메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 64, Issue 1, 2003, Pages 119-134

Freedom and Autonomy in Schiller

(1)  Roehr, Sabine a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0141768139     PISSN: 00225037     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3654299     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (28)

References (83)
  • 2
    • 84975018472 scopus 로고
    • Schiller on the Will and the Heroic Villain
    • See, W. M. Calder, "Schiller on the Will and the Heroic Villain," Oxford German Studies, 2, (1967), 41-53; Paul Menzer, "Schiller und Kant. Zum 150. Todestage Friedrich von Schillers am 9. Mai 1955," Kant-Studien, 47, (1955/56), 113-47, 234-72; R. D. Miller, Schiller and the Ideal of Freedom: A Study of Schiller's Philosophical Works with Chapters on Kant (Oxford, 1970).
    • (1967) Oxford German Studies , vol.2 , pp. 41-53
    • Calder, W.M.1
  • 3
    • 0141858680 scopus 로고
    • Schiller und Kant. Zum 150. Todestage Friedrich von Schillers am 9. Mai 1955
    • See, W. M. Calder, "Schiller on the Will and the Heroic Villain," Oxford German Studies, 2, (1967), 41-53; Paul Menzer, "Schiller und Kant. Zum 150. Todestage Friedrich von Schillers am 9. Mai 1955," Kant-Studien, 47, (1955/56), 113-47, 234-72; R. D. Miller, Schiller and the Ideal of Freedom: A Study of Schiller's Philosophical Works with Chapters on Kant (Oxford, 1970).
    • (1955) Kant-Studien , vol.47 , pp. 113-147
    • Menzer, P.1
  • 5
    • 0141635153 scopus 로고
    • Beauty and Freedom: Schiller's Struggle with Kant's Aesthetics
    • ed. Ted Cohen and Paul Guyer (Chicago)
    • Dieter Henrich, "Beauty and Freedom: Schiller's Struggle with Kant's Aesthetics," Essays in Kant's Aesthetics, ed. Ted Cohen and Paul Guyer (Chicago, 1982); Lesley Sharpe, "Schiller's Aesthetic Letters: A Theory of Beauty in a Revolutionary Age," talk given at a workshop on Schiller's Aesthetic Letters in January 1999 at the Institute of Germanic Studies, London.
    • (1982) Essays in Kant's Aesthetics
    • Henrich, D.1
  • 6
    • 85009046366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dieter Henrich, "Beauty and Freedom: Schiller's Struggle with Kant's Aesthetics," Essays in Kant's Aesthetics, ed. Ted Cohen and Paul Guyer (Chicago, 1982); Lesley Sharpe, "Schiller's Aesthetic Letters: A Theory of Beauty in a Revolutionary Age," talk given at a workshop on Schiller's Aesthetic Letters in January 1999 at the Institute of Germanic Studies, London.
    • Schiller's Aesthetic Letters: A Theory of Beauty in a Revolutionary Age
    • Sharpe, L.1
  • 7
    • 0141858690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in January, at the Institute of Germanic Studies, London
    • Dieter Henrich, "Beauty and Freedom: Schiller's Struggle with Kant's Aesthetics," Essays in Kant's Aesthetics, ed. Ted Cohen and Paul Guyer (Chicago, 1982); Lesley Sharpe, "Schiller's Aesthetic Letters: A Theory of Beauty in a Revolutionary Age," talk given at a workshop on Schiller's Aesthetic Letters in January 1999 at the Institute of Germanic Studies, London.
    • (1999) Aesthetic Letters
    • Schiller1
  • 11
    • 0004118035 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Kant introduces the concept of "heautonomy" in the introduction to his Critique of Judgment. Apparently, he made it up in order to distinguish between moral autonomy and the particular autonomy of the faculty of judgment that judges nature according to a subjective principle of purposiveness. "The judgment has therefore also in itself a principle a priori of the possibility of nature, but only in a subjective aspect, by which it prescribes not to nature (autonomy), but to itself (heautonomy) a law for its reflection upon nature." See Critique of Judgement, tr. J. H. Bernhard (London, 1951), 22. The added prefix "he," as in the Greek "heauton," is probably meant to draw attention to the purely reflexive character of such law.
    • (1951) Critique of Judgement , pp. 22
    • Bernhard, J.H.1
  • 12
    • 85009055899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kallias-Briefe, 47. See also Ernst Cassirer, Freiheit und Form: Studien zur deutschen Geistesgeschichte (Darmstadt, 1961), 286.
    • Kallias-Briefe , pp. 47
  • 16
    • 0141524045 scopus 로고
    • Die ästhetische Vernunft: Bemerkungen zu Schillers 'Kallias' mit Bezug auf die Ästhetik des 18. Jahrhunderts
    • ed. Klaus Berghahn (Kronberg)
    • See Sigbert Latzel "Die ästhetische Vernunft: Bemerkungen zu Schillers 'Kallias' mit Bezug auf die Ästhetik des 18. Jahrhunderts," Friedrich Schiller: Zur Geschichtlichkeit seines Werkes, ed. Klaus Berghahn (Kronberg, 1975), 247.
    • (1975) Friedrich Schiller: Zur Geschichtlichkeit Seines Werkes , pp. 247
    • Latzel, S.1
  • 19
    • 84877705925 scopus 로고
    • Briefe über die Kantische Philosophie
    • (Weimar), III and (Weimar, 1787), I, II, III
    • Briefe über die Kantische Philosophie, in Der Teutsche Merkur (Weimar, 1786), III and (Weimar, 1787), I, II, III.
    • (1786) Der Teutsche Merkur
  • 21
    • 0141635137 scopus 로고
    • Letter 97, to Körner, Weimar, 29 August 1787, ed. Benno von Wiese (Weimar)
    • Letter 97, to Körner, Weimar, 29 August 1787. Schillers Werke Nationalausgabe (NA), XXIV, ed. Benno von Wiese (Weimar, 1963), 143.
    • (1963) Schillers Werke Nationalausgabe (NA) , vol.24 , pp. 143
  • 25
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고
    • tr. Norman Kemp Smith (London)
    • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, tr. Norman Kemp Smith (London, 1933), A533/B561.
    • (1933) Critique of Pure Reason
    • Kant, I.1
  • 27
    • 0004011977 scopus 로고
    • tr. and intro. L. W. Beck (London), [440], (page numbers in brackets refer to the Akademie-Ausgabe)
    • Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, tr. and intro. L. W. Beck (London, 1959), [440], 59 (page numbers in brackets refer to the Akademie-Ausgabe).
    • (1959) Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals , pp. 59
    • Kant1
  • 29
    • 0004183724 scopus 로고
    • tr. and intro. L. W. Beck (London), [32]
    • Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, tr. and intro. L. W. Beck (London, 1956), [32], 32.
    • (1956) Critique of Practical Reason , pp. 32
    • Kant1
  • 31
    • 85009049676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Through the criticisms of J. A. H. Ulrich and C. C. E. Schmid
    • Through the criticisms of J. A. H. Ulrich and C. C. E. Schmid.
  • 32
    • 0003411955 scopus 로고
    • tr. John Silber (New York), BA7/ 17.I changed the translation of "Willkür" from "will" to "choice"
    • Kant, Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone, tr. John Silber (New York, 1960), BA7/ 17.I changed the translation of "Willkür" from "will" to "choice."
    • (1960) Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone
    • Kant1
  • 33
  • 40
    • 0004291536 scopus 로고
    • [Cambridge], [226]
    • Kant's answer in The Metaphysics of Morals to his critics contains some surprising, if only apparent, similarities between his and Reinhold's accounts of freedom and will. Kant, for the first time, explicitly separates the will (Wille) from choice (Willkür), reminiscent of Reinhold's distinct capacities of practical reason and free will. The will now gives the laws and thus "cannot be called either free or unfree, since it is not directed to actions immediately but immediately to giving laws for the maxims of actions (and is, therefore, practical reason itself). Hence the will directs with absolute necessity and is itself subject to no necessitation. Only choice can therefore be free." (Metaphysics of Morals, tr., notes Mary Gregor [Cambridge, 1991], [226], 52). But then Kant immediately proceeds to disclaim the possibility of a theoretical concept of free choice. "But freedom of choice cannot be defined - as some have tried to define it - as the capacity to make a choice for or against the law (libertas indifferentiae), even though choice as & phenomenon provides frequent examples of this experience" (ibid.). The "some" obviously refers to Reinhold, and this is Kant's last word on the matter: free choice cannot be defined as a separate capacity; he even characterizes it as an "incapacity" "Only freedom in relation to the internal lawgiving of reason is really a capacity; the possibility of deviation from it is an incapacity" (Ibid., [227], 52). Thus, Kant was clearly aware of the intentional, self-determinational aspects of heteronomous acting, but he could not accommodate it within the strict dualism of autonomy and heteronomy, freedom and natural causality. I will forgo discussing here Reinhold's answer to Kant in his "Einige Bemerkungen über die in der Einleitung zu den metaphysischen Anfangsgründen der Rechtslehre von I. Kant aufgestellten Begriffe von der Freiheit des Willens," Auswahl vermischer Schriften, vol. 2 (Jena, 1797).
    • (1991) Metaphysics of Morals , pp. 52
    • Gregor, M.1
  • 41
    • 84903352312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's answer in The Metaphysics of Morals to his critics contains some surprising, if only apparent, similarities between his and Reinhold's accounts of freedom and will. Kant, for the first time, explicitly separates the will (Wille) from choice (Willkür), reminiscent of Reinhold's distinct capacities of practical reason and free will. The will now gives the laws and thus "cannot be called either free or unfree, since it is not directed to actions immediately but immediately to giving laws for the maxims of actions (and is, therefore, practical reason itself). Hence the will directs with absolute necessity and is itself subject to no necessitation. Only choice can therefore be free." (Metaphysics of Morals, tr., notes Mary Gregor [Cambridge, 1991], [226], 52). But then Kant immediately proceeds to disclaim the possibility of a theoretical concept of free choice. "But freedom of choice cannot be defined - as some have tried to define it - as the capacity to make a choice for or against the law (libertas indifferentiae), even though choice as & phenomenon provides frequent examples of this experience" (ibid.). The "some" obviously refers to Reinhold, and this is Kant's last word on the matter: free choice cannot be defined as a separate capacity; he even characterizes it as an "incapacity" "Only freedom in relation to the internal lawgiving of reason is really a capacity; the possibility of deviation from it is an incapacity" (Ibid., [227], 52). Thus, Kant was clearly aware of the intentional, self-determinational aspects of heteronomous acting, but he could not accommodate it within the strict dualism of autonomy and heteronomy, freedom and natural causality. I will forgo discussing here Reinhold's answer to Kant in his "Einige Bemerkungen über die in der Einleitung zu den metaphysischen Anfangsgründen der Rechtslehre von I. Kant aufgestellten Begriffe von der Freiheit des Willens," Auswahl vermischer Schriften, vol. 2 (Jena, 1797).
    • Metaphysics of Morals
  • 42
    • 84903352312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [227]
    • Kant's answer in The Metaphysics of Morals to his critics contains some surprising, if only apparent, similarities between his and Reinhold's accounts of freedom and will. Kant, for the first time, explicitly separates the will (Wille) from choice (Willkür), reminiscent of Reinhold's distinct capacities of practical reason and free will. The will now gives the laws and thus "cannot be called either free or unfree, since it is not directed to actions immediately but immediately to giving laws for the maxims of actions (and is, therefore, practical reason itself). Hence the will directs with absolute necessity and is itself subject to no necessitation. Only choice can therefore be free." (Metaphysics of Morals, tr., notes Mary Gregor [Cambridge, 1991], [226], 52). But then Kant immediately proceeds to disclaim the possibility of a theoretical concept of free choice. "But freedom of choice cannot be defined - as some have tried to define it - as the capacity to make a choice for or against the law (libertas indifferentiae), even though choice as & phenomenon provides frequent examples of this experience" (ibid.). The "some" obviously refers to Reinhold, and this is Kant's last word on the matter: free choice cannot be defined as a separate capacity; he even characterizes it as an "incapacity" "Only freedom in relation to the internal lawgiving of reason is really a capacity; the possibility of deviation from it is an incapacity" (Ibid., [227], 52). Thus, Kant was clearly aware of the intentional, self-determinational aspects of heteronomous acting, but he could not accommodate it within the strict dualism of autonomy and heteronomy, freedom and natural causality. I will forgo discussing here Reinhold's answer to Kant in his "Einige Bemerkungen über die in der Einleitung zu den metaphysischen Anfangsgründen der Rechtslehre von I. Kant aufgestellten Begriffe von der Freiheit des Willens," Auswahl vermischer Schriften, vol. 2 (Jena, 1797).
    • Metaphysics of Morals , pp. 52
  • 43
    • 0141858684 scopus 로고
    • Einige Bemerkungen über die in der Einleitung zu den metaphysischen Anfangsgründen der Rechtslehre von I. Kant aufgestellten Begriffe von der Freiheit des Willens
    • Jena
    • Kant's answer in The Metaphysics of Morals to his critics contains some surprising, if only apparent, similarities between his and Reinhold's accounts of freedom and will. Kant, for the first time, explicitly separates the will (Wille) from choice (Willkür), reminiscent of Reinhold's distinct capacities of practical reason and free will. The will now gives the laws and thus "cannot be called either free or unfree, since it is not directed to actions immediately but immediately to giving laws for the maxims of actions (and is, therefore, practical reason itself). Hence the will directs with absolute necessity and is itself subject to no necessitation. Only choice can therefore be free." (Metaphysics of Morals, tr., notes Mary Gregor [Cambridge, 1991], [226], 52). But then Kant immediately proceeds to disclaim the possibility of a theoretical concept of free choice. "But freedom of choice cannot be defined - as some have tried to define it - as the capacity to make a choice for or against the law (libertas indifferentiae), even though choice as & phenomenon provides frequent examples of this experience" (ibid.). The "some" obviously refers to Reinhold, and this is Kant's last word on the matter: free choice cannot be defined as a separate capacity; he even characterizes it as an "incapacity" "Only freedom in relation to the internal lawgiving of reason is really a capacity; the possibility of deviation from it is an incapacity" (Ibid., [227], 52). Thus, Kant was clearly aware of the intentional, self-determinational aspects of heteronomous acting, but he could not accommodate it within the strict dualism of autonomy and heteronomy, freedom and natural causality. I will forgo discussing here Reinhold's answer to Kant in his "Einige Bemerkungen über die in der Einleitung zu den metaphysischen Anfangsgründen der Rechtslehre von I. Kant aufgestellten Begriffe von der Freiheit des Willens," Auswahl vermischer Schriften, vol. 2 (Jena, 1797).
    • (1797) Auswahl Vermischer Schriften , vol.2
    • Kant1
  • 45
    • 84922061215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ästhetische Form als Darstellung der Subjektivität: Zur Rezeption Kantischer Begriffe in Schillers Ästhetik
    • ed. K. Berghahn
    • See Menzer and Wolfgang Düsing, in his "Ästhetische Form als Darstellung der Subjektivität: Zur Rezeption Kantischer Begriffe in Schillers Ästhetik," Friedrich Schiller: Zur Geschichtlichkeit seines Werkes, ed. K. Berghahn; and Jeffrey Barnouw in his " 'Freiheit zu geben durch Freiheit': Ästhetischer Zustand - Ästhetischer Staat," Friedrich Schiller: Kunst, Humanität und Politik in der späten Aufklärung. Ein Symposium, ed. W. Wittkowski (Tüingen, 1982). Schiller himself draws attention to it in his "Über Anmut und Würde."
    • Friedrich Schiller: Zur Geschichtlichkeit Seines Werkes
    • Menzer1    Düsing, W.2
  • 46
    • 0141524031 scopus 로고
    • 'Freiheit zu geben durch Freiheit': Ästhetischer Zustand - Ästhetischer Staat
    • ed. W. Wittkowski (Tüingen)
    • See Menzer and Wolfgang Düsing, in his "Ästhetische Form als Darstellung der Subjektivität: Zur Rezeption Kantischer Begriffe in Schillers Ästhetik," Friedrich Schiller: Zur Geschichtlichkeit seines Werkes, ed. K. Berghahn; and Jeffrey Barnouw in his " 'Freiheit zu geben durch Freiheit': Ästhetischer Zustand - Ästhetischer Staat," Friedrich Schiller: Kunst, Humanität und Politik in der späten Aufklärung. Ein Symposium, ed. W. Wittkowski (Tüingen, 1982). Schiller himself draws attention to it in his "Über Anmut und Würde."
    • (1982) Friedrich Schiller: Kunst, Humanität und Politik in der Späten Aufklärung. Ein Symposium
    • Barnouw, J.1
  • 47
    • 62449156517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Menzer and Wolfgang Düsing, in his "Ästhetische Form als Darstellung der Subjektivität: Zur Rezeption Kantischer Begriffe in Schillers Ästhetik," Friedrich Schiller: Zur Geschichtlichkeit seines Werkes, ed. K. Berghahn; and Jeffrey Barnouw in his " 'Freiheit zu geben durch Freiheit': Ästhetischer Zustand - Ästhetischer Staat," Friedrich Schiller: Kunst, Humanität und Politik in der späten Aufklärung. Ein Symposium, ed. W. Wittkowski (Tüingen, 1982). Schiller himself draws attention to it in his "Über Anmut und Würde."
    • Über Anmut und Würde
    • Schiller1
  • 48
    • 85009048519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zum Einfluß K. L. Reinholds auf Schillers Kant-Rezeption
    • ed. Wolfgang Schrader and Martin Bondeli (Stuttgart, forthcoming)
    • See Düsing and Sabine Röhr "Zum Einfluß K. L. Reinholds auf Schillers Kant-Rezeption," Proceedings of the International Karl Leonhard Reinhold Colloquium 1998, ed. Wolfgang Schrader and Martin Bondeli (Stuttgart, forthcoming).
    • Proceedings of the International Karl Leonhard Reinhold Colloquium 1998
    • Düsing1    Röhr, S.2
  • 49
    • 0141635132 scopus 로고
    • Letter 13, to Wolfgang Heribert von Dalberg. Stuttgart, 12 December
    • Letter 13, to Wolfgang Heribert von Dalberg. Stuttgart, 12 December 1781. NA, vol. 23, 26.
    • (1781) NA , vol.23 , pp. 26
  • 50
    • 84905821440 scopus 로고
    • On the Pathetic
    • ed. Walter Hinderer and Daniel O. Dahlstrom, tr. Dahlstrom (New York)
    • Schiller, "On the Pathetic," Friedrich Schiller. Essays, ed. Walter Hinderer and Daniel O. Dahlstrom, tr. Dahlstrom (New York, 1993), 64.
    • (1993) Friedrich Schiller. Essays , pp. 64
    • Schiller1
  • 52
    • 85009055898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Über den moralischen Nutzen ästhetischer Sitten
    • "On the moral usefulness of aesthetic manners/habits"
    • "Über den moralischen Nutzen ästhetischer Sitten," NA, vol. 21, 29. "On the moral usefulness of aesthetic manners/habits."
    • NA , vol.21 , pp. 29
  • 54
    • 85009052111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Reason possesses a very real reason to think freedom as an absolute cause - that is, self-consciousness, through which the acting of this faculty announces itself as a fact and through which it justifies common sense to make an inference from its reality to its possibility" (Briefe ũber die Kantische Philosophie, II, 511).
    • Briefe Ũber die Kantische Philosophie , vol.2 , pp. 511
  • 61
    • 85009051742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Except in the passage from The Metaphysics of Morals quoted above, where he calls practical reason neither free nor unfree
    • Except in the passage from The Metaphysics of Morals quoted above, where he calls practical reason neither free nor unfree.
  • 62
    • 77952164489 scopus 로고
    • Versuch einer neuen Theorie des Menschlichen Vorstellungsvermögens
    • Prague; repr. Darmstadt
    • Reinhold, Versuch einer neuen Theorie des menschlichen Vorstellungsvermögens (Attempt at a new theory of the human faculty of representation) (Prague, 1789; repr. Darmstadt, 1963), 561.
    • (1789) Attempt at a New Theory of the Human Faculty of Representation , pp. 561
    • Reinhold1
  • 63
    • 0141524042 scopus 로고
    • Schiller adopted this terminology in "On the Art of Tragedy" (1791/92). After this, he employed various terms. It is confirmed that he had read at least half of Reinhold's Versuch, a particularly dry, abstract work (see Reinhold's letter to Jens Baggesen, 23 January 1792).
    • (1791) On the Art of Tragedy
  • 64
    • 85009049672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schiller adopted this terminology in "On the Art of Tragedy" (1791/92). After this, he employed various terms. It is confirmed that he had read at least half of Reinhold's Versuch, a particularly dry, abstract work (see Reinhold's letter to Jens Baggesen, 23 January 1792).
    • Versuch
    • Reinhold1
  • 73
    • 85009049675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Alternatively, it could also be seen as Kant's theoretical concept of comparative freedom of choosing between different courses of action in accordance with theoretical, hypothetical considerations.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.