocqueville, and has been defended by such notable jurists as Louis Brandeis. See generally TALCOTT PARSONS, A Sociologist Looks at the Legal Profession, in ESSAYS IN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY 370 (1964); TALCOTT PARSONS, The Professions and Social Structure, in ESSAYS IN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY 34 (1964); 1 ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE, DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA 272-80 (Henry Reeve trans., Phillips Bradley ed., Anchor Books 1963) (1835);
    • (1835) Democracy in America , pp. 272-280
    • De Tocqueville, A.1
  • 11
    • 1542715143 scopus 로고
    • The Noblesse Oblige Tradition in the Practice of Law
    • I discuss this tradition in David Luban, The Noblesse Oblige Tradition in the Practice of Law, 41 VAND. L. REV. 717 (1988).
    • (1988) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.41 , pp. 717
    • Luban, D.1
  • 13
    • 8844268911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See id. at Rule 33(a)(4) (requiring lawyer to disclose to tribunal material facts to avoid assisting in crime or fraud); id. at Rule 1.6 (forbidding lawyer from revealing certain information related to client representation).
  • 14
    • 8844238172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at Rule 1.2(d). See also id. at Rule 1.16(a)(1) (requiring lawyer to withdraw if representation will result in violation of law); id. at Rule 1.16(b)(1) (permitting lawyer to withdraw if client persists in course of action that lawyer believes to be criminal or fraudulent). My interpretation of the rule as an expression of the Parsons-Brandeis ideal may not be valid if we consider only criminal schemes, in which the requirement not to counsel or assist is nothing more than the demand not to be an accomplice or enter into a criminal conspiracy - hardly a requirement that applies only to lawyers! The interpretation is more plausible when we turn from criminal schemes to non-criminal frauds.
  • 15
    • 0001843624 scopus 로고
    • The Independence of Lawyers
    • The fundamental American treatment of this ideal is Robert W. Gordon, The Independence of Lawyers, 68 B.U. L. REV. 1 (1988).
    • (1988) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.68 , pp. 1
    • Gordon, R.W.1
  • 16
    • 8844252144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8, at Rules 1.8(f), 5.4
    • The relevant Model Rules are 1.8(f) and 5.4, both of which forbid lawyers from allowing third parties paying their fees to interfere with their judgment on behalf of clients. ABA MODEL RULES, supra note 8, at Rules 1.8(f), 5.4.
    • Aba Model Rules
  • 18
    • 8844253761 scopus 로고
    • The Sources of Legal Ethics: A German-American Comparison of Lawyers' Professional Duties
    • Interestingly, this meaning is explicitly acknowledged and centrally important in Germany. The Federal Lawyers' Act (Bundesrechtsanwaltsordnung) and the code of legal ethics (the so-called "Richtlinien" or Grundsätze des anwaltlichen Standesrechts) both begin with the fundamental principle, "a lawyer is an independent organ of the administration of justice" (Rechtspflege). BRAO § 1; RICTHLRA, Vorspruch § 1. The leading commentaries all agree that this means independence from the client as well as the state. For discussion and references, see David Luban, The Sources of Legal Ethics: A German-American Comparison of Lawyers' Professional Duties, 48 RABELS ZEITSCHRIFT FÜR AUSLÄNDISCHES UND INTERNATIONALES PRIVATRECHT 245, 266-67 (1984).
    • (1984) Rabels Zeitschrift für Ausländisches und Internationales Privatrecht , vol.48 , pp. 245
    • Luban, D.1
  • 19
    • 8844252144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8, at Rule 1.2(b)
    • See ABA MODEL RULES, supra note 8, at Rule 1.2(b) (stating that client representation does not amount to endorsement of client's views).
    • Aba Model Rules
  • 20
    • 8844242304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at Rule 3.4(e) (prohibiting attorneys from stating their own views during trial).
  • 21
    • 8844246213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "In representing a client, a lawyer shall exercise independent professional judgment and render candid advice. In rendering advice, a lawyer may refer not only to law but to other considerations such as moral, economic, social and political factors, that may be relevant to the client's situation." Id. at Rule 2.1.
  • 22
    • 8844271509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at Rule 1.6 cmt 3
    • Id. at Rule 1.6 cmt 3.
  • 25
    • 85040877221 scopus 로고
    • The distinction between citizen and consumer has been explored by Mark Sagoff in a series of elegant articles in the 1980s. Many of these were eventually incorporated into his book, The Economy of the Earth. See generally MARK SAGOFF, THE ECONOMY OF THE EARTH: PHILOSOPHY, LAW, AND THE ENVIRONMENT (1988).
    • (1988) The Economy of the Earth: Philosophy, Law, and the Environment
    • Sagoff, M.1
  • 26
    • 0004327677 scopus 로고
    • Allan Bloom trans., Basic Books ed.
    • JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, EMILE, OR ON EDUCATION 40 (Allan Bloom trans., Basic Books ed. 1979). Rousseau wrote: The Lacedaemonian Pedaretus runs for the council of three hundred. He is defeated. He goes home delighted that there were three hundred men worthier than he to be found in Sparta. I take this display to be sincere, and there is reason to believe that it was. This is the citizen. A Spartan woman had five sons in the army and was awaiting news of the battle. A Helot arrives; trembling, she asks him for news. "Your five sons were killed." "Base slave, did I ask you that?" "We won the victory." The mother runs to the temple and gives thanks to the gods. This is the female citizen. Id. (footnotes omitted).
    • (1979) Emile, or on Education , pp. 40
    • Rousseau, J.-J.1
  • 27
    • 8844265081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gordon, supra note 11, at 13
    • Gordon, supra note 11, at 13.
  • 28
    • 0005564457 scopus 로고
    • Kenneth I. Winston ed.
    • There is a sixth rejoinder as well, perhaps the least familiar but in some ways the most interesting. That is the point, developed in numerous essays and books by Lon Fuller, that the sharp distinction between citizen and consumer - state and civil society, in the terminology of nineteenth-century political economy - is excessively statist and, in the final analysis, misunderstands the pluralist nature of law. In Fuller's eyes, law arises whenever human beings subject their own conduct to the governance of rules, whether or not these rules are made by the state; thus, the law in a contract is just as much "contract law" as the law governing its formation. I believe that it is possible to recast the distinction between public norms and private interests even in a legal pluralist framework such as Fuller's, but that is an excursion for another paper. See generally LON L. FULLER, THE PRINCIPLES OF SOCIAL ORDER (Kenneth I. Winston ed., 1981).
    • (1981) The Principles of Social Order
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 29
    • 0003774434 scopus 로고
    • § 19.3 4th ed.
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW § 19.3 (4th ed. 1992). As Jonathan R. Macey puts it, "[i]nterest group theory treats statutes as commodities that are purchased by particular interest groups or coalitions of interest groups that outbid and outmaneuver competing interest groups." Jonathan R. Macey, Promoting Public-Regarding Legislation Through Statutory Interpretation: An Interest Group Model, 86 COLUM. L. REV. 223, 227 (1986). See generally DANIEL A. FARBER & PHILIP P. FRICKEY, LAW AND PUBLIC CHOICE: A CRITICAL INTRODUCTION (1991).
    • (1992) Economic Analysis of Law
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 30
    • 84935413096 scopus 로고
    • Promoting Public-Regarding Legislation Through Statutory Interpretation: An Interest Group Model
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW § 19.3 (4th ed. 1992). As Jonathan R. Macey puts it, "[i]nterest group theory treats statutes as commodities that are purchased by particular interest groups or coalitions of interest groups that outbid and outmaneuver competing interest groups." Jonathan R. Macey, Promoting Public-Regarding Legislation Through Statutory Interpretation: An Interest Group Model, 86 COLUM. L. REV. 223, 227 (1986). See generally DANIEL A. FARBER & PHILIP P. FRICKEY, LAW AND PUBLIC CHOICE: A CRITICAL INTRODUCTION (1991).
    • (1986) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.86 , pp. 223
    • Macey, J.R.1
  • 31
    • 0011674694 scopus 로고
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW § 19.3 (4th ed. 1992). As Jonathan R. Macey puts it, "[i]nterest group theory treats statutes as commodities that are purchased by particular interest groups or coalitions of interest groups that outbid and outmaneuver competing interest groups." Jonathan R. Macey, Promoting Public-Regarding Legislation Through Statutory Interpretation: An Interest Group Model, 86 COLUM. L. REV. 223, 227 (1986). See generally DANIEL A. FARBER & PHILIP P. FRICKEY, LAW AND PUBLIC CHOICE: A CRITICAL INTRODUCTION (1991).
    • (1991) Law and Public Choice: A Critical Introduction
    • Farber, D.A.1    Frickey, P.P.2
  • 33
    • 8844247688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gordon, supra note 11, at 26-27
    • Gordon, supra note 11, at 26-27.
  • 34
    • 0004052835 scopus 로고
    • See generally WILLIAM H. RIKER, LIBERALISM AGAINST POPULISM: A CONFRONTATION BETWEEN THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY AND THE THEORY OF SOCIAL CHOICE (1982) (examining theory of democratic process and social decision making); KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES (2d ed. 1963) (deriving a paradox of social choice); Richard D. McKelvey, General Conditions for Global Intransitivities in Formal Voting Models, 47 ECONOMETRICA 1085 (1979) (same); Norman Schofield, Instability of Simple Dynamic Games, 45 REV. ECON. STUD. 575 (1978) (same).
    • (1982) Liberalism Against Populism: A Confrontation Between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory of Social Choice
    • Riker, W.H.1
  • 35
    • 0003917730 scopus 로고
    • See generally WILLIAM H. RIKER, LIBERALISM AGAINST POPULISM: A CONFRONTATION BETWEEN THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY AND THE THEORY OF SOCIAL CHOICE (1982) (examining theory of democratic process and social decision making); KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES (2d ed. 1963) (deriving a paradox of social choice); Richard D. McKelvey, General Conditions for Global Intransitivities in Formal Voting Models, 47 ECONOMETRICA 1085 (1979) (same); Norman Schofield, Instability of Simple Dynamic Games, 45 REV. ECON. STUD. 575 (1978) (same).
    • (1963) Social Choice and Individual Values 2d Ed.
    • Arrow, K.J.1
  • 36
    • 34547851929 scopus 로고
    • General Conditions for Global Intransitivities in Formal Voting Models
    • See generally WILLIAM H. RIKER, LIBERALISM AGAINST POPULISM: A CONFRONTATION BETWEEN THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY AND THE THEORY OF SOCIAL CHOICE (1982) (examining theory of democratic process and social decision making); KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES (2d ed. 1963) (deriving a paradox of social choice); Richard D. McKelvey, General Conditions for Global Intransitivities in Formal Voting Models, 47 ECONOMETRICA 1085 (1979) (same); Norman Schofield, Instability of Simple Dynamic Games, 45 REV. ECON. STUD. 575 (1978) (same).
    • (1979) Econometrica , vol.47 , pp. 1085
    • McKelvey, R.D.1
  • 37
    • 84959813514 scopus 로고
    • Instability of Simple Dynamic Games
    • See generally WILLIAM H. RIKER, LIBERALISM AGAINST POPULISM: A CONFRONTATION BETWEEN THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY AND THE THEORY OF SOCIAL CHOICE (1982) (examining theory of democratic process and social decision making); KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES (2d ed. 1963) (deriving a paradox of social choice); Richard D. McKelvey, General Conditions for Global Intransitivities in Formal Voting Models, 47 ECONOMETRICA 1085 (1979) (same); Norman Schofield, Instability of Simple Dynamic Games, 45 REV. ECON. STUD. 575 (1978) (same).
    • (1978) Rev. Econ. Stud. , vol.45 , pp. 575
    • Schofield, N.1
  • 38
    • 0346675663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social Choice Theory as Jurisprudence
    • See David Luban, Social Choice Theory as Jurisprudence, 69 S. CAL. L REV. 521, 522 (1996) (discussing Arrow, McKelvey, and Schofield theorems); see also id. at 567-71 (discussing McKelvey and Schofield theorems); id. at 574 (discussing Arrow's assumption of pairwise voting); id. at 522, 556-58, 580-86 (discussing Arrow's assumption that voters may cast ballots for choices that other voters have excluded by right and demonstrating that without this assumption Arrow's theorem fails).
    • (1996) S. Cal. L Rev. , vol.69 , pp. 521
    • Luban, D.1
  • 39
    • 0347594515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Should a Christian Lawyer Sign Up for Simon's Practice of Justice?
    • Thomas L. Shatter, Should a Christian Lawyer Sign Up for Simon's Practice of Justice?, 51 STAN. L. REV. 903, 911-13 (1999).
    • (1999) STan. L. Rev. , vol.51 , pp. 903
    • Shatter, T.L.1
  • 40
    • 8844288104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 912
    • Id. at 912.
  • 41
    • 8844278179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 912-13
    • 3Z Id. at 912-13.
  • 42
    • 0346963462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Zealous Advocacy of Justice in a Less than Ideal Legal World
    • Robin West, The Zealous Advocacy of Justice in a Less than Ideal Legal World, 51 STAN. L. REV. 973, 984 (1999) (emphasis in original).
    • (1999) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.51 , pp. 973
    • West, R.1
  • 43
    • 72849145627 scopus 로고
    • The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral Foundations of the Lawyer-Client Relation
    • Charles Fried, The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral Foundations of the Lawyer-Client Relation, 85 YALE L.J. 1060, 1080 (1976) (footnotes omitted).
    • (1976) Yale L.J. , vol.85 , pp. 1060
    • Fried, C.1
  • 44
    • 72849145627 scopus 로고
    • The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral Foundations of the Lawyer-Client Relation
    • emphasis added
    • Id. (emphasis added).
    • (1976) Yale L.J. , vol.85 , pp. 1060
    • Fried, C.1
  • 45
    • 0003983534 scopus 로고
    • ch. 3
    • See DAVID LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE: AN ETHICAL STUDY ch. 3 (1988) (elaborating on the circumstances in which we do or do not have an obligation to acknowledge the law's moral authority); see generally David Luban, Conscientious Lawyers for Conscientious Lawbreakers, 52 U. PITT. L. REV. 793 (1991).
    • (1988) Lawyers and Justice: An Ethical Study
    • Luban, D.1
  • 46
    • 0347568586 scopus 로고
    • Conscientious Lawyers for Conscientious Lawbreakers
    • See DAVID LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE: AN ETHICAL STUDY ch. 3 (1988) (elaborating on the circumstances in which we do or do not have an obligation to acknowledge the law's moral authority); see generally David Luban, Conscientious Lawyers for Conscientious Lawbreakers, 52 U. PITT. L. REV. 793 (1991).
    • (1991) U. Pitt. L. Rev. , vol.52 , pp. 793
    • Luban, D.1
  • 47
    • 0033414396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Faculty Pro Bono and the Question of Identity
    • See David Luban, Faculty Pro Bono and the Question of Identity, 49 J. LEGAL EDUC. 58, 63-66 (1999) (defending this view).
    • (1999) J. Legal Educ. , vol.49 , pp. 58
    • Luban, D.1
  • 49
    • 8844255977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Twenty Theses on Adversarial Ethics
    • Helen Stacy & Michael Lavarch eds.
    • See David Luban, Twenty Theses on Adversarial Ethics, in BEYOND THE ADVERSARIAL SYSTEM 134 (Helen Stacy & Michael Lavarch eds., 1999); LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 36, at chs. 4-5 (considering ethical obligations of attorneys within adversarial system); see also David Luban, The Adversary System Excuse, in THE GOOD LAWYER: LAWYERS' ROLES AND LAWYERS' ETHICS 83-123 (David Luban ed., 1983) (discussing the conflict inherent in lawyer's ethical obligations in the adversarial system).
    • (1999) Beyond the Adversarial System , pp. 134
    • Luban, D.1
  • 50
    • 0002102054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 36, at chs. 4-5
    • See David Luban, Twenty Theses on Adversarial Ethics, in BEYOND THE ADVERSARIAL SYSTEM 134 (Helen Stacy & Michael Lavarch eds., 1999); LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 36, at chs. 4-5 (considering ethical obligations of attorneys within adversarial system); see also David Luban, The Adversary System Excuse, in THE GOOD LAWYER: LAWYERS' ROLES AND LAWYERS' ETHICS 83-123 (David Luban ed., 1983) (discussing the conflict inherent in lawyer's ethical obligations in the adversarial system).
    • Lawyers and Justice
    • Luban1
  • 51
    • 0042144025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Adversary System Excuse
    • David Luban ed.
    • See David Luban, Twenty Theses on Adversarial Ethics, in BEYOND THE ADVERSARIAL SYSTEM 134 (Helen Stacy & Michael Lavarch eds., 1999); LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 36, at chs. 4-5 (considering ethical obligations of attorneys within adversarial system); see also David Luban, The Adversary System Excuse, in THE GOOD LAWYER: LAWYERS' ROLES AND LAWYERS' ETHICS 83-123 (David Luban ed., 1983) (discussing the conflict inherent in lawyer's ethical obligations in the adversarial system).
    • (1983) The Good Lawyer: Lawyers' Roles and Lawyers' Ethics , pp. 83-123
    • Luban, D.1
  • 52
    • 8844252142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 39
    • I should add that in my view the claim of moral non-accountability is often unjustified. See generally Luban, Twenty Theses on Adversarial Ethics, supra note 39; Luban, The Adversary System Excuse, supra note 39 (discussing lawyers' ethical obligations in adversary context); LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 36, at chs. 6-8 (discussing lawyers' role and moral obligations).
    • Twenty Theses on Adversarial Ethics
    • Luban1
  • 53
    • 0042144025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 39
    • I should add that in my view the claim of moral non-accountability is often unjustified. See generally Luban, Twenty Theses on Adversarial Ethics, supra note 39; Luban, The Adversary System Excuse, supra note 39 (discussing lawyers' ethical obligations in adversary context); LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 36, at chs. 6-8 (discussing lawyers' role and moral obligations).
    • The Adversary System Excuse
    • Luban1
  • 54
    • 0002102054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 36, at chs. 6-8
    • I should add that in my view the claim of moral non-accountability is often unjustified. See generally Luban, Twenty Theses on Adversarial Ethics, supra note 39; Luban, The Adversary System Excuse, supra note 39 (discussing lawyers' ethical obligations in adversary context); LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 36, at chs. 6-8 (discussing lawyers' role and moral obligations).
    • Lawyers and Justice
    • Luban1
  • 56
    • 84866794691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RICHTLRA § 40
    • RICHTLRA § 40.
  • 57
    • 8844221051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In German criminal trials, the defendant does not testify under oath, to avoid creating a perjury trap for him. Here, too, German rules seem much more realistic in their sense of how much self-immolation it is reasonable to expect of ordinary human beings.
  • 58
    • 0009251505 scopus 로고
    • Policing the Professional Monopoly: A Constitutional and Empirical Analysis of Unauthorized Practice Prohibitions
    • Too often, this is true at the low end of legal services as well. State bars usually invoke the prohibition to drive cut-rate competitors out of business. A typical case is Florida Bar v. Brumbaugh, where a proprietor of a typing service was found guilty of unauthorized practice, after she instructed customers about how to fill out do-it-yourself legal forms. 355 So. 2d 1186 (Fla. 1978). See Deborah L. Rhode, Policing the Professional Monopoly: A Constitutional and Empirical Analysis of Unauthorized Practice Prohibitions, 34 STAN. L. REV. 1, 44-97 (1981) (discussing constitutional implications of unauthorized practice prohibitions).
    • (1981) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.34 , pp. 1
    • Rhode, D.L.1
  • 59
    • 0000638364 scopus 로고
    • The Inside Counsel Movement, Professional Judgment and Organizational Representation
    • Robert E. Rosen, The Inside Counsel Movement, Professional Judgment and Organizational Representation, 64 IND. L.J. 479, 519-36 (1989) (discussing claims of Inside Counsel Movement).
    • (1989) Ind. L.J. , vol.64 , pp. 479
    • Rosen, R.E.1
  • 60
    • 8844244536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 553 (arguing that whatever virtue inside counsel possess lies in their political power, not their independence).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.