메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 6, 1999, Pages 621-654

Addiction as defect of the will: Some philosophical reflections

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0347092162     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3505095     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (86)

References (46)
  • 2
    • 0002146422 scopus 로고
    • Current Concepts of Addiction
    • Charles P. O'Brien and Jerome H. Jaffe, eds., New York: Raven Press
    • For a helpful overview of current approaches, see Jerome H. Jaffe, "Current Concepts of Addiction," in Charles P. O'Brien and Jerome H. Jaffe, eds., Addictive States (New York: Raven Press, 1992), pp. 1-22.
    • (1992) Addictive States , pp. 1-22
    • Jaffe, J.H.1
  • 3
    • 0347491082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming
    • My conclusions here are broadly in agreement with the characterization of addiction as an acquired appetite offered by Gary Watson, in "Disordered Appetites" (forthcoming).
    • Disordered Appetites
    • Watson, G.1
  • 4
    • 0003739470 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • I use the word craving here in a non-technical sense, to designate desires of particular intensity; I do not mean the technical use sometimes found in discussions of addiction, according to which cravings are literally irresistible impulses that overwhelm all ordinary capacities for deliberate self-control. For criticism of the technical use, see Herbert Fingarette, Heavy Drinking: The Myth of Alchoholism as a Disease (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988), pp. 41-43.
    • (1988) Heavy Drinking: The Myth of Alchoholism as a Disease , pp. 41-43
    • Fingarette, H.1
  • 7
    • 0242324049 scopus 로고
    • Addiction and the Value of Freedom
    • For a sensible discussion of some actual cases of this kind, see Graham Oddie, "Addiction and the Value of Freedom," Bioethics 7 (1993), pp. 373-401.
    • (1993) Bioethics , vol.7 , pp. 373-401
    • Oddie, G.1
  • 8
    • 0346275693 scopus 로고
    • Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • In "Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person," as reprinted in Harry G. Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care about (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 11-25.
    • (1988) The Importance of What we Care about , pp. 11-25
    • Frankfurt, H.G.1
  • 9
    • 0347491078 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, chap. 1
    • Compare G. F. Schueler's discussion of the "pro-attitude" conception of desire, in his Desire (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), chap. 1.
    • (1995) Desire
    • Schueler, G.F.1
  • 10
    • 0006930849 scopus 로고
    • Backgrounding Desire
    • Compare the formulation and interpretation of the "motivational perspective" on action offered by Philip Pettit and Michael Smith, in "Backgrounding Desire," Philosophical Review 99 (1990), pp. 565-592 and "Practical Unreason," Mind 102 (1993), pp. 53-79; see also Alfred R. Mele, Autonomous Agents (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), chap. 2.
    • (1990) Philosophical Review , vol.99 , pp. 565-592
    • Pettit, P.1    Smith, M.2
  • 11
    • 0347491081 scopus 로고
    • Practical Unreason
    • Compare the formulation and interpretation of the "motivational perspective" on action offered by Philip Pettit and Michael Smith, in "Backgrounding Desire," Philosophical Review 99 (1990), pp. 565-592 and "Practical Unreason," Mind 102 (1993), pp. 53-79; see also Alfred R. Mele, Autonomous Agents (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), chap. 2.
    • (1993) Mind , vol.102 , pp. 53-79
  • 12
    • 0003920487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press, chap. 2
    • Compare the formulation and interpretation of the "motivational perspective" on action offered by Philip Pettit and Michael Smith, in "Backgrounding Desire," Philosophical Review 99 (1990), pp. 565-592 and "Practical Unreason," Mind 102 (1993), pp. 53-79; see also Alfred R. Mele, Autonomous Agents (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), chap. 2.
    • (1995) Autonomous Agents
    • Mele, A.R.1
  • 13
    • 0001981679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom in Belief and Desire
    • Compare Philip Pettit and Michael Smith, "Freedom in Belief and Desire," Journal of Philosophy 93 (1996), pp. 429-449. See also Jeanette Kennett and Michael Smith, "Frog and Toad Lose Control," Analysis 56 (1996), pp. 63-73.
    • (1996) Journal of Philosophy , vol.93 , pp. 429-449
    • Pettit, P.1    Smith, M.2
  • 14
    • 0346230101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frog and Toad Lose Control
    • Compare Philip Pettit and Michael Smith, "Freedom in Belief and Desire," Journal of Philosophy 93 (1996), pp. 429-449. See also Jeanette Kennett and Michael Smith, "Frog and Toad Lose Control," Analysis 56 (1996), pp. 63-73.
    • (1996) Analysis , vol.56 , pp. 63-73
    • Kennett, J.1    Smith, M.2
  • 16
    • 0003920487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • See Alfred R. Mele, Irrationality: An Essay on Akrasia, Self-Deception, and Self-Control (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987); see also his Autonomous Agents, chap. 3.
    • Autonomous Agents
  • 17
    • 61949464482 scopus 로고
    • What Happens When Someone Acts?
    • On this point, see J. David Velleman, "What Happens When Someone Acts?" Mind 101 (1992), pp. 461-481. (Velleman's presentation of this problem is exemplary, though I do not agree with the reductionist solution he proposes.)
    • (1992) Mind , vol.101 , pp. 461-481
    • Velleman, J.D.1
  • 18
    • 0004293140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • These remarks may seem to have a libertarian cast that fits poorly with my other published views about responsibility and agency (in Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments [Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994]). So to set the record straight: I take the emphasis on the capacity to rise above one's given desires to be an appealing feature of libertarian and agent-causation theories, something that they get right. Unlike the proponents of such theories, however, I do not believe that this important capacity must be incompatible with determinism in every form (though it is irreconcileable with the kind of psychological determinism I have attributed to the hydraulic conception). For more on these matters,
    • (1994) Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments
  • 19
    • 84875530788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Responsibility and the Practical Point of View
    • Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, forthcoming
    • see my "Moral Responsibility and the Practical Point of View," in Ton van den Beld, ed., Moral Responsibility and Ontology (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, forthcoming).
    • Moral Responsibility and Ontology
    • Van Den Beld, T.1
  • 20
    • 0348121189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Some versions of the hydraulic model tend to collapse this distinction, treating practical judgments in noncognitivist terms, as themselves expressions of our given desires. This variant gives us a nonaccidental connection between practical judgment and motivation, but at the considerable cost of depriving practical judgment of its potential autonomy from given desire.
  • 21
    • 0348121188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare the ideal of orthonomy advocated by Pettit and Smith in "Practical Unreason," p. 77: "The important thing is not to assume control . . . [but] to be someone in whom desires are neither too strong nor too weak."
    • Practical Unreason , pp. 77
    • Pettit1    Smith2
  • 22
    • 0347491070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three Conceptions of Rational Agency
    • There are more sophisticated versions of the hydraulic approach that better capture our sense of ourselves as agents, though they remain inadequate in other respects; Velleman's favored reductionist account of agency in "What Happens When Someone Acts?" might be an example. For discussion, see the remarks about "meta-internalism" in my paper "Three Conceptions of Rational Agency," Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2 (1999), pp. 217-242.
    • (1999) Ethical Theory and Moral Practice , vol.2 , pp. 217-242
  • 23
    • 0348121183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding Self-Control: Kennett and Smith on Frog and Toad
    • For these two options, see the following debate: Alfred R. Mele, "Understanding Self-Control: Kennett and Smith on Frog and Toad," Analysis 57 (1997), pp. 119-123, and Jeanette Kennett and Michael Smith, "Synchronic Self-control is Always Non-actional," Analysis 57 (1997), pp. 123-131.
    • (1997) Analysis , vol.57 , pp. 119-123
    • Mele, A.R.1
  • 24
    • 0346230100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Synchronic Self-control is Always Non-actional
    • For these two options, see the following debate: Alfred R. Mele, "Understanding Self-Control: Kennett and Smith on Frog and Toad," Analysis 57 (1997), pp. 119-123, and Jeanette Kennett and Michael Smith, "Synchronic Self-control is Always Non-actional," Analysis 57 (1997), pp. 123-131.
    • (1997) Analysis , vol.57 , pp. 123-131
    • Kennett, J.1    Smith, M.2
  • 25
    • 0347491076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I should stress here that many motivational states seem to straddle this distinction in ways that make them difficult to classify. Most salient among these are states of being attracted to a course of action precisely because one judges that it would be good to perform. The involvement of evaluative judgment in these states makes it misleading to describe them as states with respect to which we are merely passive (as Angela Smith has helped me to see). And yet, being attracted to a course of action is not under our direct control in the way our intentions, choices, and decisions seem to be.
  • 27
    • 0003343064 scopus 로고
    • Internal and External Reasons
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See, most influentially, Bernard Williams, "Internal and External Reasons," as reprinted in Williams, Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), pp. 101-113.
    • (1981) Moral Luck , pp. 101-113
    • Williams, B.1
  • 28
    • 0039688213 scopus 로고
    • Putting Rationality in its Place
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • I am indebted here to Warren Quinn, "Putting Rationality in its Place," as reprinted in Quinn, Morality and Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 228-255.
    • (1993) Morality and Action , pp. 228-255
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 29
    • 0348121185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thus my preference that a long-lost friend should be thriving may be satisfied, in this sense of formal fulfillment, even if I never find out what has become of him.
  • 30
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, chap. 1
    • Our reasons in these cases have what T. M. Scanlon calls "subjective conditions"; see his What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998), chap. 1.
    • (1998) What we Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 31
    • 0001537996 scopus 로고
    • The Authority of Desire
    • For some suggestive remarks in a similar vein, see Dennis W. Stampe, "The Authority of Desire," The Philosophical Review 96 (1987), pp. 341-381. (I would reject, however, the conclusions Stampe draws from the perceptual analogy concerning the role of desire in practical reasoning.) I should also stress in this context that the points I shall make about desires for pleasure are not meant to apply to all states that are referred to as desires in philosophical parlance (which include, among other things, the distinctive kind of "pro-attitudes" I have referred to as volitions). The phenomenological account I shall develop is an account of that sub-class of desires, of which A-desires are an example, that can present an agent with temptations in contexts of deliberation and decision.
    • (1987) The Philosophical Review , vol.96 , pp. 341-381
    • Stampe, D.W.1
  • 32
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 1
    • Compare Scanlon's remarks about desire in the "directed attention" sense, in What We Owe to Each Other, chap. 1, and Watson's discussion of the ways in which desires can be compelling, in "Disordered Appetites," sec. 3.
    • What We Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon1
  • 33
    • 0347491082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec. 3
    • Compare Scanlon's remarks about desire in the "directed attention" sense, in What We Owe to Each Other, chap. 1, and Watson's discussion of the ways in which desires can be compelling, in "Disordered Appetites," sec. 3.
    • Disordered Appetites
    • Watson1
  • 35
    • 0346860564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Morse, "Causation, Compulsion, and Involuntariness," and Herbert Fingarette, "Addiction and Criminal Responsibility," Yale Law Journal 84 (1975), pp. 413-444, at pp. 437-438. See also Gary Watson's paper in this volume, "Addiction and Duress."
    • Causation, Compulsion, and Involuntariness
    • Morse1
  • 36
    • 84925889040 scopus 로고
    • Addiction and Criminal Responsibility
    • Compare Morse, "Causation, Compulsion, and Involuntariness," and Herbert Fingarette, "Addiction and Criminal Responsibility," Yale Law Journal 84 (1975), pp. 413-444, at pp. 437-438. See also Gary Watson's paper in this volume, "Addiction and Duress."
    • (1975) Yale Law Journal , vol.84 , pp. 413-444
    • Fingarette, H.1
  • 37
    • 0346860563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Morse, "Causation, Compulsion, and Involuntariness," and Herbert Fingarette, "Addiction and Criminal Responsibility," Yale Law Journal 84 (1975), pp. 413-444, at pp. 437-438. See also Gary Watson's paper in this volume, "Addiction and Duress."
    • Addiction and Duress
    • Watson, G.1
  • 38
    • 0346231225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The effects of strong A-desires on the rationality of the agent subject to them are emphasized in Stephen Morse's contribution to the present volume, "Hooked on Hype."
    • Hooked on Hype
    • Morse, S.1
  • 39
    • 0348121180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • That is, from reflection about what one has most reason to do. It is compatible with resiliance in this sense that A-desires are connected to thoughts about the prospective pleasure to be gained through action, in the ways outlined in sec. 3 above.
  • 40
    • 0348121182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • this volume
    • In fact, the two scenarios I have described here are really two instances of the same basic kind of case. In the first scenario, we must suppose that the literal presence of the forbidden foodstuffs incites in us a desire to consume them, since chocolate and ice cream would not make us "vividly aware" of pleasant possibilities for action if they did not give rise to such a desire. The difference between the scenarios is simply that in the first, an intense desire is caused by the literal perception of the substance that is to be consumed, while this is not so in the second case. On the general role of situational cues in giving rise to A-desires, see George Loewenstein, "Willpower: A Decision-theorist's Perspective," this volume.
    • Willpower: A Decision-theorist's Perspective
    • Loewenstein, G.1
  • 41
    • 0004240370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chap. 1
    • They are treated this way, for instance, by Michael Stocker, in Valuing Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), chap. 1.
    • (1996) Valuing Emotions
    • Stocker, M.1
  • 42
    • 0039680308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Skepticism about Practical Reason
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • This is one version of the thesis referred to as internalism in discussions of normative reasons for action; see, for example, Christine M. Korsgaard, "Skepticism about Practical Reason," as reprinted in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 311-334.
    • (1996) Creating the Kingdom of Ends , pp. 311-334
    • Korsgaard, C.M.1
  • 45
    • 0347491064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • this volume
    • Questions about the justifiability of legislation proscribing addictive drugs, and their connection with the issue of whether addiction can function as a defense under the criminal law, are explored by Douglas Husak in "Addiction and Criminal Liability" (this volume).
    • Addiction and Criminal Liability
    • Husak, D.1
  • 46
    • 0347491055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I received much helpful feedback on earlier versions of this paper from the other participants in the Carolina Workshop in Law and Philosophy in September 1998, as well as from audiences at the Universities of Oxford and Reading in March 1999. I owe a special debt to Karin Boxer, Kirsten Petzold, and Angela Smith for detailed and probing comments; and to my "Hilfskräfte" Ninja Kaiser and Jacob Klingner for excellent research support.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.