메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 111, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 399-432

Veil of Ignorance Rules in Constitutional Law

(1)  Vermeule, Adrian a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0347617358     PISSN: 00440094     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/797593     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (64)

References (114)
  • 1
    • 84923726917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For a simple example, consider a rule that requires an official with regulatory authority over the stock market to place her assets in a "blind trust." Even if the official is self-interested, she will be uncertain whether any given decision will increase or decrease the value of her portfolio. She will thus be unable to skew her decisions in order to promote her personal interests. Other homely examples are blind grading and the practice by which orchestras place auditioners behind a screen.
  • 3
    • 84923726916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • An intermediate case occurs when a decisionmaker faces a decision that will principally affect not the decisionmaker herself, but her (genetic) descendants. If the time horizon over which the decision will matter is long enough, the attributes of descendants may be so difficult to predict that the decisionmaker will effectively be left ignorant of the identity of the persons whose interests she would favor, if she could. In this vein, participants at the Constitutional Convention argued that the Framers should impartially assess the interests of social classes, and of large and small states, because posterity would distribute their descendants throughout the strata and regions of society. See infra notes 55-56 and accompanying text.
  • 4
    • 0003900458 scopus 로고
    • See GEOFFREY BRENNAN & JAMES M. BUCHANAN, THE REASON OF RULES 28-31 (1985); JAMES M. BUCHANAN & GORDON TULLOCK, THE CALCULUS OF CONSENT 77-80 (1962); DENNIS MUELLER, CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRACY 61-64 (1996).
    • (1985) The Reason of Rules , pp. 28-31
    • Brennan, G.1    Buchanan, J.M.2
  • 5
    • 0004289065 scopus 로고
    • See GEOFFREY BRENNAN & JAMES M. BUCHANAN, THE REASON OF RULES 28-31 (1985); JAMES M. BUCHANAN & GORDON TULLOCK, THE CALCULUS OF CONSENT 77-80 (1962); DENNIS MUELLER, CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRACY 61-64 (1996).
    • (1962) The Calculus of Consent , pp. 77-80
    • Buchanan, J.M.1    Tullock, G.2
  • 6
    • 0003491566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See GEOFFREY BRENNAN & JAMES M. BUCHANAN, THE REASON OF RULES 28-31 (1985); JAMES M. BUCHANAN & GORDON TULLOCK, THE CALCULUS OF CONSENT 77-80 (1962); DENNIS MUELLER, CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRACY 61-64 (1996).
    • (1996) Constitutional Democracy , pp. 61-64
    • Mueller, D.1
  • 7
    • 84923726915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • U.S. CONST. art. I, § 9, cl. 3 ("No Bill of Attainder or ex post facto Law shall be passed [by Congress]."); id. art. I, § 10, cl. 1 ("No State shall . . . pass any Bill of Attainder [or] ex post facto Law . . . .").
  • 8
    • 84923726914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. art. I, § 6, cl. 2 ("No Senator or Representative shall, during the Time for which he was elected, be appointed to any civil Office under the Authority of the United States, which shall have been created, or the Emoluments whereof shall have been encreased during such time . . . .").
  • 9
    • 84923726913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. amend. XXVII ("No Law, varying the compensation for the services of the Senators and Representatives, shall take effect, until an election of Representatives shall have intervened.").
  • 10
    • 84923726912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. art. V (specifying procedures for constitutional amendment).
  • 11
    • 84923726911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. art. I, § 3, cl. 1 (stating that federal senators shall be chosen by the state legislatures), amended by id. amend. XVII (replacing legislative selection with direct election).
  • 12
    • 84923726910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. art. II, § 1, cls. 3, 5 (providing rules for presidential election and succession); id. amend. XII (providing rules for presidential election); id. amends. XX, XXV (providing rules for presidential succession).
  • 13
    • 0346918139 scopus 로고
    • Can Ignorance Be Bliss? Imperfect Information as a Positive Influence in Political Institutions
    • The most sustained discussion in the law review literature is an excellent short treatment of the veil of ignorance in Michael A. Fitts, Can Ignorance Be Bliss? Imperfect Information as a Positive Influence in Political Institutions, 88 MICH. L. REV. 917, 966-77 (1990). Fitts's emphasis, however, is on the veil effects arising from competition between political parties in a system of separated powers, rather than the sort of textual and doctrinal analysis I offer here. Another related idea is Cass Sunstein's argument that impartiality should be understood to ban decisions that embody "naked preferences." CASS R. SUNSTEIN, THE PARTIAL CONSTITUTION 17-39 (1993). Constitutional rules that instantiate such a ban, however, are not (or, not necessarily) veil rules that regulate decisionmakers' information. They are more often direct restrictions on constitutionally disfavored outcomes.
    • (1990) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.88 , pp. 917
    • Fitts, M.A.1
  • 14
    • 0003974417 scopus 로고
    • The most sustained discussion in the law review literature is an excellent short treatment of the veil of ignorance in Michael A. Fitts, Can Ignorance Be Bliss? Imperfect Information as a Positive Influence in Political Institutions, 88 MICH. L. REV. 917, 966-77 (1990). Fitts's emphasis, however, is on the veil effects arising from competition between political parties in a system of separated powers, rather than the sort of textual and doctrinal analysis I offer here. Another related idea is Cass Sunstein's argument that impartiality should be understood to ban decisions that embody "naked preferences." CASS R. SUNSTEIN, THE PARTIAL CONSTITUTION 17-39 (1993). Constitutional rules that instantiate such a ban, however, are not (or, not necessarily) veil rules that regulate decisionmakers' information. They are more often direct restrictions on constitutionally disfavored outcomes.
    • (1993) The Partial Constitution , pp. 17-39
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 15
    • 84937258250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Efficiency and Conspiracy: Conflicts of Interest, Anti-Nepotism Rules, and Separation Strategies
    • See Saul Levmore, Efficiency and Conspiracy: Conflicts of Interest, Anti-Nepotism Rules, and Separation Strategies, 66 FORDHAM L. REV. 2099 (1998) (analyzing the tradeoff between information and neutrality in conflict-of-interest law); see also Fitts, supra note 11, at 970 (noting that the veil of ignorance is "overinclusive" if "too much information is eliminated"); Elizabeth Garrett, Rethinking the Structures of Decisionmaking in the Federal Budget Process, 35 HARV. J. ON LEGIS. 387, 409-15 (1998) (analyzing the information-bias tradeoff in the context of the federal budget process).
    • (1998) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.66 , pp. 2099
    • Levmore, S.1
  • 16
    • 84923726909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 11
    • See Saul Levmore, Efficiency and Conspiracy: Conflicts of Interest, Anti-Nepotism Rules, and Separation Strategies, 66 FORDHAM L. REV. 2099 (1998) (analyzing the tradeoff between information and neutrality in conflict-of-interest law); see also Fitts, supra note 11, at 970 (noting that the veil of ignorance is "overinclusive" if "too much information is eliminated"); Elizabeth Garrett, Rethinking the Structures of Decisionmaking in the Federal Budget Process, 35 HARV. J. ON LEGIS. 387, 409-15 (1998) (analyzing the information-bias tradeoff in the context of the federal budget process).
    • Fitts1
  • 17
    • 0042234784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking the Structures of Decisionmaking in the Federal Budget Process
    • See Saul Levmore, Efficiency and Conspiracy: Conflicts of Interest, Anti-Nepotism Rules, and Separation Strategies, 66 FORDHAM L. REV. 2099 (1998) (analyzing the tradeoff between information and neutrality in conflict-of-interest law); see also Fitts, supra note 11, at 970 (noting that the veil of ignorance is "overinclusive" if "too much information is eliminated"); Elizabeth Garrett, Rethinking the Structures of Decisionmaking in the Federal Budget Process, 35 HARV. J. ON LEGIS. 387, 409-15 (1998) (analyzing the information-bias tradeoff in the context of the federal budget process).
    • (1998) Harv. J. on Legis. , vol.35 , pp. 387
    • Garrett, E.1
  • 18
    • 84923726908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I shall subsume within the category of self-interest a partial preference for decisionmakers' relatives, descendants, political allies, and so forth. The justification for this treatment derives from the modesty of constitutional law's ambitions and the crudity of its instruments. Although there may be conceptual reasons for treating these categories differently, constitutional rules are not usually fine-grained enough to take such differences into account.
  • 19
    • 0001156293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Explaining Bargaining Impasse: The Role of Self-Serving Biases
    • Winter
    • See Linda Babcock & George Loewenstein, Explaining Bargaining Impasse: The Role of Self-Serving Biases, J. ECON. PERSP., Winter 1997, at 109, 111 (observing that self-serving bias causes decisionmakers to "arrive at judgments of what is fair or right that are biased in the direction of their own self-interests").
    • (1997) J. Econ. Persp. , pp. 109
    • Babcock, L.1    Loewenstein, G.2
  • 20
    • 0345786103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chevron, State Farm, and EPA in the Court of Appeals during the 1990s
    • See Christopher H. Schroeder & Robert L. Glicksman, Chevron, State Farm, and EPA in the Court of Appeals During the 1990s, [2001] 31 Envtl. L. Rep. (Envtl. L. Inst.) 10,371 (explaining "motivated reasoning").
    • (2001) Envtl. L. Rep. (Envtl. L. Inst.) , vol.31 , pp. 10371
    • Schroeder, C.H.1    Glicksman, R.L.2
  • 21
    • 0003214842 scopus 로고
    • Morality and the Theory of Rational Behaviour
    • Amartya Sen & Bernard Williams eds.
    • John Harsanyi, for example, advocates a utilitarian account of choice in the original position and uses an "equiprobability postulate" that maximizes the mean utility level of all individuals in society. John C. Harsanyi, Morality and the Theory of Rational Behaviour, in UTILITARIANISM AND BEYOND 39, 44-46 (Amartya Sen & Bernard Williams eds., 1982).
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and Beyond , pp. 39
    • Harsanyi, J.C.1
  • 22
    • 0042094014 scopus 로고
    • Rawls uses the maximin criterion to derive his "difference principle," which says that allocative inequalities are permissible only to the extent they maximize the position of the least-well-off. RAWLS, supra note 2, at 132-35
    • The maximin criterion instructs decisionmakers to choose, from among possible actions, the one whose worst possible consequences are better than the worst possible consequences of the alternative actions. See R. DUNCAN LUCE & HOWARD RAIFFA, GAMES AND DECISIONS 278 (1957). Rawls uses the maximin criterion to derive his "difference principle," which says that allocative inequalities are permissible only to the extent they maximize the position of the least-well-off. RAWLS, supra note 2, at 132-35.
    • (1957) Games and Decisions , pp. 278
    • Duncan Luce, R.1    Raiffa, H.2
  • 24
    • 0007025819 scopus 로고
    • See MORTON WHITE, PHILOSOPHY, THE FEDERALIST, AND THE CONSTITUTION 102-28 (1987). In the present analysis, I will ignore the role of passion. Attempts by constitutional designers to prevent in-system decisionmakers from falling prey to their temporary passions is the subject of the theory of constitutional precommitments, a subject that has been thoroughly studied of late. See, e.g., JON ELSTER, ULYSSES UNBOUND 88-167 (2000); Jeremy Waldron, Precommitment and Disagreement, in CONSTITUTIONALISM: PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS 271 (Larry Alexander ed., 1998).
    • (1987) Philosophy, the Federalist, and the Constitution , pp. 102-128
    • White, M.1
  • 25
    • 0004015171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MORTON WHITE, PHILOSOPHY, THE FEDERALIST, AND THE CONSTITUTION 102-28 (1987). In the present analysis, I will ignore the role of passion. Attempts by constitutional designers to prevent in-system decisionmakers from falling prey to their temporary passions is the subject of the theory of constitutional precommitments, a subject that has been thoroughly studied of late. See, e.g., JON ELSTER, ULYSSES UNBOUND 88-167 (2000); Jeremy Waldron, Precommitment and Disagreement, in CONSTITUTIONALISM: PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS 271 (Larry Alexander ed., 1998).
    • (2000) Ulysses Unbound , pp. 88-167
    • Elster, J.1
  • 26
    • 0346417213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Precommitment and Disagreement
    • Larry Alexander ed.
    • See MORTON WHITE, PHILOSOPHY, THE FEDERALIST, AND THE CONSTITUTION 102-28 (1987). In the present analysis, I will ignore the role of passion. Attempts by constitutional designers to prevent in-system decisionmakers from falling prey to their temporary passions is the subject of the theory of constitutional precommitments, a subject that has been thoroughly studied of late. See, e.g., JON ELSTER, ULYSSES UNBOUND 88-167 (2000); Jeremy Waldron, Precommitment and Disagreement, in CONSTITUTIONALISM: PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS 271 (Larry Alexander ed., 1998).
    • (1998) Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations , pp. 271
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 27
    • 0345786099 scopus 로고
    • (James Madison) (Isaac Kramnick ed.)
    • THE FEDERALIST NO. 10, at 123 (James Madison) (Isaac Kramnick ed., 1987).
    • (1987) The Federalist No. 10 , vol.10 , pp. 123
  • 28
    • 0042824893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20 James Madison
    • THE FEDERALIST NO. 51, supra note 20, at 320 (James Madison).
    • The Federalist No. 51 , vol.51 , pp. 320
  • 29
    • 0039720757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20, (James Madison)
    • THE FEDERALIST No. 48, supra note 20, at 309 (James Madison).
    • The Federalist No. 48 , vol.48 , pp. 309
  • 30
    • 84923726907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Tumey v. Ohio, 273 U.S. 510 (1927) (holding that due process is violated when the adjudicator has a financial stake in the outcome).
  • 31
    • 84923726906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • U.S. CONST. art. I, § 6, cl. 2 ("[N]o Person holding any Office under the United States, shall be a Member of either House during his Continuance in Office.").
  • 32
    • 84923726905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The corollary problem of legislators who give up their seats to assume offices they have themselves created, or whose perquisites they have enhanced, is the subject of the Emoluments Clause. See infra notes 70-75 and accompanying text.
  • 33
    • 84923726904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ELSTER, supra note 19, at 140-41
    • See ELSTER, supra note 19, at 140-41.
  • 34
    • 0005807114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We might also speak of recusal as a remedy for conflict of interest. See ANDREW STARK, CONFLICT OF INTEREST IN AMERICAN PUBLIC LIFE 10 (2000). Indeed, the same is true of veil rules. Consider the blind trust remedy in nonconstitutional conflict-of-interest law, which denies the decisionmaker information about how his decisions will affect his financial interests. I assume that very little turns on whether we use the remedial label for the rules discussed in this Section.
    • (2000) Conflict of Interest in American Public Life , pp. 10
    • Stark, A.1
  • 35
    • 0347047504 scopus 로고
    • See U.S. CONST. art. I, § 3, cl. 6; § (Carolina Acad. Press)
    • See U.S. CONST. art. I, § 3, cl. 6; JOSEPH STORY, COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES § 389, at 276 (Carolina Acad. Press 1987) (1833).
    • (1833) Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States , vol.389 , pp. 276
    • Story, J.1
  • 36
    • 0347417190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legislative History and the Limits of Judicial Competence: The Untold Story of Holy Trinity Church
    • n.181
    • This use of originalist materials contrasts with (what I take to be) the right conception of textualism in statutory interpretation, which eschews legislative history altogether. For the argument that the two positions are consistent, see Adrian Vermeule, Legislative History and the Limits of Judicial Competence: The Untold Story of Holy Trinity Church, 50 STAN. L. REV. 1833, 1886 n.181 (1998).
    • (1998) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.50 , pp. 1833
    • Vermeule, A.1
  • 37
    • 84884043660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hercules, Herbert and Amar: The Trouble with Intratextualism
    • For a critique of holistic comparison, see Adrian Vermeule & Ernest A. Young, Hercules, Herbert and Amar: The Trouble with Intratextualism, 113 HARV. L. REV. 730 (2000).
    • (2000) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.113 , pp. 730
    • Vermeule, A.1    Young, E.A.2
  • 38
    • 84923726903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 10
    • See supra note 10.
  • 39
    • 0347716229 scopus 로고
    • Presidents, Vice Presidents, and Death: Closing the Constitution's Succession Gap
    • See Akhil Reed Amar, Presidents, Vice Presidents, and Death: Closing the Constitution's Succession Gap, 48 ARK. L. REV. 215, 227 (1994) (justifying the congressional enactment of succession rules on veil of ignorance grounds); cf. 17 CONG. REC. 815 (1886) (statement of Sen. Sherman) ("The proposed [Electoral Count Act] comes before us . . . at the beginning of an administration, when no party advantage can be derived from our decision.").
    • (1994) Ark. L. Rev. , vol.48 , pp. 215
    • Amar, A.R.1
  • 40
    • 84923747559 scopus 로고
    • See Akhil Reed Amar, Presidents, Vice Presidents, and Death: Closing the Constitution's Succession Gap, 48 ARK. L. REV. 215, 227 (1994) (justifying the congressional enactment of succession rules on veil of ignorance grounds); cf. 17 CONG. REC. 815 (1886) (statement of Sen. Sherman) ("The proposed [Electoral Count Act] comes before us . . . at the beginning of an administration, when no party advantage can be derived from our decision.").
    • (1886) Cong. Rec. , vol.17 , pp. 815
  • 41
    • 84923726902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Amar, supra note 32, at 221
    • Amar, supra note 32, at 221.
  • 42
    • 84923726901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 5
    • See supra note 5.
  • 43
    • 0345786094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Should Bouie Be Buoyed?: Judicial Retroactive Lawmaking and the Ex Post Facto Clause
    • E.g., Weaver v. Graham, 450 U.S. 24 (1981) (invalidating a Florida statute that had retroactively reduced prisoners' "gain time" for good behavior). A minor wrinkle is that the Supreme Court has occasionally read ex post facto principles into the Due Process Clause, with the result that a few cases hold unforeseeable judicial interpretations of statutes unconstitutional. E.g., Bouie v. City of Columbia, 378 U.S. 347 (1964) (holding that the South Carolina Supreme Court violated the petitioners' due process rights by retroactively applying its new construction of a state statute). But the unforeseeability requirement is construed very grudgingly, and the official view remains that the ex post facto prohibition binds only legislatures, not courts. See Rogers v. Tennessee, 121 S. Ct. 1693 (2001); Harold J. Krent, Should Bouie Be Buoyed?: Judicial Retroactive Lawmaking and the Ex Post Facto Clause, 3 ROGER WILLIAMS U. L. REV. 35 (1997).
    • (1997) Roger Williams U. L. Rev. , vol.3 , pp. 35
    • Krent, H.J.1
  • 44
    • 84923726900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Dobbert v. Florida, 432 U.S. 282 (1977) (upholding, against an ex post facto challenge, a retroactive change in death penalty sentencing procedure).
  • 45
    • 0042124827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Puzzling Boundary between Criminal and Civil Retroactive Lawmaking
    • Harold J. Krent, The Puzzling Boundary Between Criminal and Civil Retroactive Lawmaking, 84 GEO. L.J. 2143 (1996).
    • (1996) Geo. L.J. , vol.84 , pp. 2143
    • Krent, H.J.1
  • 46
    • 0345562963 scopus 로고
    • The Case for Retroactive Taxation
    • Saul Levmore, The Case for Retroactive Taxation, 22 J. LEGAL STUD. 265, 280 (1993) (arguing, in light of interest-group theory, that rules burdening identifiable groups are less likely to be enacted than rules burdening unidentifiable groups).
    • (1993) J. Legal Stud. , vol.22 , pp. 265
    • Levmore, S.1
  • 47
    • 84923726899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Krent, supra note 37, at 2168 n.132
    • Krent, supra note 37, at 2168 n.132.
  • 48
    • 84923726898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The Clause was held to cover only criminal legislation in Calder v. Bull, 3 U.S. (3 Dall.) 386, 390 (1798). But that holding was hotly contested at the time. Satterlee v. Matthewson, 27 U.S. (2 Pet.) 380, 414-16 (1829) (Johnson, J., dissenting). It is still controversial in originalist circles today. See, e.g., E. Enters, v. Apfel, 524 U.S. 498, 538 (1998) (Thomas, J., concurring) (expressing his willingness to overrule Calder).
  • 49
    • 84923726897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • E. Enters., 524 U.S. at 537 (plurality opinion) (invalidating a retroactive civil statute as an uncompensated taking of property); id. at 539 (Kennedy, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (reaching the same result under a due process analysis).
  • 50
    • 84923726896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Perhaps the Justices in Calder v. Bull intuited this point. See 3 U.S. (3 Dall.) at 400 (Iredell, J.) (warning that "[w]ithout the possession of this power [to enact retroactive civil laws] the operations of government would often be obstructed").
  • 51
    • 84928220165 scopus 로고
    • Equality Guarantees in State Constitutional Law
    • Robert F. Williams, Equality Guarantees in State Constitutional Law, 63 TEX. L. REV. 1195, 1196 (1985).
    • (1985) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.63 , pp. 1195
    • Williams, R.F.1
  • 52
    • 84923726895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 1 ("[A]ll Duties, Imposts and Excises shall be uniform throughout the United States . . . ."); id. art. I, § 8, cl. 4 ("Congress shall have power . . . To establish an uniform Rule of Naturalization, and uniform laws on the subject of Bankruptcies throughout the United States . . . ."); id. art. I, § 9, cl. 6 ("No Preference shall be given by any Regulation of Commerce or Revenue to the Ports of one State over those of another . . . .").
  • 53
    • 84926274285 scopus 로고
    • A Common Law for Labor Relations: A Critique of the New Deal Labor Legislation
    • Richard A. Epstein, A Common Law for Labor Relations: A Critique of the New Deal Labor Legislation, 92 YALE L.J. 1357, 1364 (1983); see also RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, TAKINGS 240 (1985) (justifying general tort rules on veil of ignorance grounds). For a recent attempt to make generality the master principle of constitutional choice, see JAMES M. BUCHANAN & ROGER D. CONGLETON, POLITICS BY PRINCIPLE, NOT INTEREST (1998).
    • (1983) Yale L.J. , vol.92 , pp. 1357
    • Epstein, R.A.1
  • 54
    • 0004267870 scopus 로고
    • Richard A. Epstein, A Common Law for Labor Relations: A Critique of the New Deal Labor Legislation, 92 YALE L.J. 1357, 1364 (1983); see also RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, TAKINGS 240 (1985) (justifying general tort rules on veil of ignorance grounds). For a recent attempt to make generality the master principle of constitutional choice, see JAMES M. BUCHANAN & ROGER D. CONGLETON, POLITICS BY PRINCIPLE, NOT INTEREST (1998).
    • (1985) Takings , pp. 240
    • Epstein, R.A.1
  • 55
    • 0006773120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richard A. Epstein, A Common Law for Labor Relations: A Critique of the New Deal Labor Legislation, 92 YALE L.J. 1357, 1364 (1983); see also RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, TAKINGS 240 (1985) (justifying general tort rules on veil of ignorance grounds). For a recent attempt to make generality the master principle of constitutional choice, see JAMES M. BUCHANAN & ROGER D. CONGLETON, POLITICS BY PRINCIPLE, NOT INTEREST (1998).
    • (1998) Politics by Principle, Not Interest
    • Buchanan, J.M.1    Congleton, R.D.2
  • 56
    • 0043117639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Attainder and Amendment 2: Romer's Rightness
    • Akhil Reed Amar, Attainder and Amendment 2: Romer's Rightness, 95 MICH. L. REV. 203, 210 (1996).
    • (1996) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 203
    • Amar, A.R.1
  • 57
    • 84923726894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These hypotheticals are inspired by, but are different from, a series of cases examined id. at 211-13.
  • 58
    • 0345786092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is Amendment 2 Really a Bill of Attainder? Some Questions about Professor Amar's Analysis of Romer
    • Roderick M. Hills, Jr., Is Amendment 2 Really a Bill of Attainder? Some Questions About Professor Amar's Analysis of Romer, 95 MICH. L. REV. 236, 240 (1996).
    • (1996) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 236
    • Hills R.M., Jr.1
  • 59
    • 0003638780 scopus 로고
    • See United States v. Brown, 381 U.S. 437, 454 n.29 (1965); n.25 (2d ed.)
    • See United States v. Brown, 381 U.S. 437, 454 n.29 (1965); LAURENCE H. TRIBE, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 646 n.25 (2d ed. 1988).
    • (1988) AMerican Constitutional Law , pp. 646
    • Tribe, L.H.1
  • 60
    • 84923726893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Brown, 381 U.S. at 450-56
    • See Brown, 381 U.S. at 450-56.
  • 61
    • 84923726892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Notwithstanding the dubious decision in Nixon v. Administrator of General Services, 433 U.S. 425, 472 (1977), which held that a statute specifically regulating the disposition of former President Nixon's papers, and of his alone, did not amount to a bill of attainder because Nixon constituted a "legitimate class of one."
  • 62
    • 84923726891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Heckler v. Mathews, 465 U.S. 728 (1984) (upholding a gender-discriminatory allocation of social security benefits).
  • 63
    • 0001114770 scopus 로고
    • Legal Policy and the Endowment Effect
    • See Herbert Hovenkamp, Legal Policy and the Endowment Effect, 20 J. LEGAL STUD. 225 (1991).
    • (1991) J. Legal Stud. , vol.20 , pp. 225
    • Hovenkamp, H.1
  • 64
    • 84923726890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., BRENNAN & BUCHANAN, supra note 4, at 29-30
    • See, e.g., BRENNAN & BUCHANAN, supra note 4, at 29-30.
  • 65
    • 84923726889 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • An important special case of durability arises where the decisionmaker anticipates that she will occupy different, even opposed, roles in a series of future transactions that will be governed by a durable legal rule. This veil mechanism appears most commonly in nonconstitutional contexts. A decisionmaker who must choose rules of contract law, for example, might be led to choose impartially by anticipating that (1) the rules will govern a long series of future contracts and that (2) she will sometimes occupy the role of buyer, sometimes the role of seller.
  • 67
    • 84923726888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 531
    • Id. at 531.
  • 68
    • 84923726887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 11 n.173
    • See Fitts, supra note 11, at 967 n.173;
    • Fitts1
  • 69
    • 0345786083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Inevitable Infidelities of Constitutional Translation: The Case of the New Deal
    • John O. McGinnis, The Inevitable Infidelities of Constitutional Translation: The Case of the New Deal, 41 WM. & MARY L. REV. 177, 209 (1999).
    • (1999) Wm. & Mary L. Rev. , vol.41 , pp. 177
    • McGinnis, J.O.1
  • 70
    • 84923726886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Collin v. Smith, 578 F.2d 1197 (7th Cir. 1978) (invalidating a village ordinance that barred peaceful demonstrations by the American Nazi Party).
  • 71
    • 84937325710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Impeachment as Congressional Constitutional Interpretation
    • See Neal Kumar Katyal, Impeachment as Congressional Constitutional Interpretation, 63 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 169, 186 (2000).
    • (2000) Law & Contemp. Probs. , vol.63 , pp. 169
    • Katyal, N.K.1
  • 72
    • 0011804297 scopus 로고
    • See ROBERT E. GOODIN, POLITICAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 162-83 (1982) (comparing an approach that discounts the distant future with an approach that ignores it on decision-theoretic grounds); Adrian Vermeule, Interpretive Choice, 75 N.Y.U. L. REV. 74, 123-28 (2000) (explaining why decisionmakers might rationally ignore the speculative future consequences of their decisions).
    • (1982) Political Theory and Public Policy , pp. 162-183
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 73
    • 23044520555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretive Choice
    • See ROBERT E. GOODIN, POLITICAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 162-83 (1982) (comparing an approach that discounts the distant future with an approach that ignores it on decision-theoretic grounds); Adrian Vermeule, Interpretive Choice, 75 N.Y.U. L. REV. 74, 123-28 (2000) (explaining why decisionmakers might rationally ignore the speculative future consequences of their decisions).
    • (2000) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 74
    • Vermeule, A.1
  • 74
    • 0037550435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arguing and Bargaining in Two Constituent Assemblies
    • Jon Elster, Arguing and Bargaining in Two Constituent Assemblies, 2 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 345 (2000); Robert A. McGuire, Constitution Making: A Rational Choice Model of the Federal Convention of 1787, 32 AM. J. POL. SCI. 483 (1988) (stating that voting patterns at the Federal Convention correlated with the economic interests of constituents and, less strongly, with the economic interests of the delegates themselves).
    • (2000) U. Pa. J. Const. L. , vol.2 , pp. 345
    • Elster, J.1
  • 75
    • 84935898640 scopus 로고
    • Constitution Making: A Rational Choice Model of the Federal Convention of 1787
    • Jon Elster, Arguing and Bargaining in Two Constituent Assemblies, 2 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 345 (2000); Robert A. McGuire, Constitution Making: A Rational Choice Model of the Federal Convention of 1787, 32 AM. J. POL. SCI. 483 (1988) (stating that voting patterns at the Federal Convention correlated with the economic interests of constituents and, less strongly, with the economic interests of the delegates themselves).
    • (1988) Am. J. Pol. Sci. , vol.32 , pp. 483
    • McGuire, R.A.1
  • 76
    • 84923726885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98, 109 (2000) (per curiam) ("Our consideration is limited to the present circumstances, for the problem of equal protection in election processes generally presents many complexities.").
  • 77
    • 84923726884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Katyal, supra note 60, at 186
    • See Katyal, supra note 60, at 186.
  • 78
    • 84923726883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "Ordinary" legislation should be understood to mean legislation that is, among other things, solely prospective when it does enter into effect. This excludes the intricate, but unprofitable, analytic complexities that would arise if legislatures could enact laws that would, upon taking effect after a delay, have retroactive effects on conduct occurring before or during the period of delay.
  • 79
    • 0346417197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6-7
    • The closest analogue in the Federal Constitution is a matched pair of rules in Article I and in Article V. The Article I provision forbade Congress from prohibiting the "Migration or Importation of such Persons as any of the States now existing shall think proper to admit" (read: slaves) until the year 1808. U.S. CONST, art. I, § 9, cl. 1. The latter provision made the former provision unamendable before 1808 (at which point any amendment would be moot). Id. art. V. But the analogy is not very close. These rules prohibited action until a particular time certain; Congress could and did legislate in 1807 with no uncertainty at all about the distribution of benefits and burdens from the decision. DAVID P. CURRIE, THE CONSTITUTION IN CONGRESS: THE JEFFERSONIANS, 1801-29, at 6-7 (2001) (describing federal legislation enacted in 1807 that abolished the slave trade). A delayed-effectiveness rule, by contrast, produces veil-like effects only because it builds in a delay period that attaches no matter when the legislation is enacted or the decision made.
    • (2001) The Constitution in Congress: the Jeffersonians , pp. 1801-1829
    • Currie, D.P.1
  • 80
    • 84923726882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. CONST. amend. XXVII
    • U.S. CONST. amend. XXVII.
  • 81
    • 84923726881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This was an inaccuracy on Madison's part. The Amendment, as drafted and as eventually enacted, requires a delay only until the next election of representatives, not (also) of senators. We should probably see this as a raw compromise with the costs of delay: Waiting until after the whole Senate had been subject to reelection - that is, until after the next three senatorial elections - would prevent a medium-term adjustment of legislative salaries for little marginal gain in impartial decisionmaking.
  • 82
    • 0347047492 scopus 로고
    • (Joseph Gales ed.) (emphasis added)
    • 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 457-58 (Joseph Gales ed., 1789) (emphasis added).
    • (1789) Annals of Cong. , vol.1 , pp. 457-458
  • 83
    • 84923726880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. CONST. art. I, § 6, cl. 2
    • U.S. CONST. art. I, § 6, cl. 2.
  • 84
    • 84923726879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • STORY, supra note 28, § 440, at 311.
    • , vol.440 , pp. 311
    • Story1
  • 85
    • 0346417191 scopus 로고
    • The Emoluments Clause: An Anti-Federalist Intruder in a Federalist Constitution
    • A somewhat different account of the purpose of the Clause emphasizes the fear that legislative-executive collusion would create an excessive number of new federal offices, expanding the federal government at the expense of the states
    • A somewhat different account of the purpose of the Clause emphasizes the fear that legislative-executive collusion would create an excessive number of new federal offices, expanding the federal government at the expense of the states. John F. O'Connor, The Emoluments Clause: An Anti-Federalist Intruder in a Federalist Constitution, 24 HOFSTRA L. REV. 89, 164-68 (1995).
    • (1995) Hofstra L. Rev. , vol.24 , pp. 89
    • O'Connor, J.F.1
  • 86
    • 0347047485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 56
    • This is something of an exaggeration, because even a permanent disability would leave scope for legislators to advance friends and relatives to federal offices, to create a new office in the hope of assuming an old office after its current occupant has moved to the new one, or to carry out other subtle schemes of evasion. But the Framers argued that suppressing the core case of biased decisionmaking would be worthwhile even if other (but costlier) substitutes remained available. 1 THE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, supra note 56, at 387-89.
    • The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787 , vol.1 , pp. 387-389
  • 87
    • 84923726878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 308
    • Id. at 308.
  • 88
    • 84923726877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Not merely confirmed to the office. The consistent practice has been to treat nomination as a component of appointment. O'Connor, supra note 71, at 105. The legislator may not, therefore, demand that the President nominate him to the office before voting on the bill - any action necessary to place the legislator in the new or enhanced office must wait until after the completion of the legislator's term.
  • 89
    • 69249173093 scopus 로고
    • Is Lloyd Bentsen Unconstitutional?
    • In this century, the Clause has been partially diluted by the so-called Saxbe fix, in which Congress attempts to remove a legislator's disability under the Clause by reducing the compensation of the office to the level prevailing at the beginning of the legislator's current electoral term. Therefore, if Congress raises the salary of the Secretary of the Treasury, and the President nominates a sitting senator to the post, the Saxbe fix purports to remove the senators ineligibility. See Michael Stokes Paulsen, Is Lloyd Bentsen Unconstitutional?, 46 STAN. L. REV. 907, 908-09 (1994). Nothing I say here turns upon the much-debated question whether the Saxbe fix is constitutional.
    • (1994) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.46 , pp. 907
    • Paulsen, M.S.1
  • 90
    • 0346417193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice Without Justices
    • John O. McGinnis, Justice Without Justices, 16 CONST. COMMENT. 541, 545 (1999). In a similar vein is Michael Abramowicz's ingenious proposal that an en banc decision in any one federal circuit court of appeals should be made by courts of appeals judges randomly selected from other circuits - a proposal that Abramowicz justifies, in part, on the veil-like ground that "judges might make better decisions when the identities of those who will review the decisions are unknown." Michael Abramowicz, En Banc Revisited, 100 COLUM. L. REV. 1600, 1603 (2000).
    • (1999) Const. Comment. , vol.16 , pp. 541
    • McGinnis, J.O.1
  • 91
    • 0042279879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • En Banc Revisited
    • John O. McGinnis, Justice Without Justices, 16 CONST. COMMENT. 541, 545 (1999). In a similar vein is Michael Abramowicz's ingenious proposal that an en banc decision in any one federal circuit court of appeals should be made by courts of appeals judges randomly selected from other circuits - a proposal that Abramowicz justifies, in part, on the veil-like ground that "judges might make better decisions when the identities of those who will review the decisions are unknown." Michael Abramowicz, En Banc Revisited, 100 COLUM. L. REV. 1600, 1603 (2000).
    • (2000) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.100 , pp. 1600
    • Abramowicz, M.1
  • 92
    • 84923747936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20, (Alexander Hamilton)
    • THE FEDERALIST No. 73, supra note 20, at 419 (Alexander Hamilton).
    • The Federalist No. 73 , vol.73 , pp. 419
  • 95
    • 0003920084 scopus 로고
    • See JON ELSTER SOLOMONIC JUDGMENTS 36-37 (1989) (explaining "the nonadoption of lotteries in situations where they would seem to be normatively compelling" on the basis that we have a strong reluctance to admit uncertainty and indeterminacy in human affairs. Rather than accept the limits of reason, we prefer the rituals of reason").
    • (1989) Solomonic Judgments , pp. 36-37
    • Elster, J.1
  • 96
    • 84923726876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By "independent" executive action, I mean executive action taken pursuant to a freestanding grant of constitutional authority, such as the pardon power or the power to appoint principal officers, rather than action taken in the President's capacity as a participant in the process of statutory enactment, such as the signature or veto of a bill. So I assimilate restrictions on the President's action in his capacity as legislator-in-chief into restrictions on the Congress itself. That the President, for example, may not constitutionally sign into law a bill that raises legislative salaries until an election of representatives has intervened - because the Twenty-Seventh Amendment bars such a law - counts, in my view, as a restriction on Congress, not on the President. The rationale for the categorization, in this example, is not that the salaries being raised are those of the Congress. The Constitution also prohibits altering the President's salary during his term of office, U.S. CONST, art. II, § 1, cl. 7 (thanks to Saul Levmore for reminding me of this provision), but since the President's salary must be altered by statute, that rule too counts in my schema as a restriction on Congress. Classifying veil rules in this way may overstate the skewed character of the constitutional distribution, but classifying such cases as restrictions on the President might be taken to understate the skew. There is no neutral baseline. I have chosen the former approach because the Framers invariably conceived rules such as the Ex Post Facto Clause as restrictions on legislative rather than executive power, despite the fact that such rules prevent the President from signing a retroactive criminal law just as much as they prevent the Congress from enacting one.
  • 97
    • 84923726875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 35
    • See supra note 35.
  • 99
    • 23044523944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prosecutorial Discretion and Prosecution Guidelines: A Case Study in Controlling Federalization
    • Cf. Michael A. Simons, Prosecutorial Discretion and Prosecution Guidelines: A Case Study in Controlling Federalization, 75 N.Y.U. L. REV. 893, 930-36 (2000) (arguing, among other things, that more specific prosecutorial guidelines, by controlling prosecutorial discretion, would prevent unfair treatment of individual defendants).
    • (2000) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 893
    • Simons, M.A.1
  • 101
    • 84923726874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Hills, supra note 48, at 242; see also Krent, supra note 35, at 41, 85-90 (arguing that "legislative retroactivity in the criminal context is more disfavored than lawmakmg by judges" because institutional-design features such as life tenure insulate judges from interest-group pressures).
  • 102
    • 84923709648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20, (James Madison)
    • THE FEDERALIST No. 10, supra note 20, at 125-26 (James Madison).
    • The Federalist No. 10 , vol.10 , pp. 125-126
  • 103
    • 84923726873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Levmore, supra note 12, at 2099-2101
    • See Levmore, supra note 12, at 2099-2101.
  • 104
    • 84923726831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Cf. ELSTER, supra note 19, at 145 (noting that delaying the effective date of constitutions is "utopian and probably undesirable" because "[d]emands for constitution-making or constitutional revision tend to arise in times of crisis in which waiting is an unaffordable luxury").
  • 105
    • 84923733947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20, (Alexander Hamilton)
    • See THE FEDERALIST No. 70, supra note 20, at 402 (Alexander Hamilton) (discussing "[e]nergy in the executive").
    • The Federalist No. 70 , vol.70 , pp. 402
  • 106
    • 84923726829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The modern federal judiciary has developed a great deal of control over its own agenda through such devices as standing and justiciability rules, see, e.g., Ashwander v. Tenn. Valley Auth., 297 U.S. 288, 341 (1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring), doctrines of equitable restraint, see, e.g., Younger v. Harris, 401 U.S. 37, 48-50 (1971), and the development of discretionary certiorari. But it should be noted that quite early in its history, the federal judiciary moved to assert control over its activities. See, e.g., Hayburn's Case, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 408, 410 n.a (1792) (listing circuit court opinions declining to give Congress and the Secretary of War nonbinding opinions on pension applications).
  • 108
    • 84923726827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There are only a handful of conflict-of-interest rules in the Constitution. In addition to the previously discussed provision that bars the Vice President from presiding over a Senate impeachment trial of the President, see supra note 28, other examples are Article I, Section 9, Clause 8, which bars officeholders from accepting foreign gifts or titles without the consent of Congress; Article II, Section 1, Clause 2, which prohibits members of Congress and federal officers from serving in the Electoral College; and Article II, Section 1, Clause 7, which bars the President from accepting any emolument from the states during his term in office.
  • 109
    • 84923718058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20, (James Madison)
    • THE FEDERALIST NO. 44, supra note 20, at 287-88 (James Madison).
    • The Federalist No. 44 , vol.44 , pp. 287-288
  • 110
    • 84923726826 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 288
    • Id. at 288.
  • 111
    • 84923738186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 20, (Alexander Hamilton)
    • See THE FEDERALIST No. 70, supra note 20, at 402-03 (Alexander Hamilton).
    • The Federalist No. 70 , vol.70 , pp. 402-403
  • 112
    • 84923726825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Alexander Hamilton) (arguing for four-year presidential terms on this basis)
    • See THE FEDERALIST No. 71 (Alexander Hamilton) (arguing for four-year presidential terms on this basis).
    • , vol.71
  • 113
    • 84923726824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Citizens To Preserve Overton Park, Inc. v. Volpe, 401 U.S. 402, 416 (1971).
  • 114
    • 84923726823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Bowen v. Georgetown Univ. Hosp., 488 U.S. 204, 208-09 (1988) (stating that agencies may make retroactive rules only under clear statutory authorization).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.