-
1
-
-
60950056906
-
Malebranche's Natural Theodicy and the Incompleteness of God's Volitions
-
Andrew Pessin, "Malebranche's Natural Theodicy and the Incompleteness of God's Volitions," Religious Studies 36 (2000): 47-63;
-
(2000)
Religious Studies
, vol.36
, pp. 47-63
-
-
Pessin, A.1
-
2
-
-
60950024200
-
Malebranche's Doctrine of Freedom/Consent and the Incompleteness of God's Volitions
-
"Malebranche's Doctrine of Freedom/Consent and the Incompleteness of God's Volitions," British Journal for the History of Philosophy 8 (2000): 21-53;
-
(2000)
British Journal for the History of Philosophy
, vol.8
, pp. 21-53
-
-
-
3
-
-
84868725903
-
Does Continuous Creation Entail Occasionalism? Malebranche (and Descartes)
-
"Does Continuous Creation Entail Occasionalism? Malebranche (and Descartes)," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30 (2000): 413-40;
-
(2000)
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.30
, pp. 413-440
-
-
-
4
-
-
0344342988
-
Malebranche's Distinction Between General and Particular Volitions
-
"Malebranche's Distinction Between General and Particular Volitions," Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (2001): 77-99.
-
(2001)
Journal of the History of Philosophy
, vol.39
, pp. 77-99
-
-
-
5
-
-
60949704066
-
Cartesian Causality, Explanation, and Divine Concurrence
-
In recent scholarship only the following even entertain the idea of Cartesian concurrentism: Kenneth Clatterbaugh, "Cartesian Causality, Explanation, and Divine Concurrence," History of Philosophy Quarterly 12 (1995): 195-207;
-
(1995)
History of Philosophy Quarterly
, vol.12
, pp. 195-207
-
-
Clatterbaugh, K.1
-
8
-
-
84868421578
-
One Cause or Many? Jesuit Influences on Descartes's Division of Causes
-
Helen Hattab, "One Cause or Many? Jesuit Influences on Descartes's Division of Causes," Rencontres de Philosophie Médiévale 7, Société Internationale pour l'Étude de la Philosophie Médiévale (1998), and also "The Problem of Secondary Causation in Descartes: A Response to Des Chene," forthcoming in Perspectives on Science. Of these, only Hattab ultimately defends Cartesian concurrentism, although in aversion quite different from my own. I discuss Van Ruler and Clatterbaugh below.
-
Rencontres de Philosophie Médiévale
, pp. 7
-
-
Hattab, H.1
-
10
-
-
80053792021
-
-
Nicholas Jolley, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (henceforth Dialogues)
-
See the following: Malebranche, Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion, David Scott, trans., Nicholas Jolley, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), VII (henceforth Dialogues);
-
(1997)
Malebranche, Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion
-
-
Scott, D.1
-
11
-
-
79954724895
-
-
D. Clarke, trans. (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers (henceforth Treatise)
-
La Forge, Treatise on the Human Mind, D. Clarke, trans. (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1997), XVI (henceforth Treatise);
-
(1997)
Treatise on the Human Mind
-
-
Forge, L.1
-
12
-
-
0042179956
-
Cartesian Motion
-
P. Machamer and R. Turnbull, eds, Columbus: The Ohio State University Press
-
for discussion, see: Wallace Anderson, "Cartesian Motion," in Motion and Time, Space and Matter, P. Machamer and R. Turnbull, eds. (Columbus: The Ohio State University Press, 1976), 203-5;
-
(1976)
Motion and Time, Space and Matter
, pp. 203-205
-
-
Anderson, W.1
-
14
-
-
80053699524
-
-
D. Garber and M. Ayers, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press chs. 9 and 18, respectively
-
and Daniel Garber, John Henry, Lynn Joy and Alan Gabbey, "New Doctrines of Body and its Powers, Place, and Space," both in The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy, D. Garber and M. Ayers, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), chs. 9 and 18, respectively;
-
(1998)
New Doctrines of Body and its Powers, Place, and Space, both in The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy
-
-
Garber, D.1
Henry, J.2
Joy, L.3
Gabbey, A.4
-
15
-
-
80053696806
-
Philosophical Commentary on Malebranche's The Search After Truth
-
T. Lennon and P. Olscamp, trans, and eds. (Columbus: The Ohio State University Press
-
Thomas Lennon, "Philosophical Commentary on Malebranche's The Search After Truth," in Nicolas Malebranche, The Search After Truth, T. Lennon and P. Olscamp, trans, and eds. (Columbus: The Ohio State University Press, 1980), 814-5.
-
(1980)
Nicolas Malebranche, The Search After Truth
, pp. 814-815
-
-
Lennon, T.1
-
16
-
-
85050709620
-
-
n. 39 below, and, Oxford: Blackwell
-
for discussion, see n. 39 below, and John Cottingham, A Descartes Dictionary (Oxford: Blackwell 1993), 22.
-
(1993)
A Descartes Dictionary
, pp. 22
-
-
Cottingham, J.1
-
18
-
-
0345205478
-
Necessity and Physical Laws in Descartes's Philosophy
-
In conversation, Daniel Garber suggested that the laws follow from God's immutable manner of conserving the material world without being explicitly willed by Him. I offer a more detailed reply in "Descartes's Nomic Concurrentism and its Implications" (in preparation); here I merely note that there is no reason for Descartes not to construe the laws as willed, and that Garber's suggestion seems inconsistent with Descartes's distinction between conservation and concurrence (part 2 below) and with his many references to laws as "causes." (For relevant discussion, see Janet Broughton, "Necessity and Physical Laws in Descartes's Philosophy," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 68 [1987], 205-21,
-
(1987)
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.68
, pp. 205-221
-
-
Broughton, J.1
-
19
-
-
54749099716
-
Platonism and Descartes' View of Immutable Essences
-
and Tad Schmaltz, "Platonism and Descartes' View of Immutable Essences," Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophie, 73 [1991] 129-70.)
-
(1991)
Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophie
, vol.73
, pp. 129-170
-
-
Schmaltz, T.1
-
22
-
-
77952432400
-
-
In fact the term "laws of nature" may refer to at least five different things: the rules that God follows in forming some practical volitions (cf. Hatfield, "Force (God) in Descartes's Physics,"
-
Force (God) in Descartes's Physics
-
-
Hatfield1
-
23
-
-
34249960669
-
Descartes and Some Predecessors on the Divine Conservation of Motion
-
and Stephen Menn, "Descartes and Some Predecessors on the Divine Conservation of Motion," Synthese 83 [1990]: 215-38), the contents of those volitions, the volitions themselves, the regularities in nature resulting from the volitions, or nature itself insofar as it is empowered by the volitions. Descartes does not distinguish these, and uses "laws" variably to refer to most or all of them. It is no surprise, then, that he does not distinguish between GC and PC.
-
(1990)
Synthese
, vol.83
, pp. 215-238
-
-
Menn, S.1
-
25
-
-
60949705595
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press chs. 2 and 3
-
(i) Descartes offers no explicit statements of such laws (not that he should be expected to); (ii) it is unclear how such laws would be framed, for the ontologically basic variables concerning mind and its modes are not apparent (see Tad Schmaltz, Malebranche's Theory of the Soul [New York: Oxford University Press, 1996], chs. 2 and 3);
-
(1996)
Malebranche's Theory of the Soul
-
-
Schmaltz, T.1
-
26
-
-
34247209190
-
God's General Concurrence with Secondary Causes: Why Conservation is Not Enough
-
J. Tomberlin, ed, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company
-
There are also numerous technical differences between the different scholastic versions of concurrentism (cf. Alfred Freddoso, "God's General Concurrence with Secondary Causes: Why Conservation is Not Enough," in Philosophical Perspectives, 5: Philosophy of Religion, J. Tomberlin, ed. [Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company, 1991], 553-86), which we may ignore here. For further discussion of scholastic concurrentism, see work already cited by Van Ruler, Des Chene, and Hattab.
-
(1991)
Philosophical Perspectives, 5: Philosophy of Religion
, pp. 553-586
-
-
Freddoso, A.1
-
28
-
-
61349168750
-
God's General Concurrence with Secondary Causes: Pitfalls and Prospects
-
Cf. Alfred Freddoso, "God's General Concurrence with Secondary Causes: Pitfalls and Prospects," American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 68 (1994): [For concurrentists] . . . God's mode of acting when He concurs with secondary causes must be distinct from any mode of acting in which He produces an effect by Himself, without the cooperation of secondary causes (145). . . . when God concurs with a secondary agent to produce a given effect, God's immediate causal contribution and the secondary agent's immediate causal contribution are complementary, with neither rendering the other superfluous . . . Yet St. Thomas explicitly denies that an effect produced jointly by God and creatures is a conjunction of two independently produced per se effects: '. . . Rather, the whole [effect] is effected by both [God and the secondary cause] according to different modes' . . . In short, the effect is undivided and yet such that both its universal or general cause (God) and its particular causes . . . contribute to its production in distinctive and non-redundant modes . . . (145-7). . . . God and the secondary cause constitute a single total cause that produces the relevant unitary effect by means of a single, undivided, action. . . . (154-5)
-
(1994)
American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.68
-
-
Freddoso, A.1
-
29
-
-
80053859472
-
-
Molesworth, ed. London 48
-
Even where the laws a ated in a universal form not explicitly conditional, it was not uncommon at the time to treat such propositions as equivalent to conditionals; although Descartes's minimal interest in logic results in his not discussing the issue, see (for example), Hobbes, Opera Philosophica quae Latine scripsit omnia, Molesworth, ed. (London, 1839-45), I, 34-5, 48;
-
(1839)
Opera Philosophica quae Latine scripsit omnia
, vol.1
, pp. 34-35
-
-
Hobbes1
-
30
-
-
0003951260
-
-
P. Remnant and J. Bennett, trans. and eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Leibniz, New Essays on Human Understanding, P. Remnant and J. Bennett, trans. and eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), IV.xi;
-
(1982)
New Essays on Human Understanding
-
-
Leibniz1
-
32
-
-
80053846539
-
Discussing Leibnizian concurrence, Robert Adams
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Discussing Leibnizian concurrence, Robert Adams, in Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994) puts it well: God produces the creature's producing (97-8). In our idiom, given God's volitions, God causes the creature to cause motion by virtue of its states.
-
(1994)
Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist
-
-
-
34
-
-
0040869152
-
Descartes and Occasionalism
-
University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press
-
and "Descartes and Occasionalism," in Causation in Early Modern Philosophy, S. Nadler, ed. [University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993], who sees Descartes as inclining towards occasionalism in dispensing with an earlier reference to bodily "active faculties," but who ignores the thorough causal context of the passage);
-
(1993)
Causation in Early Modern Philosophy
-
-
Nadler, S.1
-
35
-
-
60949207747
-
Mind-Body Interaction and Metaphysical Consistency: A Defense of Descartes
-
see also Eileen O'Neill, "Mind-Body Interaction and Metaphysical Consistency: A Defense of Descartes," Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (1987): 227-45,
-
(1987)
Journal of the History of Philosophy
, vol.25
, pp. 227-245
-
-
O'Neill, E.1
-
36
-
-
60949149939
-
Sensation, Occasionalism, and Descartes' Causal Principles
-
P. Cummins and G. Zoeller, eds. (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishin pany
-
and Tad Schmaltz, "Sensation, Occasionalism, and Descartes' Causal Principles," in Minds, Ideas, and Objects: Essays on the Theory of Representation in Modern Philosophy, P. Cummins and G. Zoeller, eds. (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishin pany, 1992).
-
(1992)
Minds, Ideas, and Objects: Essays on the Theory of Representation in Modern Philosophy
-
-
Schmaltz, T.1
-
37
-
-
80053808872
-
Causality and Explanation in Descartes' Natural Philosophy
-
Columbus: The Ohio State University Press, Machamer P., Turnbull R
-
Others also seem to read Descartes as Clatterbaugh does, explicitly or implicitly, offering additional evidence: Peter Machamer, "Causality and Explanation in Descartes' Natural Philosophy," in Motion and Time, Space and Matter, P. Machamer and R. Turnbull, eds. (Columbus: The Ohio State University Press, 1976), 168-99;
-
(1976)
Motion and Time, Space and Matter
, pp. 168-199
-
-
Machamer, P.1
-
39
-
-
0004010110
-
-
University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press
-
and Descartes' Philosophy of Science (University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1982);
-
(1982)
Descartes' Philosophy of Science
-
-
-
40
-
-
80053836818
-
First Philosophy and Natural Philosophy in Descartes
-
A. J. Holland, ed, Dordrecht: D. Reidel
-
and Gary Hatfield, "First Philosophy and Natural Philosophy in Descartes," in Philosophy: Its History and Historiography, A. J. Holland, ed. (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1985), 149-64.
-
(1985)
Philosophy: Its History and Historiography
, pp. 149-164
-
-
Hatfield, G.1
-
41
-
-
0039430520
-
How God Causes Motion: Descartes, Divine Sustenance, and Occasionalism
-
and "How God Causes Motion: Descartes, Divine Sustenance, and Occasionalism," Journal of Philosophy 84 (1987): 567-80-while not explicitly addressing concurrence, also seems to commit him to understanding concurrence this way.
-
(1987)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.84
, pp. 567-580
-
-
-
43
-
-
61249330267
-
Medieval Aristotelianism and the Case Against Secondary Causation in Nature
-
T. Morris, ed. (Ithaca: Cornell University Press
-
and in addition to his already cited works, Alfred Freddoso, "Medieval Aristotelianism and the Case Against Secondary Causation in Nature," in Divine and Human Action, T. Morris, ed. (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988), 74-118. Although Garber does not explicitly make this error, his interpretation of Descartes's physics seems committed to it. Van Ruler is less clear: he seems to infer occasionalism from the identification of concurrence with conservation, but then admits ". . . there is reason to assume that Descartes accepted a distinct causality of secondary causes . . ." (276, n. 47).
-
(1988)
Divine and Human Action
, pp. 74-118
-
-
Freddoso, A.1
-
44
-
-
80053777202
-
-
Descartes's conception of a finite cause, for example, is broader than a typical scholastic one (see parts 3 and 4). Also, see Garber, "How God Causes Motion," 573, for differences between Descartes's and Aquinas's conceptions of conservation.
-
How God Causes Motion
, pp. 573
-
-
Garber1
-
45
-
-
80053722543
-
-
Of course this conception coheres with Clatterbaugh's and others' mentioned in part 2. There may be other important constraints on Descartes's conception of a cause, including what O'Neill, in "Mind-Body Interaction," refers to as t ntainment and reality principles (see also Schmaltz, "Sensation, Occasionalism, and Descartes' Causal Principles,"
-
Sensation, Occasionalism, and Descartes' Causal Principles
-
-
Schmaltz1
-
47
-
-
80053869192
-
Gorham's paper appears in Dialogue: Canadian
-
Gorham's paper appears in Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, vol. 42, no. 1, 2001).
-
(2001)
Philosophical Review
, vol.42
, Issue.1
-
-
-
48
-
-
60949950257
-
Descartes on Mind-Body Interaction and the Conservation of Motion
-
Cf. Peter McLaughlin, "Descartes on Mind-Body Interaction and the Conservation of Motion," Philosophical Review 102 (1993): 155-82.
-
(1993)
Philosophical Review
, vol.102
, pp. 155-182
-
-
Peter McLaughlin, C.1
-
50
-
-
0004131595
-
-
London: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co
-
refers to C. D. Broad, Mind and Its Place in Nature (London: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co., 1925) as holding this interpretation, then quickly dismisses it.
-
(1925)
Mind and Its Place in Nature
-
-
Broad, C.D.1
-
52
-
-
84859300814
-
The Concept of Vis in Part III of the Principia
-
Napoli: Vivarium
-
For related discussion, see Clarke, "The Concept of Vis in Part III of the Principia," in Descartes: Principia Philosophiae (1644-1994) (Napoli: Vivarium, 1994), 331,
-
(1994)
Descartes: Principia Philosophiae (1644-1994)
, pp. 331
-
-
Clarke1
-
54
-
-
0009863365
-
God and Nature in the Thought of Robert Boyle
-
For what is ultimately a similar interpretation of Boyle, see Timothy Shanahan, "God and Nature in the Thought of Robert Boyle," Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (1988): 547-70,
-
(1988)
Journal of the History of Philosophy
, vol.26
, pp. 547-570
-
-
Shanahan, T.1
-
55
-
-
0042208763
-
Boyle on Occasionalism: An Unexamined Source
-
and Peter Anstey, "Boyle on Occasionalism: An Unexamined Source," Journal of the History of Ideas, 60 (1999): 57-81.
-
(1999)
Journal of the History of Ideas
, vol.60
, pp. 57-81
-
-
Anstey, P.1
-
57
-
-
80053793624
-
-
As a result, there is no reason here to rule out Thomistic instrumentalism. In light of what I said about pure deductions above, instrumentalism is consistent even with Clatterbaugh's conception of concurrence, and is not an alternative to it, as he suggests ("Cartesian Causality," 202).
-
Cartesian Causality
, pp. 202
-
-
-
59
-
-
0347641532
-
-
316ff
-
Cf. Des Chene, in Physiologia, 316ff., who discusses using the eternality of divine volitions to reconcile divine immutability with the variability of the effects of divine action.
-
Physiologia
-
-
Des Chene, C.1
|