메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 108, Issue 4, 1998, Pages 719-745

Civic Education and Liberal Legitimacy

(1)  Brighouse, Harry a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0344022584     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233849     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (149)

References (62)
  • 1
    • 0004031772 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1987) Democratic Education
    • Gutmann, A.1
  • 2
    • 84937295250 scopus 로고
    • Civic Education and Social Diversity
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1995) Ethics , vol.105 , pp. 557-579
  • 3
    • 0003925898 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1990) Liberal Virtues
    • Macedo, S.1
  • 4
    • 58149478781 scopus 로고
    • Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1995) Ethics , vol.105 , pp. 468-496
  • 5
    • 84863972926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Liberalism and Political Education
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1996) Review of Politics , vol.58 , pp. 5-33
    • Callan, E.1
  • 6
    • 0003740324 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1987) Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community
    • Lomasky, L.1
  • 7
    • 0003750156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1992) Liberal Purposes
    • Galston, W.1
  • 8
    • 84916947233 scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Liberalism
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1995) Ethics , vol.105 , pp. 516-534
  • 9
    • 84959649671 scopus 로고
    • Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1994) Review of Politics , vol.56 , pp. 51-70
    • Burtt, S.1
  • 10
    • 0141981729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools
    • New York: New York University Press
    • On the side of teaching autonomy, see Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987), and "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995): 557-79; Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), and "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?" Ethics 105 (1995): 468-96; Eamonn Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," Review of Politics 58 (1996): 5-33; and against, see Loren Lomasky, Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987); William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995): 516-34. For a liberal who rejects both civic education and autonomy-facilitating education, see Shelley Burtt, "Religious Parents, Secular Schools: A Liberal Defence of an Illiberal Education." Review of Politics 56 (1994): 51-70, and "In Defense of Yoder: Parental Authority and the Public Schools," in NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin (New York: New York University Press, 1996), pp. 412-37.
    • (1996) NOMOS XXXVIII: Political Order , pp. 412-437
    • Shapiro, I.1    Hardin, R.2
  • 11
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 137. Rawls appears to think that constitutions could be legitimate while failing to implement his theory of justice: see his "The Law of Peoples" in On Human Rights, ed. Steven Shute and Susan Hurley (New York: Basic Books, 1993), pp. 41-82. For criticism of Rawls's view expressed in that paper, see Darrell Moellendorf, "Rethinking the Law of Peoples," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (1996): 132-54.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 137
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 12
    • 0002923507 scopus 로고
    • The Law of Peoples
    • New York: Basic Books
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 137. Rawls appears to think that constitutions could be legitimate while failing to implement his theory of justice: see his "The Law of Peoples" in On Human Rights, ed. Steven Shute and Susan Hurley (New York: Basic Books, 1993), pp. 41-82. For criticism of Rawls's view expressed in that paper, see Darrell Moellendorf, "Rethinking the Law of Peoples," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (1996): 132-54.
    • (1993) On Human Rights , pp. 41-82
    • Shute, S.1    Hurley, S.2
  • 13
    • 0002188877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking the Law of Peoples
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 137. Rawls appears to think that constitutions could be legitimate while failing to implement his theory of justice: see his "The Law of Peoples" in On Human Rights, ed. Steven Shute and Susan Hurley (New York: Basic Books, 1993), pp. 41-82. For criticism of Rawls's view expressed in that paper, see Darrell Moellendorf, "Rethinking the Law of Peoples," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (1996): 132-54.
    • (1996) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.77 , pp. 132-154
    • Moellendorf, D.1
  • 20
    • 0003750156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (emphasis added); courage is "the willingness to fight and die for one's country" (p. 221)
    • Galston, Liberal Purposes, pp. 222, 223, 224, 221 (emphasis added); courage is "the willingness to fight and die for one's country" (p. 221).
    • Liberal Purposes , pp. 222
    • Galston1
  • 22
    • 21344485987 scopus 로고
    • Beyond Sentimental Civic Education
    • For an excellent and far more detailed critique of Galston's civic education, see Eamonn Callan, "Beyond Sentimental Civic Education," American Journal of Education 102 (1994): 190-221. Callan focuses not on the problems for liberal legitimacy but on the moral problems with this sort of education, and the possibility of providing a nonsentimentalizing civic education which engages citizens in public life.
    • (1994) American Journal of Education , vol.102 , pp. 190-221
    • Callan, E.1
  • 25
    • 0030544354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Egalitarianism and Equal Availability of Political Influence
    • Gutmann's civic republicanism is not essential for radically egalitarian democracy. Consider the analogy with equality of resources. Egalitarians say that all should have available roughly equal resources, but would not say that all should consume the resources available to them: those who prefer to consume less than equality gives them may do so. Similarly, one can say that all citizens should have available roughly equal influence, without advocating that all citizens should take up the equal influence available to them. Radical democracy privileges politics as a sphere of activity because it advocates a principled insulation of the distribution of political power from the distribution of other goods, but it does not necessarily require citizens to use that power. See my "Egalitarianism and Equal Availability of Political Influence," Journal of Political Philosophy 4 (1996): 118-41.
    • (1996) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.4 , pp. 118-141
  • 26
    • 0345812156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Egalitarians and School Choice
    • The following argument appears in very truncated form in my "Liberal Egalitarians and School Choice," Politics and Society 22 (1996): 457-86, p. 465. See also Ian Shapiro, Democracy's Place (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1996), pp. 167-71 (in a chapter co- authored with Richard Arneson) for a similar argument.
    • (1996) Politics and Society , vol.22 , pp. 457-486
  • 27
    • 85033929140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, (in a chapter co-authored with Richard Arneson) for a similar argument
    • The following argument appears in very truncated form in my "Liberal Egalitarians and School Choice," Politics and Society 22 (1996): 457-86, p. 465. See also Ian Shapiro, Democracy's Place (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1996), pp. 167-71 (in a chapter co-authored with Richard Arneson) for a similar argument.
    • (1996) Democracy's Place , pp. 167-171
    • Shapiro, I.1
  • 28
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), pp. 369-70.
    • (1987) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 369-370
    • Raz, J.1
  • 30
    • 0004022577 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, for an elaboration of the idea of living a life from the inside
    • See Will Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 80-84 for an elaboration of the idea of living a life from the inside.
    • (1995) Multicultural Citizenship , pp. 80-84
    • Kymlicka, W.1
  • 31
    • 85033906531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It might be objected that this notion of living well unacceptably demotes unchosen commitments - e.g., commitments to the welfare of our parents or other relatives. I think that is wrong: whether one lives well in carrying out such commitments depends not on rationally choosing them, but on whether the obligations flowing from them are accepted "from the inside." The obligations are undertaken from the inside if the agent identifies with them. She does not live well if she undertakes them with deep resentment and anger, even if what she is doing is good. But she can live well consistent with undertaking them, without choosing them or the commitments from which they flow.
  • 32
    • 0010016004 scopus 로고
    • New York: Simon & Schuster, for an account of Mozert v. Hawkins, in which parents demanded that textbooks teaching, among other things, that a central ideal of the Renaissance was a belief in the equal worth of all human beings, be removed from the school. The Mozert parents, like the Amish parents in Wisconsin v. Yoder, took the prospective autonomy of their children as a threat to their continued adherence to their religion
    • See Stephen Bates, Battleground: One Mother's Crusade, the Religious Right, and the Struggle for Control of Our Classrooms (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1993) for an account of Mozert v. Hawkins, in which parents demanded that textbooks teaching, among other things, that a central ideal of the Renaissance was a belief in the equal worth of all human beings, be removed from the school. The Mozert parents, like the Amish parents in Wisconsin v. Yoder, took the prospective autonomy of their children as a threat to their continued adherence to their religion.
    • (1993) Battleground: One Mother's Crusade, the Religious Right, and the Struggle for Control of Our Classrooms
    • Bates, S.1
  • 33
    • 85033917985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I owe this example to Laura Osinski, who helped me identify the different levels of abstraction relevant to my argument.
  • 34
    • 85033930436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In the case of children, furthermore, it is not clear that the principle of equal opportunity even permits inequalities arising from choices.
  • 35
    • 85033904255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thanks to Jocelyn Johnson for this example
    • Thanks to Jocelyn Johnson for this example.
  • 36
    • 85033903713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I doubt that homosexuality would be a way of life in nonoppressive circumstances, any more than heterosexuality is in most contemporary societies: but in oppressive circumstances it sometimes is.
  • 37
    • 85033912823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for a detailed discussion of two texts that contribute to an education of the sort I am suggesting
    • See Callan, "Beyond Sentimental Civic Education," esp. pp. 205-14, for a detailed discussion of two texts that contribute to an education of the sort I am suggesting.
    • Beyond Sentimental Civic Education , pp. 205-214
    • Callan1
  • 38
    • 0004001518 scopus 로고
    • New York: Norton
    • As Mill says of adults, "Nor is it enough that he should hear the arguments of adversaries from his own teachers, presented as they state them, and accompanied by what they offer as refutations. That is not the way to do justice to the arguments, or bring them into real contact with his own mind. He must be able to hear them from persons who actually believe them; who defend them in earnest and do their very utmost for them." John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (New York: Norton, 1975), p. 36.
    • (1975) On Liberty , pp. 36
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 39
    • 85033919953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There may be reasons that children should be taught these virtues. The instrumental argument does not provide them.
  • 40
    • 0003565839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Doubleday, chap. 2
    • Although I have focused on the "skills associated with autonomy" I am skeptical that any cognitive skills can be taught without teaching knowledge. See E. D. Hirsch, Jr., The Schools We Need and Why We Don't Have Them (New York: Doubleday, 1996), chap. 2.
    • (1996) The Schools We Need and Why We Don't Have Them
    • Hirsch E.D., Jr.1
  • 41
    • 85033905460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I have not shown that autonomy facilitation is all that is owed to children and am open to the possibility that autonomy should be actively promoted. However, the considerations I invoke concerning legitimacy, while they do suggest that critical reflection on the values underlying social institutions should be actively encouraged, make me uneasy about active encouragement of autonomy.
  • 42
    • 85033920024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thanks to Erik Olin Wright and an editor of Ethics for pointing out these difficulties.
  • 43
    • 85033911574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I'm grateful to Shelley Burtt for forcing me to make a number of distinctions I had hitherto missed in this and the ensuing paragraphs.
  • 45
    • 0004105957 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Some examples of the first kind of argument can be found in Charles Fried, Right and Wrong (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1976); Galston, Liberal Purposes; and Lomasky. I discuss them in my "School Choice: Some Theoretical Considerations," in Samuel Bowles, Herbert Gintis et al., Recasting Egalitarianism: New Rules for Equity and Accountability through Markets, Communities, and Governments (London: Verso, 1998), in press.
    • (1976) Right and Wrong
    • Fried, C.1
  • 46
    • 85033905211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some examples of the first kind of argument can be found in Charles Fried, Right and Wrong (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1976); Galston, Liberal Purposes; and Lomasky. I discuss them in my "School Choice: Some Theoretical Considerations," in Samuel Bowles, Herbert Gintis et al., Recasting Egalitarianism: New Rules for Equity and Accountability through Markets, Communities, and Governments (London: Verso, 1998), in press.
    • Liberal Purposes; and Lomasky
    • Galston1
  • 47
    • 0347073587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • School Choice: Some Theoretical Considerations
    • London: Verso, in press
    • Some examples of the first kind of argument can be found in Charles Fried, Right and Wrong (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1976); Galston, Liberal Purposes; and Lomasky. I discuss them in my "School Choice: Some Theoretical Considerations," in Samuel Bowles, Herbert Gintis et al., Recasting Egalitarianism: New Rules for Equity and Accountability through Markets, Communities, and Governments (London: Verso, 1998), in press.
    • (1998) Recasting Egalitarianism: New Rules for Equity and Accountability Through Markets, Communities, and Governments
    • Bowles, S.1    Gintis, H.2
  • 48
    • 0007365420 scopus 로고
    • Democracy at National and Workplace Levels
    • ed. David Copp, Jean Hampton, and John Roemer Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, gives a nice statement of this view
    • Richard Arneson, "Democracy at National and Workplace Levels," in The Idea of Democracy, ed. David Copp, Jean Hampton, and John Roemer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), gives a nice statement of this view.
    • (1991) The Idea of Democracy
    • Arneson, R.1
  • 49
    • 85007409178 scopus 로고
    • Neutrality, Publicity, and State Funding of the Arts
    • I discuss the possibility that neutrality must be seen to be done in "Neutrality, Publicity, and State Funding of the Arts," Philosophy and Public Affairs 24 (1995): 36-63.
    • (1995) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.24 , pp. 36-63
  • 50
    • 0345812157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," esp. pp. 22-23. Callan's more general argument is that political liberalism is in fact "a kind of closet ethical liberalism" (p. 22), and that the distinction between political liberalism and ethical (or comprehensive) liberalisms is thus of limited interest. make a similar argument in "Is There Any Such Thing as Political Liberalism?" Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 75 (1994): 318-32.
    • Political Liberalism and Political Education , pp. 22-23
    • Callan1
  • 51
    • 0346443419 scopus 로고
    • Is There Any Such Thing as Political Liberalism?
    • Callan, "Political Liberalism and Political Education," esp. pp. 22-23. Callan's more general argument is that political liberalism is in fact "a kind of closet ethical liberalism" (p. 22), and that the distinction between political liberalism and ethical (or comprehensive) liberalisms is thus of limited interest. make a similar argument in "Is There Any Such Thing as Political Liberalism?" Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 75 (1994): 318-32.
    • (1994) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.75 , pp. 318-332
  • 53
    • 0347704138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Children need a moral and sentimental education: we owe them an upbringing that provides the material and psychological resources that allow for a full and flourishing human life."
    • Burtt, "In Defense of Yoder," pp. 425, 426; and see p. 428: "Children need a moral and sentimental education: we owe them an upbringing that provides the material and psychological resources that allow for a full and flourishing human life."
    • In Defense of Yoder , pp. 425
    • Burtt1
  • 55
    • 85033932766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Gutmann's recommendations would, in my view, be likely to have similar effects, but that is not part of her aim.
  • 58
    • 84875609191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls makes a similar point: "It may be objected that requiring children to understand the political conception in these ways is, in effect, though not in intention, to educate them in a comprehensive liberal conception. Doing the one may lead to the other, if only because once we know the one we may of our own accord go on to the other. It must be granted that this may indeed happen in the case of some" (Political Liberalism, pp. 199-200).
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 199-200
  • 61
    • 85033922521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Education, Diversity, and the State
    • (in press), that most of the charges laid against deeply religious parents by participants in the mainstream have direct reciprocal analogues (I would be as horrified if my daughter became Amish as an Amish parent would be if her son became a liberal socialist). The desirability of permeability between ways of life seems an exception: religious parents would not welcome more permeability because it would make their children more likely to leave, whereas many secular parents would welcome more permeability even if it raised the probability of their children leaving
    • Francis Schrag points out, in "Education, Diversity, and the State," Studies in Philosophy and Education (in press), that most of the charges laid against deeply religious parents by participants in the mainstream have direct reciprocal analogues (I would be as horrified if my daughter became Amish as an Amish parent would be if her son became a liberal socialist). The desirability of permeability between ways of life seems an exception: religious parents would not welcome more permeability because it would make their children more likely to leave, whereas many secular parents would welcome more permeability even if it raised the probability of their children leaving.
    • Studies in Philosophy and Education
    • Schrag, F.1
  • 62
    • 85033918583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to Randall Blumenstein for raising this issue with me
    • I am grateful to Randall Blumenstein for raising this issue with me.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.