-
1
-
-
0003643504
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
On biographical details see: Critchley, M. and Critchley, E. A., John Hughlings Jackson, father of British Neurology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998). On an analysis of his ideas in relation to neurology and psychiatry, respectively, see: López Piñero, J. M., John Hughlings Jackson. Evolutionismo y Neurology (Madrid: Moneda, 1973); Dewhurst, K., Hughlings Jackson on Psychiatry (Oxford: Sanford Publications, 1982).
-
(1998)
John Hughlings Jackson, Father of British Neurology
-
-
Critchley, M.1
Critchley, E.A.2
-
2
-
-
24844476352
-
-
Madrid: Moneda
-
On biographical details see: Critchley, M. and Critchley, E. A., John Hughlings Jackson, father of British Neurology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998). On an analysis of his ideas in relation to neurology and psychiatry, respectively, see: López Piñero, J. M., John Hughlings Jackson. Evolutionismo y Neurology (Madrid: Moneda, 1973); Dewhurst, K., Hughlings Jackson on Psychiatry (Oxford: Sanford Publications, 1982).
-
(1973)
John Hughlings Jackson. Evolutionismo y Neurology
-
-
López Piñero, J.M.1
-
3
-
-
0004266830
-
-
Oxford: Sanford Publications
-
On biographical details see: Critchley, M. and Critchley, E. A., John Hughlings Jackson, father of British Neurology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998). On an analysis of his ideas in relation to neurology and psychiatry, respectively, see: López Piñero, J. M., John Hughlings Jackson. Evolutionismo y Neurology (Madrid: Moneda, 1973); Dewhurst, K., Hughlings Jackson on Psychiatry (Oxford: Sanford Publications, 1982).
-
(1982)
Hughlings Jackson on Psychiatry
-
-
Dewhurst, K.1
-
4
-
-
0002422987
-
The major influences on the early life and work of John Hughlings Jackson
-
The issue is described as 'obscure' for there is not always agreement between (a) what Jackson officially declared as his sources, (b) what close textual reading of his work suggests to the historian, and (c) what is known of indirect influences, i.e. assumptions which came to him hidden in the views of the physicians and neurologists he admired (on the latter see the useful: Greenblatt, S. H., 'The major influences on the early life and work of John Hughlings Jackson', Bulletin of the History of Medicine, xxxix (1965), 346-76).
-
(1965)
Bulletin of the History of Medicine
, vol.39
, pp. 346-376
-
-
Greenblatt, S.H.1
-
5
-
-
0347333460
-
Hughlings Jackson's doctrine of consciousness
-
Jackson's views on consciousness (see Riese, W., 'Hughlings Jackson's doctrine of consciousness', Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, cxx (1954), 330-7), 'the mind' (Levin, M., 'Hughlings Jackson's views on mentation', Archives of Psychiatry, xxx (1933), 848-74) and 'the mental' (see Balan, B., 'Les Fondements psychologiques de la notion d'automatisme mental chez John Hughlings Jackson', L'Information psychiatrique, lxix (1989), 610-19), and 'mental disorders' (see Savage, G., 'Dr Hughlings Jackson on mental disorders') The Journal of Mental Science, xliii (1917), 315-28) have not been yet fully disentangled. As with other abstruse (or careless) writers, the historian may choose to take Jackson's claims ad verbum or dig in for subterranean meanings. Because in the case of Jackson the former approach often leads to blind alleys (i.e. contradictory and/or meaningless claims are soon met with), and because of the reputation of the man, historians turn exegetes with some ease.
-
(1954)
Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease
, vol.120
, pp. 330-337
-
-
Riese, W.1
-
6
-
-
0347333459
-
Hughlings Jackson's views on mentation
-
Jackson's views on consciousness (see Riese, W., 'Hughlings Jackson's doctrine of consciousness', Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, cxx (1954), 330-7), 'the mind' (Levin, M., 'Hughlings Jackson's views on mentation', Archives of Psychiatry, xxx (1933), 848-74) and 'the mental' (see Balan, B., 'Les Fondements psychologiques de la notion d'automatisme mental chez John Hughlings Jackson', L'Information psychiatrique, lxix (1989), 610-19), and 'mental disorders' (see Savage, G., 'Dr Hughlings Jackson on mental disorders') The Journal of Mental Science, xliii (1917), 315-28) have not been yet fully disentangled. As with other abstruse (or careless) writers, the historian may choose to take Jackson's claims ad verbum or dig in for subterranean meanings. Because in the case of Jackson the former approach often leads to blind alleys (i.e. contradictory and/or meaningless claims are soon met with), and because of the reputation of the man, historians turn exegetes with some ease.
-
(1933)
Archives of Psychiatry
, vol.30
, pp. 848-874
-
-
Levin, M.1
-
7
-
-
0347333454
-
Les Fondements psychologiques de la notion d'automatisme mental chez John Hughlings Jackson
-
Jackson's views on consciousness (see Riese, W., 'Hughlings Jackson's doctrine of consciousness', Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, cxx (1954), 330-7), 'the mind' (Levin, M., 'Hughlings Jackson's views on mentation', Archives of Psychiatry, xxx (1933), 848-74) and 'the mental' (see Balan, B., 'Les Fondements psychologiques de la notion d'automatisme mental chez John Hughlings Jackson', L'Information psychiatrique, lxix (1989), 610-19), and 'mental disorders' (see Savage, G., 'Dr Hughlings Jackson on mental disorders') The Journal of Mental Science, xliii (1917), 315-28) have not been yet fully disentangled. As with other abstruse (or careless) writers, the historian may choose to take Jackson's claims ad verbum or dig in for subterranean meanings. Because in the case of Jackson the former approach often leads to blind alleys (i.e. contradictory and/or meaningless claims are soon met with), and because of the reputation of the man, historians turn exegetes with some ease.
-
(1989)
L'Information Psychiatrique
, vol.69
, pp. 610-619
-
-
Balan, B.1
-
8
-
-
0347333457
-
Dr Hughlings Jackson on mental disorders
-
Jackson's views on consciousness (see Riese, W., 'Hughlings Jackson's doctrine of consciousness', Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, cxx (1954), 330-7), 'the mind' (Levin, M., 'Hughlings Jackson's views on mentation', Archives of Psychiatry, xxx (1933), 848-74) and 'the mental' (see Balan, B., 'Les Fondements psychologiques de la notion d'automatisme mental chez John Hughlings Jackson', L'Information psychiatrique, lxix (1989), 610-19), and 'mental disorders' (see Savage, G., 'Dr Hughlings Jackson on mental disorders') The Journal of Mental Science, xliii (1917), 315-28) have not been yet fully disentangled. As with other abstruse (or careless) writers, the historian may choose to take Jackson's claims ad verbum or dig in for subterranean meanings. Because in the case of Jackson the former approach often leads to blind alleys (i.e. contradictory and/or meaningless claims are soon met with), and because of the reputation of the man, historians turn exegetes with some ease.
-
(1917)
The Journal of Mental Science
, vol.43
, pp. 315-328
-
-
Savage, G.1
-
9
-
-
72849161609
-
The mind-body problem and Hughlings Jacksons doctrine of concomitance
-
Levin, M., The mind-body problem and Hughlings Jacksons doctrine of concomitance', American Journal of Psychiatry, cxvi (1959-60), 718-22.
-
(1959)
American Journal of Psychiatry
, vol.116
, pp. 718-722
-
-
Levin, M.1
-
10
-
-
0346072289
-
-
Leipzig: Enke
-
The literature on psychophysical parallelism or concomitance is enormous (see Eisler, M. R., 'Der psychophysische Parallelismus' (Leipzig: Enke, 1894); Bain, A., Mind and Body (London: King, 1874) and concerns the solutions offered in Western culture to the issue of how physical and psychological phenomena exchange information (see Rieber, R. W. (ed.), Body and Mind. Past Present and Future (New York: Academic Press, 1980). The problem remains extant (see: Feigl, H., 'The "mental" and the "physical", in Feigl, H. et al. (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), 370-497; Moravia, S., The Enigma of the Mind. The Mind-Body Problem in Contemporary Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)). Versions of Parallelism have been grouped into metaphysical (or ontological) and psychological, although it is generally believed that the latter can be subsumed under the former. For example, the versions put forward by Spinoza, Descartes or Leibniz are considered as 'ontological'. Psychological versions of psychophysical parallelism appeared during the nineteenth century in the work of writers such as Fechner and Helmholtz and ranged from the belief in 'correspondence' simpliciter to broader conceptions where even forms of interaction (between the physical and psychological) were allowed (see Boring, E. G., Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology (New York: Irvington Publishers, 1942)).
-
(1894)
Der Psychophysische Parallelismus
-
-
Eisler, M.R.1
-
11
-
-
0013429137
-
-
London: King
-
The literature on psychophysical parallelism or concomitance is enormous (see Eisler, M. R., 'Der psychophysische Parallelismus' (Leipzig: Enke, 1894); Bain, A., Mind and Body (London: King, 1874) and concerns the solutions offered in Western culture to the issue of how physical and psychological phenomena exchange information (see Rieber, R. W. (ed.), Body and Mind. Past Present and Future (New York: Academic Press, 1980). The problem remains extant (see: Feigl, H., 'The "mental" and the "physical", in Feigl, H. et al. (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), 370-497; Moravia, S., The Enigma of the Mind. The Mind-Body Problem in Contemporary Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)). Versions of Parallelism have been grouped into metaphysical (or ontological) and psychological, although it is generally believed that the latter can be subsumed under the former. For example, the versions put forward by Spinoza, Descartes or Leibniz are considered as 'ontological'. Psychological versions of psychophysical parallelism appeared during the nineteenth century in the work of writers such as Fechner and Helmholtz and ranged from the belief in 'correspondence' simpliciter to broader conceptions where even forms of interaction (between the physical and psychological) were allowed (see Boring, E. G., Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology (New York: Irvington Publishers, 1942)).
-
(1874)
Mind and Body
-
-
Bain, A.1
-
12
-
-
0346072281
-
-
New York: Academic Press
-
The literature on psychophysical parallelism or concomitance is enormous (see Eisler, M. R., 'Der psychophysische Parallelismus' (Leipzig: Enke, 1894); Bain, A., Mind and Body (London: King, 1874) and concerns the solutions offered in Western culture to the issue of how physical and psychological phenomena exchange information (see Rieber, R. W. (ed.), Body and Mind. Past Present and Future (New York: Academic Press, 1980). The problem remains extant (see: Feigl, H., 'The "mental" and the "physical", in Feigl, H. et al. (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), 370-497; Moravia, S., The Enigma of the Mind. The Mind-Body Problem in Contemporary Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)). Versions of Parallelism have been grouped into metaphysical (or ontological) and psychological, although it is generally believed that the latter can be subsumed under the former. For example, the versions put forward by Spinoza, Descartes or Leibniz are considered as 'ontological'. Psychological versions of psychophysical parallelism appeared during the nineteenth century in the work of writers such as Fechner and Helmholtz and ranged from the belief in 'correspondence' simpliciter to broader conceptions where even forms of interaction (between the physical and psychological) were allowed (see Boring, E. G., Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology (New York: Irvington Publishers, 1942)).
-
(1980)
Body and Mind. Past Present and Future
-
-
Rieber, R.W.1
-
13
-
-
0000817626
-
The "mental" and the "physical"
-
Feigl, H. et al. (eds), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
-
The literature on psychophysical parallelism or concomitance is enormous (see Eisler, M. R., 'Der psychophysische Parallelismus' (Leipzig: Enke, 1894); Bain, A., Mind and Body (London: King, 1874) and concerns the solutions offered in Western culture to the issue of how physical and psychological phenomena exchange information (see Rieber, R. W. (ed.), Body and Mind. Past Present and Future (New York: Academic Press, 1980). The problem remains extant (see: Feigl, H., 'The "mental" and the "physical", in Feigl, H. et al. (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), 370-497; Moravia, S., The Enigma of the Mind. The Mind-Body Problem in Contemporary Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)). Versions of Parallelism have been grouped into metaphysical (or ontological) and psychological, although it is generally believed that the latter can be subsumed under the former. For example, the versions put forward by Spinoza, Descartes or Leibniz are considered as 'ontological'. Psychological versions of psychophysical parallelism appeared during the nineteenth century in the work of writers such as Fechner and Helmholtz and ranged from the belief in 'correspondence' simpliciter to broader conceptions where even forms of interaction (between the physical and psychological) were allowed (see Boring, E. G., Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology (New York: Irvington Publishers, 1942)).
-
Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science
, vol.2
, pp. 370-497
-
-
Feigl, H.1
-
14
-
-
0346072283
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
The literature on psychophysical parallelism or concomitance is enormous (see Eisler, M. R., 'Der psychophysische Parallelismus' (Leipzig: Enke, 1894); Bain, A., Mind and Body (London: King, 1874) and concerns the solutions offered in Western culture to the issue of how physical and psychological phenomena exchange information (see Rieber, R. W. (ed.), Body and Mind. Past Present and Future (New York: Academic Press, 1980). The problem remains extant (see: Feigl, H., 'The "mental" and the "physical", in Feigl, H. et al. (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), 370-497; Moravia, S., The Enigma of the Mind. The Mind-Body Problem in Contemporary Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)). Versions of Parallelism have been grouped into metaphysical (or ontological) and psychological, although it is generally believed that the latter can be subsumed under the former. For example, the versions put forward by Spinoza, Descartes or Leibniz are considered as 'ontological'. Psychological versions of psychophysical parallelism appeared during the nineteenth century in the work of writers such as Fechner and Helmholtz and ranged from the belief in 'correspondence' simpliciter to broader conceptions where even forms of interaction (between the physical and psychological) were allowed (see Boring, E. G., Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology (New York: Irvington Publishers, 1942)).
-
(1995)
The Enigma of the Mind. The Mind-Body Problem in Contemporary Thought
-
-
Moravia, S.1
-
15
-
-
0004244064
-
-
New York: Irvington Publishers
-
The literature on psychophysical parallelism or concomitance is enormous (see Eisler, M. R., 'Der psychophysische Parallelismus' (Leipzig: Enke, 1894); Bain, A., Mind and Body (London: King, 1874) and concerns the solutions offered in Western culture to the issue of how physical and psychological phenomena exchange information (see Rieber, R. W. (ed.), Body and Mind. Past Present and Future (New York: Academic Press, 1980). The problem remains extant (see: Feigl, H., 'The "mental" and the "physical", in Feigl, H. et al. (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), 370-497; Moravia, S., The Enigma of the Mind. The Mind-Body Problem in Contemporary Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)). Versions of Parallelism have been grouped into metaphysical (or ontological) and psychological, although it is generally believed that the latter can be subsumed under the former. For example, the versions put forward by Spinoza, Descartes or Leibniz are considered as 'ontological'. Psychological versions of psychophysical parallelism appeared during the nineteenth century in the work of writers such as Fechner and Helmholtz and ranged from the belief in 'correspondence' simpliciter to broader conceptions where even forms of interaction (between the physical and psychological) were allowed (see Boring, E. G., Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology (New York: Irvington Publishers, 1942)).
-
(1942)
Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology
-
-
Boring, E.G.1
-
16
-
-
0016516181
-
John Hughlings Jackson and the mind-body relation
-
The best analysis of this issue remains Engelhardt, H. T., 'John Hughlings Jackson and the mind-body relation', Bulletin of the History of Medicine, xlix (1975), 137-51.
-
(1975)
Bulletin of the History of Medicine
, vol.49
, pp. 137-151
-
-
Engelhardt, H.T.1
-
17
-
-
0347333450
-
Recollections
-
Jackson, J. H., London: Oxford University Press
-
Mercier, Ch., 'Recollections', in Jackson, J. H., Neurological Fragments (London: Oxford University Press), 44.
-
Neurological Fragments
, pp. 44
-
-
Mercier, Ch.1
-
18
-
-
0346072287
-
-
December
-
Fortnightly Review, December 1874, 728.
-
(1874)
Fortnightly Review
, pp. 728
-
-
-
19
-
-
84965195772
-
On the comparative study of diseases of the nervous system
-
Jackson, J. H., 'On the comparative study of diseases of the nervous system'. Originally published in British Medical Journal, ii (1889), 355. Quoted here from Selected Writings of John Hughlings Jackson, Vol. II. Edited by James Taylor (London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1932), 393-410.
-
(1889)
British Medical Journal
, vol.2
, pp. 355
-
-
Jackson, J.H.1
-
20
-
-
0346703072
-
-
Edited by James Taylor London: Hodder & Stoughton
-
Jackson, J. H., 'On the comparative study of diseases of the nervous system'. Originally published in British Medical Journal, ii (1889), 355. Quoted here from Selected Writings of John Hughlings Jackson, Vol. II. Edited by James Taylor (London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1932), 393-410.
-
(1932)
Selected Writings of John Hughlings Jackson
, vol.2
, pp. 393-410
-
-
-
21
-
-
0002482406
-
Evolution and dissolution of the nervous system
-
Croonian Lectures delivered at the Royal College of Physicians Edited by James Taylor London: Hodder & Stoughton
-
p.72, 'Evolution and dissolution of the nervous system'. Croonian Lectures delivered at the Royal College of Physicians. In Selected Writings of John Hughlings Jackson, Vol. I. Edited by James Taylor (London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1932), 45-75.
-
(1932)
Selected Writings of John Hughlings Jackson
, vol.1
, pp. 45-75
-
-
-
22
-
-
0347333446
-
Hughlings Jackson on the connection between the mind and the brain
-
p.252, Prince, M., 'Hughlings Jackson on the connection between the mind and the brain', Brain, xiv (1891), 250-69.
-
(1891)
Brain
, vol.14
, pp. 250-269
-
-
Prince, M.1
-
23
-
-
0346072288
-
-
note
-
It is unclear whether his rejection of pre-ordainment resulted from a religious reason or a rejection or ignorance of Leibniz's views.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
0346703065
-
-
London: Everyman's Library
-
The locus classicus for the discussion of the issue of the parallelism between two 'self contained substances' is Leibniz's 'New system and explanation of the new system' where he writes: 'I was insensibly led to adopt a view which surprised me, but which seems inevitable, and which does in fact possess very great advantages and considerable beauties. This view is that we must say that God first created the soul, and every other real unity, in such a way that everything in it must spring from within itself, by a perfect spontaneity with regard to itself, and yet in a perfect conformity with things outside ... it follows from this that ... there will be a perfect agreement between all these substances, producing the same effect as would occur if these communicated with one another by means of a transmission of species or qualities...' (pp.122-3, in Leibniz: Philosophical Writings. Edited and Translated by G. H. R. Parkinson (London: Everyman's Library)).
-
Leibniz: Philosophical Writings
, pp. 122-123
-
-
Parkinson, G.H.R.1
-
25
-
-
0346072284
-
-
Paris: Collection Les Empêcheurs de Penser en Rond
-
In his excellent book on the influence of Leibniz's ideas on psychiatry, Jacques Chazaud calls Jackson a 'Leibnizian' (p.84, Chazaud, J., Leibniz pour les psy (Paris: Collection Les Empêcheurs de Penser en Rond, 1997).
-
(1997)
Leibniz Pour les Psy
, pp. 84
-
-
Chazaud, J.1
-
27
-
-
0346072286
-
-
Edited by Leslie Stephen and Frederick Pollock (London: Macmillan)
-
In Clifford, W. K., Lectures and Essays, Vol. II. Edited by Leslie Stephen and Frederick Pollock (London: Macmillan, 1879), 88. This quotation was used by Mach to support his own views (see Prologue to Third edition, Mach, E., Análisis de las Sensaciones (Barcelona, 1987)).
-
(1879)
Lectures and Essays
, vol.2
, pp. 88
-
-
Clifford, W.K.1
-
28
-
-
0347333456
-
Prologue to Third edition
-
Barcelona
-
In Clifford, W. K., Lectures and Essays, Vol. II. Edited by Leslie Stephen and Frederick Pollock (London: Macmillan, 1879), 88. This quotation was used by Mach to support his own views (see Prologue to Third edition, Mach, E., Análisis de las Sensaciones (Barcelona, 1987)).
-
(1987)
Análisis de Las Sensaciones
-
-
Mach, E.1
-
30
-
-
0004230658
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
For biographical information see Leslie Stephen's entry in the Dictionary of National Biography (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975).
-
(1975)
Dictionary of National Biography
-
-
-
35
-
-
0347963740
-
-
translated by J. W. Harvey et al. London: George Allen & Unwin
-
pp.121-7, in Metz, R., A Hundred Years of British Philosophy, translated by J. W. Harvey et al. (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1938).
-
(1938)
A Hundred Years of British Philosophy
, pp. 121-127
-
-
Metz, R.1
-
36
-
-
0346703071
-
Lecture XI (Theory of Psychophysical parallelism)
-
London; Adam & Charles Black
-
For a serious criticism of Clifford's views see Lecture XI (Theory of Psychophysical parallelism) in Ward, J., Naturalism and Gnosticism. The Gifford Lectures 1896-1898, Vol. II (London; Adam & Charles Black, 1899), 13-17; and McIntyre, J. L., 'Body and mind". In Vol. II of Hastings, J., Encyclopædia of Religion and Ethics (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1909), 774-8.
-
(1899)
Naturalism and Gnosticism. The Gifford Lectures 1896-1898
, vol.2
, pp. 13-17
-
-
Ward, J.1
-
37
-
-
0347963745
-
Body and mind
-
Hastings, J., Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark
-
For a serious criticism of Clifford's views see Lecture XI (Theory of Psychophysical parallelism) in Ward, J., Naturalism and Gnosticism. The Gifford Lectures 1896-1898, Vol. II (London; Adam & Charles Black, 1899), 13-17; and McIntyre, J. L., 'Body and mind". In Vol. II of Hastings, J., Encyclopædia of Religion and Ethics (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1909), 774-8.
-
(1909)
Encyclopædia of Religion and Ethics
, vol.2
, pp. 774-778
-
-
McIntyre, J.L.1
-
38
-
-
0000970696
-
Hughlings Jackson's influence in psychiatry
-
See Stengel, E., 'Hughlings Jackson's influence in psychiatry', British Journal of Psychiatry, cix (1963), 348-55.
-
(1963)
British Journal of Psychiatry
, vol.109
, pp. 348-355
-
-
Stengel, E.1
-
39
-
-
0022005284
-
Positive and negative symptoms and Jackson: A conceptual history
-
Berrios, G. E., 'Positive and negative symptoms and Jackson: a conceptual history", Archives General Psychiatry, xlii (1985), 95-7.
-
(1985)
Archives General Psychiatry
, vol.42
, pp. 95-97
-
-
Berrios, G.E.1
-
41
-
-
0004197648
-
-
London: George Allen & Unwin
-
pp.xv-xvi, Bergson, H., Matter and Memory (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1911).
-
(1911)
Matter and Memory
-
-
Bergson, H.1
-
42
-
-
0346703074
-
The principle of evolution of nervous function
-
On this concept see: Riese, W., 'The principle of evolution of nervous function', Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, xcviii (1943), 255-66.
-
(1943)
Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease
, vol.98
, pp. 255-266
-
-
Riese, W.1
|