메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 39, Issue 4, 2001, Pages

What did mathematics do to physics?

(1)  Gingas, Yves a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0042696021     PISSN: 00732753     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (13)

References (255)
  • 3
    • 0042603366 scopus 로고
    • Galileo and the causes
    • R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), Dordrecht
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1978) New Perspectives on Galileo , pp. 161-180
    • Machamer, P.1
  • 4
    • 0038104291 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences
    • W. Wallace (ed.), Washington, D.C.
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1986) Reinterpreting Galileo , pp. 29-51
    • Lennox, J.G.1
  • 5
    • 85136431510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Galileo and the mixed sciences
    • Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Aldershot
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1997) Method and Order in the Renaissance Philosophy of Nature , pp. 253-270
    • Laird, W.R.1
  • 6
    • 0003987150 scopus 로고
    • Geneva
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1975) The Italian Renaissance of Mathematics
    • Rose, P.L.1
  • 7
    • 0004065718 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1995) Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution
    • Dear, P.1
  • 8
    • 0042102226 scopus 로고
    • Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la renaissance
    • Geneva
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1994) Comprendre et Maitriser la Nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'Histoire des Sciences Offerts à Guy Beaujouan , pp. 115-138
    • Mandosio, J.-M.1
  • 9
    • 84972208784 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's subordinate sciences
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1978) The British Journal for the History of Science , vol.11 , pp. 197-220
    • McKirahan, R.D.1
  • 10
    • 0010891251 scopus 로고
    • Leiden
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1995) Aristotle and Mathematics
    • Cleary, J.J.1
  • 11
    • 0042603357 scopus 로고
    • The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'
    • ii
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1991) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.1 , pp. 81-102
    • Brown, G.I.1
  • 12
    • 0043104162 scopus 로고
    • Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy
    • There is a considerably large literature on the mixed sciences, but, to my knowledge, there is still no general account of its extension to fields other than the canonical ones (Astronomy, Optics, Harmonics) as suggested here. For the case of Galileo, see Peter Machamer, "Galileo and the causes", in R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitts (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (Dordrecht, 1978), 161-80; James G. Lennox, "Aristotle, Galileo, and 'mixed sciences'", in W. Wallace (ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (Washington, D.C., 1986), 29-51; W. R. Laird, "Galileo and the mixed sciences", in Daniel A. Di Liscia, E. Kessler and C. Methuen (eds), Method and order in the Renaissance philosophy of nature (Aldershot, 1997), 253-70. More generally, see Paul Lawrence Rose, The Italian renaissance of mathematics (Geneva, 1975); Peter Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995); Jean-Marc Mandosio, "Entre mathématiques et physique: Note sur les 'sciences intermédiaires' à la Renaissance", in Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age: Mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (Geneva, 1994), 115-38; Richard D. McKirahan, "Aristotle's subordinate sciences", The British journal for the history of science, xi (1978), 197-220; John J. Cleary, Aristotle and mathematics (Leiden, 1995); Gary I. Brown, "The evolution of the term 'mixed mathematics'", Journal of the history of ideas, 1ii (1991), 81-102; James W. Garrison, "Newton and the relation of mathematics to natural philosophy", Journal of the history of ideas, xlviii (1987), 609-27.
    • (1987) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.48 , pp. 609-627
    • Garrison, J.W.1
  • 13
    • 0042102222 scopus 로고
    • Sur l'utilité des mathématiques et de la physique et sur les travaux de l'académie des sciences
    • Paris
    • B. le Bovier de Fontenelle, "Sur l'utilité des mathématiques et de la physique et sur les travaux de l'Académie des Sciences", Oeuvres complètes, vi (Paris, 1994), 37-50; John Arbuthnot, "An essay on the usefulness of mathematical learning", in George A. Aitken (ed.), The life and works of John Arbuthnot (Oxford, 1892), 409-35; Boyle's 1671 essay "On the usefulness of mathematics to natural philosophy" is in vol. iii of The works of the Honourable Robert Boyle, ed. by Thomas Birch (London, 1744), 425-34. For Bacon's views on mathematics, see Graham Rees, "Mathematics and Francis Bacon's natural philosophy", Revue internationale de philosophie, xl (1986), 399-126.
    • (1994) Oeuvres Complètes , vol.6 , pp. 37-50
    • Le Bovier De Fontenelle, B.1
  • 14
    • 0041601276 scopus 로고
    • An essay on the usefulness of mathematical learning
    • George A. Aitken (ed.), Oxford
    • B. le Bovier de Fontenelle, "Sur l'utilité des mathématiques et de la physique et sur les travaux de l'Académie des Sciences", Oeuvres complètes, vi (Paris, 1994), 37-50; John Arbuthnot, "An essay on the usefulness of mathematical learning", in George A. Aitken (ed.), The life and works of John Arbuthnot (Oxford, 1892), 409-35; Boyle's 1671 essay "On the usefulness of mathematics to natural philosophy" is in vol. iii of The works of the Honourable Robert Boyle, ed. by Thomas Birch (London, 1744), 425-34. For Bacon's views on mathematics, see Graham Rees, "Mathematics and Francis Bacon's natural philosophy", Revue internationale de philosophie, xl (1986), 399-126.
    • (1892) The Life and Works of John Arbuthnot , pp. 409-435
    • Arbuthnot, J.1
  • 15
    • 0042102224 scopus 로고
    • On the usefulness of mathematics to natural philosophy
    • 1671 essay ed. by Thomas Birch London
    • B. le Bovier de Fontenelle, "Sur l'utilité des mathématiques et de la physique et sur les travaux de l'Académie des Sciences", Oeuvres complètes, vi (Paris, 1994), 37-50; John Arbuthnot, "An essay on the usefulness of mathematical learning", in George A. Aitken (ed.), The life and works of John Arbuthnot (Oxford, 1892), 409-35; Boyle's 1671 essay "On the usefulness of mathematics to natural philosophy" is in vol. iii of The works of the Honourable Robert Boyle, ed. by Thomas Birch (London, 1744), 425-34. For Bacon's views on mathematics, see Graham Rees, "Mathematics and Francis Bacon's natural philosophy", Revue internationale de philosophie, xl (1986), 399-126.
    • (1744) The Works of the Honourable Robert Boyle , vol.3 , pp. 425-434
    • Boyle's1
  • 16
    • 0041601279 scopus 로고
    • Mathematics and Francis Bacon's natural philosophy
    • B. le Bovier de Fontenelle, "Sur l'utilité des mathématiques et de la physique et sur les travaux de l'Académie des Sciences", Oeuvres complètes, vi (Paris, 1994), 37-50; John Arbuthnot, "An essay on the usefulness of mathematical learning", in George A. Aitken (ed.), The life and works of John Arbuthnot (Oxford, 1892), 409-35; Boyle's 1671 essay "On the usefulness of mathematics to natural philosophy" is in vol. iii of The works of the Honourable Robert Boyle, ed. by Thomas Birch (London, 1744), 425-34. For Bacon's views on mathematics, see Graham Rees, "Mathematics and Francis Bacon's natural philosophy", Revue internationale de philosophie, xl (1986), 399-126.
    • (1986) Revue Internationale de Philosophie , vol.40 , pp. 399-1126
    • Rees, G.1
  • 17
    • 0002462967 scopus 로고
    • Robert Boyle and mathematics: Reality, representation and experimental practice
    • For Boyle's views on mathematics see Steven Shapin, "Robert Boyle and mathematics: Reality, representation and experimental practice", Science in context, ii (1988), 23-58.
    • (1988) Science in Context , vol.2 , pp. 23-58
    • Shapin, S.1
  • 18
    • 0007227969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics
    • Cited by Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lvii (1997), 265-87, pp. 280-1. Barrow's Essay was first published in Latin in 1683. On the tradition of the mixed sciences in England, see J. A. Bennett, "Christopher Wren: Astronomy, architecture, and the mathematical sciences", Journal for the history of astronomy, vi (1975), 149-84.
    • (1997) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.57 , pp. 265-287
    • Malet, A.1
  • 19
    • 84965650237 scopus 로고
    • Christopher Wren: Astronomy, architecture, and the mathematical sciences
    • Cited by Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lvii (1997), 265-87, pp. 280-1. Barrow's Essay was first published in Latin in 1683. On the tradition of the mixed sciences in England, see J. A. Bennett, "Christopher Wren: Astronomy, architecture, and the mathematical sciences", Journal for the history of astronomy, vi (1975), 149-84.
    • (1975) Journal for the History of Astronomy , vol.6 , pp. 149-184
    • Bennett, J.A.1
  • 20
    • 84996232635 scopus 로고
    • Wallis to Oldenburg, 5 December 1668, Madison and London
    • Wallis to Oldenburg, 5 December 1668, in A. R. Hall and Marie B. Hall (eds), The correspondence of Henry Oldenburg (Madison and London, 1965-86), v, 221.
    • (1965) The Correspondence of Henry Oldenburg , vol.5 , pp. 221
    • Hall, A.R.1    Hall, M.B.2
  • 21
    • 84996175789 scopus 로고
    • Huygens to Marquis de l'Hôpital, 29 December 1692, The Hague
    • Huygens to Marquis de l'Hôpital, 29 December 1692, in C. Huygens, Oeuvres complètes (The Hague, 1888-1950), x, 354; the quotation from Seneca was "calculis ludimus, in supervacuis subtilitas tertur". On Huygens, see Joella G. Yoder, Unrolling time: Christiaan Huygens and the mathematization of nature (Cambridge, 1988).
    • (1888) Oeuvres Complètes , vol.10 , pp. 354
    • Huygens, C.1
  • 22
    • 0008792512 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Huygens to Marquis de l'Hôpital, 29 December 1692, in C. Huygens, Oeuvres complètes (The Hague, 1888-1950), x, 354; the quotation from Seneca was "calculis ludimus, in supervacuis subtilitas tertur". On Huygens, see Joella G. Yoder, Unrolling time: Christiaan Huygens and the mathematization of nature (Cambridge, 1988).
    • (1988) Unrolling Time: Christiaan Huygens and the Mathematization of Nature
    • Yoder, J.G.1
  • 23
    • 0042102216 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Alan S. Shapiro (ed.), The optical papers of Isaac Newton (Cambridge, 1984), i, 86; cited by Allan Gabbey, "Newton's mathematical principles of natural philosophy: A treatise on 'mechanics'?", in P. M. Harman and Alan E. Shapiro (eds). The investigation of difficult things (Cambridge, 1992), 312-13.
    • (1984) The Optical Papers of Isaac Newton , vol.1 , pp. 86
    • Shapiro, A.S.1
  • 24
    • 77952831107 scopus 로고
    • Newton's mathematical principles of natural philosophy: A treatise on 'mechanics'?
    • P. M. Harman and Alan E. Shapiro (eds). Cambridge
    • Alan S. Shapiro (ed.), The optical papers of Isaac Newton (Cambridge, 1984), i, 86; cited by Allan Gabbey, "Newton's mathematical principles of natural philosophy: A treatise on 'mechanics'?", in P. M. Harman and Alan E. Shapiro (eds). The investigation of difficult things (Cambridge, 1992), 312-13.
    • (1992) The Investigation of Difficult Things , pp. 312-313
    • Gabbey, A.1
  • 25
    • 0042102221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I distinguish 'quantification' from 'mathematization'. The first refers to the production of numbers for measuring phenomena through the construction of a metric (a graduated thermometer for example) whereas the second refers to the writing of abstract geometric or algebraic formulations (like the law of free fall or the law of refraction). The first can exist without the second and the latter can be formulated before the former.
  • 26
    • 0042102138 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • For a useful survey of the traditional discussion of mathematization in physics, see H. Floris Cohen, The Scientific Revolution: A historiographical inquiry (Chicago, 1994). Koyré's view is presented in his classic paper "Galileo and Plato", published in 1943 and reprinted as chap. 2 of his Metaphysics and measurement (Cambridge, 1968). For a synthetic presention see Gérard Jorland, La science dans la philosophie: Les recherches épistémologiques de Alexandre Koyré (Paris, 1981).
    • (1994) The Scientific Revolution: A Historiographical Inquiry
    • Floris Cohen, H.1
  • 27
    • 0000937332 scopus 로고
    • Galileo and Plato
    • published in 1943 and reprinted as chap. 2 of his Cambridge
    • For a useful survey of the traditional discussion of mathematization in physics, see H. Floris Cohen, The Scientific Revolution: A historiographical inquiry (Chicago, 1994). Koyré's view is presented in his classic paper "Galileo and Plato", published in 1943 and reprinted as chap. 2 of his Metaphysics and measurement (Cambridge, 1968). For a synthetic presention see Gérard Jorland, La science dans la philosophie: Les recherches épistémologiques de Alexandre Koyré (Paris, 1981).
    • (1968) Metaphysics and Measurement
    • Koyré'S1
  • 28
    • 0007290916 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • For a useful survey of the traditional discussion of mathematization in physics, see H. Floris Cohen, The Scientific Revolution: A historiographical inquiry (Chicago, 1994). Koyré's view is presented in his classic paper "Galileo and Plato", published in 1943 and reprinted as chap. 2 of his Metaphysics and measurement (Cambridge, 1968). For a synthetic presention see Gérard Jorland, La science dans la philosophie: Les recherches épistémologiques de Alexandre Koyré (Paris, 1981).
    • (1981) La Science dans la Philosophie: Les Recherches Épistémologiques de Alexandre Koyré
    • Jorland, G.1
  • 29
    • 84965410194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The mechanics' philosophy and the mechanical philosophy
    • See for example J. A. Bennett, "The mechanics' philosophy and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxiv (1986), 1-28; Dear, op. cit. (ref. 3); Mario Biagioli, Galileo courtier (Chicago, 1993).
    • (1986) History of Science , vol.24 , pp. 1-28
    • Bennett, J.A.1
  • 30
    • 84965410194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 3)
    • See for example J. A. Bennett, "The mechanics' philosophy and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxiv (1986), 1-28; Dear, op. cit. (ref. 3); Mario Biagioli, Galileo courtier (Chicago, 1993).
    • Dear1
  • 31
    • 84965410194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • See for example J. A. Bennett, "The mechanics' philosophy and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxiv (1986), 1-28; Dear, op. cit. (ref. 3); Mario Biagioli, Galileo courtier (Chicago, 1993).
    • (1993) Galileo Courtier
    • Biagioli, M.1
  • 32
    • 0003539735 scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • For a general discussion of mathematization, see Salomon Bochner, The role of mathematics in the rise of science (Princeton, 1966); Enrico Bellone, A world on paper (Cambridge, Mass., 1982). A recent historical analysis of the role of mathematics in physics is provided by Elizabeth Garber, The language of physics: The calculus and the development of theoretical physics in Europe, 1750-1914 (Boston, 1999). See also J. L. Heilbron, Weighing imponderables and other quantitative science around 1800, Historical studies in the physical sciences, Supplement to vol. xxiv/1 (1993). For case studies of mathematization, see Jed Z. Buchwald, "William Thomson and the mathematization of electrostatics", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 101-36; Norton Wise, "William Thomson's mathematical route to energy conservation: A case study of the role of mathematics in concept formation", Historical studies in the physical sciences, x (1979), 49-83. None of these works, however, emphasizes the resistances to mathematization.
    • (1966) The Role of Mathematics in the Rise of Science
    • Bochner, S.1
  • 33
    • 0041601277 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.
    • For a general discussion of mathematization, see Salomon Bochner, The role of mathematics in the rise of science (Princeton, 1966); Enrico Bellone, A world on paper (Cambridge, Mass., 1982). A recent historical analysis of the role of mathematics in physics is provided by Elizabeth Garber, The language of physics: The calculus and the development of theoretical physics in Europe, 1750-1914 (Boston, 1999). See also J. L. Heilbron, Weighing imponderables and other quantitative science around 1800, Historical studies in the physical sciences, Supplement to vol. xxiv/1 (1993). For case studies of mathematization, see Jed Z. Buchwald, "William Thomson and the mathematization of electrostatics", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 101-36; Norton Wise, "William Thomson's mathematical route to energy conservation: A case study of the role of mathematics in concept formation", Historical studies in the physical sciences, x (1979), 49-83. None of these works, however, emphasizes the resistances to mathematization.
    • (1982) A World on Paper
    • Bellone, E.1
  • 34
    • 0003452987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boston
    • For a general discussion of mathematization, see Salomon Bochner, The role of mathematics in the rise of science (Princeton, 1966); Enrico Bellone, A world on paper (Cambridge, Mass., 1982). A recent historical analysis of the role of mathematics in physics is provided by Elizabeth Garber, The language of physics: The calculus and the development of theoretical physics in Europe, 1750-1914 (Boston, 1999). See also J. L. Heilbron, Weighing imponderables and other quantitative science around 1800, Historical studies in the physical sciences, Supplement to vol. xxiv/1 (1993). For case studies of mathematization, see Jed Z. Buchwald, "William Thomson and the mathematization of electrostatics", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 101-36; Norton Wise, "William Thomson's mathematical route to energy conservation: A case study of the role of mathematics in concept formation", Historical studies in the physical sciences, x (1979), 49-83. None of these works, however, emphasizes the resistances to mathematization.
    • (1999) The Language of Physics: The Calculus and the Development of Theoretical Physics in Europe, 1750-1914
    • Garber, E.1
  • 35
    • 0042102223 scopus 로고
    • For a general discussion of mathematization, see Salomon Bochner, The role of mathematics in the rise of science (Princeton, 1966); Enrico Bellone, A world on paper (Cambridge, Mass., 1982). A recent historical analysis of the role of mathematics in physics is provided by Elizabeth Garber, The language of physics: The calculus and the development of theoretical physics in Europe, 1750-1914 (Boston, 1999). See also J. L. Heilbron, Weighing imponderables and other quantitative science around 1800, Historical studies in the physical sciences, Supplement to vol. xxiv/1 (1993). For case studies of mathematization, see Jed Z. Buchwald, "William Thomson and the mathematization of electrostatics", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 101-36; Norton Wise, "William Thomson's mathematical route to energy conservation: A case study of the role of mathematics in concept formation", Historical studies in the physical sciences, x (1979), 49-83. None of these works, however, emphasizes the resistances to mathematization.
    • (1993) Weighing Imponderables and Other Quantitative Science Around 1800, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.24 , Issue.1 SUPPL.
    • Heilbron, J.L.1
  • 36
    • 84968286708 scopus 로고
    • William Thomson and the mathematization of electrostatics
    • For a general discussion of mathematization, see Salomon Bochner, The role of mathematics in the rise of science (Princeton, 1966); Enrico Bellone, A world on paper (Cambridge, Mass., 1982). A recent historical analysis of the role of mathematics in physics is provided by Elizabeth Garber, The language of physics: The calculus and the development of theoretical physics in Europe, 1750-1914 (Boston, 1999). See also J. L. Heilbron, Weighing imponderables and other quantitative science around 1800, Historical studies in the physical sciences, Supplement to vol. xxiv/1 (1993). For case studies of mathematization, see Jed Z. Buchwald, "William Thomson and the mathematization of electrostatics", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 101-36; Norton Wise, "William Thomson's mathematical route to energy conservation: A case study of the role of mathematics in concept formation", Historical studies in the physical sciences, x (1979), 49-83. None of these works, however, emphasizes the resistances to mathematization.
    • (1977) Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.8 , pp. 101-136
    • Buchwald, J.Z.1
  • 37
    • 84968283735 scopus 로고
    • William Thomson's mathematical route to energy conservation: A case study of the role of mathematics in concept formation
    • For a general discussion of mathematization, see Salomon Bochner, The role of mathematics in the rise of science (Princeton, 1966); Enrico Bellone, A world on paper (Cambridge, Mass., 1982). A recent historical analysis of the role of mathematics in physics is provided by Elizabeth Garber, The language of physics: The calculus and the development of theoretical physics in Europe, 1750-1914 (Boston, 1999). See also J. L. Heilbron, Weighing imponderables and other quantitative science around 1800, Historical studies in the physical sciences, Supplement to vol. xxiv/1 (1993). For case studies of mathematization, see Jed Z. Buchwald, "William Thomson and the mathematization of electrostatics", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 101-36; Norton Wise, "William Thomson's mathematical route to energy conservation: A case study of the role of mathematics in concept formation", Historical studies in the physical sciences, x (1979), 49-83. None of these works, however, emphasizes the resistances to mathematization.
    • (1979) Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.10 , pp. 49-83
    • Wise, N.1
  • 39
    • 0026836535 scopus 로고
    • Apollo mathematicus: A story of resistance to quantification in the seventeenth century
    • Stephen M. Stigler, "Apollo mathematicus: A story of resistance to quantification in the seventeenth century", Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, cxxxvi (1992), 93-126. Allen G. Debus, "Mathematics and nature in the chemical texts of the Renaisssance", Ambix, xv (1968), 1-28.
    • (1992) Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society , vol.136 , pp. 93-126
    • Stigler, S.M.1
  • 40
    • 84975019531 scopus 로고
    • Mathematics and nature in the chemical texts of the Renaisssance
    • Stephen M. Stigler, "Apollo mathematicus: A story of resistance to quantification in the seventeenth century", Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, cxxxvi (1992), 93-126. Allen G. Debus, "Mathematics and nature in the chemical texts of the Renaisssance", Ambix, xv (1968), 1-28.
    • (1968) Ambix , vol.15 , pp. 1-28
    • Debus, A.G.1
  • 41
    • 0042603362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • La substance évanescente de la physique
    • Liège, in press
    • e Congrès International d'Histoire des Sciences (Liège, in press). It should be noted that by concentrating on what mathematics did to physics, I do not wish to suggest that the development of new instruments and new methods of experimentation did not also affect access to the practice of physics; that would be absurd. Although I cannot here develop this aspect of the transformation of the discipline, I do allude to it. As one reviewer suggested, one could also analyse what physics did to mathematics; but that of course would require writing a different, though complementary, paper.
    • e Congrès International d'Histoire des Sciences
    • Gingras, Y.1
  • 43
    • 84965740831 scopus 로고
    • How the Principia got its name: Or, taking natural philosophy seriously
    • For such an approach, see Andrew Cunningham, "How the Principia got its name: or, taking natural philosophy seriously", History of science, xix (1991), 377-92; see also his "Getting the game right: Some plain words on the identity and invention of science", Studies in the history and philosophy of science, xix (1988), 365-89. The author seems to suggest that it is historiographically 'illegitimate' to use words in ways that differ from how the authors themselves used them, as if words could have but a single meaning at any given time.
    • (1991) History of Science , vol.19 , pp. 377-392
    • Cunningham, A.1
  • 44
    • 33750187135 scopus 로고
    • Getting the game right: Some plain words on the identity and invention of science
    • For such an approach, see Andrew Cunningham, "How the Principia got its name: or, taking natural philosophy seriously", History of science, xix (1991), 377-92; see also his "Getting the game right: Some plain words on the identity and invention of science", Studies in the history and philosophy of science, xix (1988), 365-89. The author seems to suggest that it is historiographically 'illegitimate' to use words in ways that differ from how the authors themselves used them, as if words could have but a single meaning at any given time.
    • (1988) Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science , vol.19 , pp. 365-389
  • 47
    • 0042603358 scopus 로고
    • The invention of physics
    • chap. 4 of her book New York
    • For a discussion of the changing content of 'physics', see Susan Faye Cannon, "The invention of physics", chap. 4 of her book Science in culture: The early Victorian period (New York, 1978), 111-36; Thomas Kuhn, The essential tension (Chicago, 1977), 60-64; John L. Heilbron, "Experimental natural philosophy", in G. S. Rousseau and Roy Porter (eds), The ferment of knowledge: Studies in the historiography of eighteenth-century science (Cambridge, 1980), 357-87.
    • (1978) Science in Culture: the Early Victorian Period , pp. 111-136
    • Cannon, S.F.1
  • 48
    • 0003666086 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • For a discussion of the changing content of 'physics', see Susan Faye Cannon, "The invention of physics", chap. 4 of her book Science in culture: The early Victorian period (New York, 1978), 111-36; Thomas Kuhn, The essential tension (Chicago, 1977), 60-64; John L. Heilbron, "Experimental natural philosophy", in G. S. Rousseau and Roy Porter (eds), The ferment of knowledge: Studies in the historiography of eighteenth-century science (Cambridge, 1980), 357-87.
    • (1977) The Essential Tension , pp. 60-64
    • Kuhn, T.1
  • 49
    • 0043104158 scopus 로고
    • Experimental natural philosophy
    • G. S. Rousseau and Roy Porter (eds), Cambridge
    • For a discussion of the changing content of 'physics', see Susan Faye Cannon, "The invention of physics", chap. 4 of her book Science in culture: The early Victorian period (New York, 1978), 111-36; Thomas Kuhn, The essential tension (Chicago, 1977), 60-64; John L. Heilbron, "Experimental natural philosophy", in G. S. Rousseau and Roy Porter (eds), The ferment of knowledge: Studies in the historiography of eighteenth-century science (Cambridge, 1980), 357-87.
    • (1980) The Ferment of Knowledge: Studies in the Historiography of Eighteenth-century Science , pp. 357-387
    • Heilbron, J.L.1
  • 50
    • 0042603364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I think, for example, that much of the discussion about the 'non-existence' of the Scientific Revolution is based on a confusion of levels and categories of analysis.
  • 51
    • 84996261247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Uses and abuses of anachronism in the history of the sciences
    • For a recent discussion of that question see Nick Jardine, "Uses and abuses of anachronism in the history of the sciences", History of science, xxxviii (2000), 251-70. Though I essentially agree with the author, I would not use the term 'anachronism' to refer to the application of sociological categories to past events (p. 261). Since analytical categories are defined by analysts they need not have been part of the actor's repertoire. It is thus a category mistake to call them 'anachronistic' since they are not used as if they were actors' categories. Otherwise we would have to call anachronistic any explanations of past diseases invoking 'virus' or 'microbes' before the 'discovery' of these entities. I know of no historian ready to pay that price. And it should be clear that these categories do not prevent us from looking at how the actors themselves explained these diseases in the absence of the categories of 'virus' or 'microbes'. They are simply different levels of analysis.
    • (2000) History of Science , vol.38 , pp. 251-270
    • Jardine, N.1
  • 52
    • 0042603363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fatio to Huygens, 24 June 1687, ref. 8
    • Fatio to Huygens, 24 June 1687, in Huygens, Oeuvres (ref. 8), ix, 167-8.
    • Oeuvres , vol.9 , pp. 167-168
    • Huygens1
  • 58
    • 0042102225 scopus 로고
    • University of California Publications in Modem Philology, Berkeley
    • e siècle (Paris, 1965), 33-59; C. Lennart Carlson, A history of the Gentleman's Magazine (Providence, 1938); Albert Pailler, Edward Cave et le Gentleman's Magazine (1731-1754) (Lille, 1975).
    • (1941) Le Journal des Savants et l'Angleterre, 1702-1789 , vol.20 , Issue.6
    • De La Harpe, J.1
  • 60
    • 0042603354 scopus 로고
    • Berthier's journal de trévoux and thé philosophes
    • e siècle (Paris, 1965), 33-59; C. Lennart Carlson, A history of the Gentleman's Magazine (Providence, 1938); Albert Pailler, Edward Cave et le Gentleman's Magazine (1731-1754) (Lille, 1975).
    • (1957) Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century , vol.3 , pp. 13-63
    • Pappas, J.N.1
  • 61
    • 0043104151 scopus 로고
    • e siècle: Le journal des savants et les mémoires de trévoux
    • G. Bolleme et al. (eds), Paris
    • e siècle (Paris, 1965), 33-59; C. Lennart Carlson, A history of the Gentleman's Magazine (Providence, 1938); Albert Pailler, Edward Cave et le Gentleman's Magazine (1731-1754) (Lille, 1975).
    • (1965) e Siècle , pp. 33-59
    • Ehrard, J.1    Roger, J.2
  • 64
    • 0004090203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • In his classic book La formation de l'esprit scientifique (Paris, 1938), Gaston Bachelard studied typical works of 18th-century science but only to contrast them with modern 19th- and 20th-century science. Completing this approach, I wish to follow the process of exclusion that transformed scientific practice and led to the situation described by Bachelard as "scientific" as opposed to what he called the "pre-scientific" spirit of the 18th century. It is obvious that I do not have to use these normative categories in order to describe that process. For a more detailed discussion of Bachelard's views in relation to our project, see Yves Gingras, "Mathématisation et exclusion: Socio-analyse de la formation des cités savantes", in Jean-Jacques Wunenburger (ed.), Gaston Bachelard et l'épistémologie française (Paris, in press).
    • (1938) La Formation de l'Esprit Scientifique
  • 65
    • 84864903207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mathématisation et exclusion: Socio-analyse de la formation des cités savantes
    • Jean-Jacques Wunenburger (ed.), Paris, in press
    • In his classic book La formation de l'esprit scientifique (Paris, 1938), Gaston Bachelard studied typical works of 18th-century science but only to contrast them with modern 19th- and 20th-century science. Completing this approach, I wish to follow the process of exclusion that transformed scientific practice and led to the situation described by Bachelard as "scientific" as opposed to what he called the "pre-scientific" spirit of the 18th century. It is obvious that I do not have to use these normative categories in order to describe that process. For a more detailed discussion of Bachelard's views in relation to our project, see Yves Gingras, "Mathématisation et exclusion: Socio-analyse de la formation des cités savantes", in Jean-Jacques Wunenburger (ed.), Gaston Bachelard et l'épistémologie française (Paris, in press).
    • Gaston Bachelard et l'Épistémologie Française
    • Gingras, Y.1
  • 66
    • 0007235313 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • For a detailed analysis of Leibniz's reaction to Newton's mathematization of natural philosophy. see Domenico Bertoloni Meli, Equivalence and priority: Newton versus Leibniz (Oxford, 1993). As he explains, Leibniz stressed "the insufficiency of purely mathematical laws [and] the need for physical explanations ..." (p. 24); see also Yves Gingras, "La dynamique de Leibniz: Métaphysique et substantialisme", Philosophiques, xxii (1995), 395-405. In the 1730s Jean Bernoulli also devoted two prize-winning essays to the question of the physical cause of gravitation, trying to reconcile vortex motions with the mathematical laws of Kepler and Newton. For him, Newton's vacuum and attraction were "incomprehensible for a physicist" who had to "search the causes of the facts"; "Essai d'une nouvelle physique céleste" in Opera omnia (Geneva, 1742), iii, 266-7. For details, see William Shea, "The unfinished revolution: Johann Bernoulli (1667-1748) and the debate between the Cartesians and the Newtonians", William Shea (ed.), Revolutions in science: Their meaning and relevance (Canton, 1988), 70-92.
    • (1993) Equivalence and Priority: Newton Versus Leibniz
    • Meli, D.B.1
  • 67
    • 0042102208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a detailed analysis of Leibniz's reaction to Newton's mathematization of natural philosophy. see Domenico Bertoloni Meli, Equivalence and priority: Newton versus Leibniz (Oxford, 1993). As he explains, Leibniz stressed "the insufficiency of purely mathematical laws [and] the need for physical explanations ..." (p. 24); see also Yves Gingras, "La dynamique de Leibniz: Métaphysique et substantialisme", Philosophiques, xxii (1995), 395-405. In the 1730s Jean Bernoulli also devoted two prize-winning essays to the question of the physical cause of gravitation, trying to reconcile vortex motions with the mathematical laws of Kepler and Newton. For him, Newton's vacuum and attraction were "incomprehensible for a physicist" who had to "search the causes of the facts"; "Essai d'une nouvelle physique céleste" in Opera omnia (Geneva, 1742), iii, 266-7. For details, see William Shea, "The unfinished revolution: Johann Bernoulli (1667-1748) and the debate between the Cartesians and the Newtonians", William Shea (ed.), Revolutions in science: Their meaning and relevance (Canton, 1988), 70-92.
    • The Insufficiency of Purely Mathematical Laws [and] the Need for Physical Explanations ... , pp. 24
  • 68
    • 0043104142 scopus 로고
    • La dynamique de Leibniz: Métaphysique et substantialisme
    • For a detailed analysis of Leibniz's reaction to Newton's mathematization of natural philosophy. see Domenico Bertoloni Meli, Equivalence and priority: Newton versus Leibniz (Oxford, 1993). As he explains, Leibniz stressed "the insufficiency of purely mathematical laws [and] the need for physical explanations ..." (p. 24); see also Yves Gingras, "La dynamique de Leibniz: Métaphysique et substantialisme", Philosophiques, xxii (1995), 395-405. In the 1730s Jean Bernoulli also devoted two prize-winning essays to the question of the physical cause of gravitation, trying to reconcile vortex motions with the mathematical laws of Kepler and Newton. For him, Newton's vacuum and attraction were "incomprehensible for a physicist" who had to "search the causes of the facts"; "Essai d'une nouvelle physique céleste" in Opera omnia (Geneva, 1742), iii, 266-7. For details, see William Shea, "The unfinished revolution: Johann Bernoulli (1667-1748) and the debate between the Cartesians and the Newtonians", William Shea (ed.), Revolutions in science: Their meaning and relevance (Canton, 1988), 70-92.
    • (1995) Philosophiques , vol.22 , pp. 395-405
    • Gingras, Y.1
  • 69
    • 0042603345 scopus 로고
    • Essai d'une nouvelle physique céleste
    • Geneva
    • For a detailed analysis of Leibniz's reaction to Newton's mathematization of natural philosophy. see Domenico Bertoloni Meli, Equivalence and priority: Newton versus Leibniz (Oxford, 1993). As he explains, Leibniz stressed "the insufficiency of purely mathematical laws [and] the need for physical explanations ..." (p. 24); see also Yves Gingras, "La dynamique de Leibniz: Métaphysique et substantialisme", Philosophiques, xxii (1995), 395-405. In the 1730s Jean Bernoulli also devoted two prize-winning essays to the question of the physical cause of gravitation, trying to reconcile vortex motions with the mathematical laws of Kepler and Newton. For him, Newton's vacuum and attraction were "incomprehensible for a physicist" who had to "search the causes of the facts"; "Essai d'une nouvelle physique céleste" in Opera omnia (Geneva, 1742), iii, 266-7. For details, see William Shea, "The unfinished revolution: Johann Bernoulli (1667-1748) and the debate between the Cartesians and the Newtonians", William Shea (ed.), Revolutions in science: Their meaning and relevance (Canton, 1988), 70-92.
    • (1742) Opera Omnia , vol.3 , pp. 266-267
  • 70
    • 0041601267 scopus 로고
    • The unfinished revolution: Johann Bernoulli (1667-1748) and the debate between the Cartesians and the Newtonians
    • William Shea (ed.), Canton
    • For a detailed analysis of Leibniz's reaction to Newton's mathematization of natural philosophy. see Domenico Bertoloni Meli, Equivalence and priority: Newton versus Leibniz (Oxford, 1993). As he explains, Leibniz stressed "the insufficiency of purely mathematical laws [and] the need for physical explanations ..." (p. 24); see also Yves Gingras, "La dynamique de Leibniz: Métaphysique et substantialisme", Philosophiques, xxii (1995), 395-405. In the 1730s Jean Bernoulli also devoted two prize-winning essays to the question of the physical cause of gravitation, trying to reconcile vortex motions with the mathematical laws of Kepler and Newton. For him, Newton's vacuum and attraction were "incomprehensible for a physicist" who had to "search the causes of the facts"; "Essai d'une nouvelle physique céleste" in Opera omnia (Geneva, 1742), iii, 266-7. For details, see William Shea, "The unfinished revolution: Johann Bernoulli (1667-1748) and the debate between the Cartesians and the Newtonians", William Shea (ed.), Revolutions in science: Their meaning and relevance (Canton, 1988), 70-92.
    • (1988) Revolutions in Science: Their Meaning and Relevance , pp. 70-92
    • Shea, W.1
  • 74
    • 0042603349 scopus 로고
    • The notion of experimental physics in the early eighteenth-century
    • J. C. Pitt (ed.), Dordrecht
    • Cited by R. W. Home, "The notion of experimental physics in the early eighteenth-century", in J. C. Pitt (ed.), Change and progress in modern science (Dordrecht, 1985), 107-31, p. 124.
    • (1985) Change and Progress in Modern Science , pp. 107-131
    • Home, R.W.1
  • 75
    • 0004320688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • translated by I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman Berkeley
    • Isaac Newton, Principia, translated by I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman (Berkeley, 1999), 381.
    • (1999) Principia , pp. 381
    • Newton, I.1
  • 76
    • 0043104146 scopus 로고
    • The letters and papers of Codwallader Colden, iii: 1743-1747
    • P. Collinson to C. Colden, 27 March 1747, New York
    • P. Collinson to C. Colden, 27 March 1747, in "The letters and papers of Codwallader Colden, iii: 1743-1747", Collections of the New York Historical Society for the year 1919 (New York, 1920), 368.
    • (1920) Collections of the New York Historical Society for the Year 1919 , pp. 368
  • 77
    • 0043104141 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Cadwallader Colden, Principles of action in matter, the gravitation of bodies and the notion of the planets, explained of those principles (London, 1751), preface. Also mentioned in C. Colden to Dr Betts, 25 April 1750, in "The letters and papers of Codwallader Colden, iv: 1748-1754", Collections of the New York Historical Society for the year 1920 (New York, 1921), 204. Cadwallader Colden, Explication des premières causes de l'action de la matière et de la cause de la gravitation (Paris, 1751). Since Colden was, through his relation with Franklin, in indirect contact with Abbé Nollet, the latter may have been at the origin of the translation.
    • (1751) Principles of Action in Matter, the Gravitation of Bodies and the Notion of the Planets, Explained of Those Principles
    • Colden, C.1
  • 78
    • 0042102196 scopus 로고
    • The letters and papers of Codwallader Colden, iv: 1748-1754
    • preface. Also mentioned in C. Colden to Dr Betts, 25 April 1750, New York
    • Cadwallader Colden, Principles of action in matter, the gravitation of bodies and the notion of the planets, explained of those principles (London, 1751), preface. Also mentioned in C. Colden to Dr Betts, 25 April 1750, in "The letters and papers of Codwallader Colden, iv: 1748-1754", Collections of the New York Historical Society for the year 1920 (New York, 1921), 204. Cadwallader Colden, Explication des premières causes de l'action de la matière et de la cause de la gravitation (Paris, 1751). Since Colden was, through his relation with Franklin, in indirect contact with Abbé Nollet, the latter may have been at the origin of the translation.
    • (1921) Collections of the New York Historical Society for the Year 1920 , pp. 204
  • 79
    • 0043104137 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • Cadwallader Colden, Principles of action in matter, the gravitation of bodies and the notion of the planets, explained of those principles (London, 1751), preface. Also mentioned in C. Colden to Dr Betts, 25 April 1750, in "The letters and papers of Codwallader Colden, iv: 1748-1754", Collections of the New York Historical Society for the year 1920 (New York, 1921), 204. Cadwallader Colden, Explication des premières causes de l'action de la matière et de la cause de la gravitation (Paris, 1751). Since Colden was, through his relation with Franklin, in indirect contact with Abbé Nollet, the latter may have been at the origin of the translation.
    • (1751) Explication des Premières Causes de l'Action de la Matière et de la cause de la Gravitation
    • Colden, C.1
  • 80
    • 0042102197 scopus 로고
    • December and January 65-66
    • Gentleman's magazine, December 1752, 499-500, 570-1, 589-90; and January 1753, 65-66.
    • (1752) Gentleman's Magazine , pp. 499-500
  • 82
    • 0042102195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • C. Colden to P. Collinson, 20 June 1745, ref. 37
    • C. Colden to P. Collinson, 20 June 1745, in "The letters and papers of Codwallader Colden, iii" (ref. 37), 119. The Anglo-American fleet was then attacking the French settlement of the LouisBourg fortress which capitulated on 26 June.
    • The Letters and Papers of Codwallader Colden, III , pp. 119
  • 83
    • 0042603346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 38, A similar statement is also found in the 1745 edition, p. v.
    • Colden, Principles of action in matter (ref. 38), 2. A similar statement is also found in the 1745 edition, p. v.
    • Principles of Action in Matter , pp. 2
    • Colden1
  • 86
    • 0043104127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Euler to Wetstein, 21 November 1752, vera copia in the letter from P. Collinson to Colden, 7 March 1753, ref. 38
    • Euler to Wetstein, 21 November 1752, vera copia in the letter from P. Collinson to Colden, 7 March 1753, in "The letters and papers of Codwallader Colden, iv" (ref. 38), 356.
    • The Letters and Papers of Codwallader Colden, IV , pp. 356
  • 88
    • 0011547394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Euler on action-at-a-distance and fundamental equations in continuum mechanics
    • Harman and Shapiro (eds), ref. 9
    • On Euler's views on mechanical explanation, see Curtis Wilson, "Euler on action-at-a-distance and fundamental equations in continuum mechanics", in Harman and Shapiro (eds), The investigation of difficult things (ref. 9), 399-420.
    • The Investigation of Difficult Things , pp. 399-420
    • Wilson, C.1
  • 89
    • 0041601261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Euler to Wetstein, op. cit. (ref. 38), 356
    • Euler to Wetstein, op. cit. (ref. 38), 356.
  • 90
    • 0043104135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • On these exchanges, see "The letters and papers of Codwallader Colden, iv" (ref. 38), 378 (letter from Collinson, March 10, 1754,), 395-396 (Colden to Collinson, July 7 1753); the citation is on p. 406 (Collinson to Golden Sept. 1, 1753). He seems not to have succeeded for I could find nothing on gravitation by Golden in the Magazine after the extracts from his book appeared in January 1753. In his letter to Golden on 10 March 1754, Collinson noted that "your answer to pro: Euler is not yett publis'd...", ibid., 378.
  • 91
    • 0042603339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 5), 42
    • Shapin, op. cit. (ref. 5), 42.
    • Shapin1
  • 92
    • 0041601256 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • P. Varignon, Nouvelles conjectures sur la pesanteur (Paris, 1690). It is interesting to note that though historians have studied in detail Varignon's contribution to analytical mechanics, they pass over in silence this essay totally devoted to a mechanical explanation of gravity. Somehow in the 1690s, Varignon seems to have had a conversion to the mathematical approach and to have completely abandoned this project.
    • (1690) Nouvelles Conjectures sur la Pesanteur
    • Varignon, P.1
  • 93
    • 0043104126 scopus 로고
    • Journal de Trévoux, xlii (1742), 1093; George R. Healy, "Mechanistic science and the French Jesuits: A study of the response of the Journal de Trévoux (1701-1762) to Descartes and Newton", Ph.D. dissertation, University of Minnesota, 1956, p. 198, attributes, plausibly, the text to Castel, though it is not signed.
    • (1742) Journal de Trévoux , vol.42 , pp. 1093
  • 96
    • 0042603338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 30), 230
    • Cited by Bachelard, op. cit. (ref. 30), 230.
    • Bachelard1
  • 98
    • 0042603295 scopus 로고
    • Precision instruments and the demonstrative order of proofs in Lavoisier's chemistry
    • J. Golinski, "Precision instruments and the demonstrative order of proofs in Lavoisier's chemistry", Osiris, n.s., ix (1994), 30-47 and idem, Science and public culture: Chemistry and enlightenment in Britain, 1760-1820 (Cambridge, 1992), 138.
    • (1994) Osiris , vol.9 , pp. 30-47
    • Golinski, J.1
  • 100
    • 0041601216 scopus 로고
    • La réception des rayons X au Québec: Radiographie des pratiques scientifiques
    • Marcel Fournier, Yves Gingras and Othmar Keel (eds), Sainte-Foy
    • By contrast, the relatively wide distribution of X-ray apparatus at the end of the nineteenth century made that phenomena accessible to non-professional physicists, see Yves Gingras, "La réception des rayons X au Québec: Radiographie des pratiques scientifiques", in Marcel Fournier, Yves Gingras and Othmar Keel (eds), Sciences et médecine au Québec: Perspectives sociohistoriques (Sainte-Foy, 1987), 69-86.
    • (1987) Sciences et Médecine au Québec: Perspectives Sociohistoriques , pp. 69-86
    • Gingras, Y.1
  • 101
  • 102
    • 0041601220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 56), 48
    • Castel exchanged letters with Diderot on his Lettre sur les aveugles; see Schier, op. cit. (ref. 56), 48.
    • Schier1
  • 103
    • 0042603294 scopus 로고
    • Lesprit de finesse contre l'esprit de géométrie: Un débat entre Diderot et d'Alembert
    • See John Pappas, "Lesprit de finesse contre l'esprit de géométrie: Un débat entre Diderot et d'Alembert", Sudies on Voltaire and the eighteenth century. lxxxix (1972), 1229-53; and more generally T. L. Hankins, Jean d'Alembert: Science and the Enlightenment (Oxford, 1970); Michel Paty, D'Alembert (Paris, 1998).
    • (1972) Sudies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century , vol.89 , pp. 1229-1253
    • Pappas, J.1
  • 104
    • 0039144700 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • See John Pappas, "Lesprit de finesse contre l'esprit de géométrie: Un débat entre Diderot et d'Alembert", Sudies on Voltaire and the eighteenth century. lxxxix (1972), 1229-53; and more generally T. L. Hankins, Jean d'Alembert: Science and the Enlightenment (Oxford, 1970); Michel Paty, D'Alembert (Paris, 1998).
    • (1970) Jean d'Alembert: Science and the Enlightenment
    • Hankins, T.L.1
  • 105
    • 0041601217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • See John Pappas, "Lesprit de finesse contre l'esprit de géométrie: Un débat entre Diderot et d'Alembert", Sudies on Voltaire and the eighteenth century. lxxxix (1972), 1229-53; and more generally T. L. Hankins, Jean d'Alembert: Science and the Enlightenment (Oxford, 1970); Michel Paty, D'Alembert (Paris, 1998).
    • (1998) D'Alembert
    • Paty, M.1
  • 106
    • 0041601218 scopus 로고
    • De l'interprétation de la nature
    • Paris
    • D. Diderot, "De l'interprétation de la nature", Oeuvres philosophiques (Paris, 1961), 177-244. p. 216.
    • (1961) Oeuvres Philosophiques , pp. 177-244
    • Diderot, D.1
  • 107
    • 61149255837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See for example ibid., 214 where he writes: "nos faiseurs de cours d'expérience ressemblent un peu à celui qui penserait avoir donné un grand repas parce qu'il aurait eu beaucoup de monde à sa table."
    • Oeuvres Philosophiques , pp. 214
  • 111
    • 0043104091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction aux recherches sur la précession des équinoxes et sur la nutation de l'axe de la Terre dans le système newtonien
    • Geneva
    • J. R. D'Alembert, "Introduction aux recherches sur la précession des équinoxes et sur la nutation de l'axe de la Terre dans le système newtonien", in Oeuvres complètes (Geneva, 1967), i, 437-50, p. 437. On Buffon's critiques of mathematics, also published in 1749, see Jacques Roger, Buffon (Paris, 1989), 263-5.
    • (1967) Oeuvres Complètes , vol.1 , pp. 437-450
    • D'Alembert, J.R.1
  • 112
    • 0002230916 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • J. R. D'Alembert, "Introduction aux recherches sur la précession des équinoxes et sur la nutation de l'axe de la Terre dans le système newtonien", in Oeuvres complètes (Geneva, 1967), i, 437-50, p. 437. On Buffon's critiques of mathematics, also published in 1749, see Jacques Roger, Buffon (Paris, 1989), 263-5.
    • (1989) Buffon , pp. 263-265
    • Roger, J.1
  • 114
    • 79957107478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See for example ibid., 344, 353.
    • Introduction , pp. 344
  • 116
    • 0043104096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discours préliminaire ou analyse des recherches sur différents points importants du système du monde
    • ref. 65
    • D'Alembert, "Discours préliminaire ou analyse des recherches sur différents points importants du système du monde", in Oeuvres complètes (ref. 65), i, 349-91, p. 355.
    • Oeuvres Complètes , vol.1 , pp. 349-391
    • D'Alembert1
  • 117
    • 4744349428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See for example, ibid., 352, 356, 358, 438; see also Michel Paty, "Rapports des mathématiques et de la physique chez D'Alembert", Dix-huitième siècle, no. 16 (1984), 69-79.
    • Oeuvres Complètes , pp. 352
  • 118
    • 0042102139 scopus 로고
    • Rapports des mathématiques et de la physique chez D'Alembert
    • See for example, ibid., 352, 356, 358, 438; see also Michel Paty, "Rapports des mathématiques et de la physique chez D'Alembert", Dix-huitième siècle, no. 16 (1984), 69-79.
    • (1984) Dix-huitième Siècle , vol.16 , pp. 69-79
    • Paty, M.1
  • 120
    • 0042603293 scopus 로고
    • Clairault to Euler, 19 June 1749, Basel
    • Clairault to Euler, 19 June 1749, in Adolf P. Juskevic and René Taton (eds), Correspondance de Leonhard Euler avec A. C. Clairault, J. D'Alembert et J. L. Lagrange (Basel, 1980), 186. On the debate over the shape of the Earth, see John L. Greenberg, The problem of the Earth's shape from Newton to Clairault (Cambridge, 1995). For a fascinating cultural history of this period see Elizabeth Badinter, Les passions intellectuelles I: Désirs de gloire (1735-1751) (Paris, 1999).
    • (1980) Correspondance de Leonhard Euler Avec A. C. Clairault, J. D'Alembert et J. L. Lagrange , pp. 186
    • Juskevic, A.P.1    Taton, R.2
  • 121
    • 0039144778 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Clairault to Euler, 19 June 1749, in Adolf P. Juskevic and René Taton (eds), Correspondance de Leonhard Euler avec A. C. Clairault, J. D'Alembert et J. L. Lagrange (Basel, 1980), 186. On the debate over the shape of the Earth, see John L. Greenberg, The problem of the Earth's shape from Newton to Clairault (Cambridge, 1995). For a fascinating cultural history of this period see Elizabeth Badinter, Les passions intellectuelles I: Désirs de gloire (1735-1751) (Paris, 1999).
    • (1995) The Problem of the Earth's Shape from Newton to Clairault
    • Greenberg, J.L.1
  • 122
    • 0041601213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • Clairault to Euler, 19 June 1749, in Adolf P. Juskevic and René Taton (eds), Correspondance de Leonhard Euler avec A. C. Clairault, J. D'Alembert et J. L. Lagrange (Basel, 1980), 186. On the debate over the shape of the Earth, see John L. Greenberg, The problem of the Earth's shape from Newton to Clairault (Cambridge, 1995). For a fascinating cultural history of this period see Elizabeth Badinter, Les passions intellectuelles I: Désirs de gloire (1735-1751) (Paris, 1999).
    • (1999) Les Passions Intellectuelles I: Désirs de Gloire (1735-1751)
    • Badinter, E.1
  • 123
    • 0038066366 scopus 로고
    • Halley to Newton, 29 June 1686, Cambridge
    • Halley to Newton, 29 June 1686, in H. W. Turnbull (ed.), The correspondance of Isaac Newton, ii: 1676-1687 (Cambridge, 1960), 443. Mordechai Feingold analysed the debate on the place of mathematics in the Royal Society in "Mathematicians and naturalists: Sir Isaac Newton and the Royal Society", in Jed Z. Buchwald and I. Bernard Cohen (eds). Isaac Newton's natural philosophy (Cambridge, Mass, 2000), 77-102.
    • (1960) The Correspondance of Isaac Newton, II: 1676-1687 , pp. 443
    • Turnbull, H.W.1
  • 124
    • 0042102120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mathematicians and naturalists: Sir Isaac Newton and the Royal Society
    • Jed Z. Buchwald and I. Bernard Cohen (eds). Cambridge, Mass
    • Halley to Newton, 29 June 1686, in H. W. Turnbull (ed.), The correspondance of Isaac Newton, ii: 1676-1687 (Cambridge, 1960), 443. Mordechai Feingold analysed the debate on the place of mathematics in the Royal Society in "Mathematicians and naturalists: Sir Isaac Newton and the Royal Society", in Jed Z. Buchwald and I. Bernard Cohen (eds). Isaac Newton's natural philosophy (Cambridge, Mass, 2000), 77-102.
    • (2000) Isaac Newton's Natural Philosophy , pp. 77-102
    • Feingold, M.1
  • 134
    • 0043104093 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • Charles-François Viel, De l'impuissance des mathématiques pour assurer la solidité des batimens et Recherches sur la construction des ponts (Paris, 1805). For a general discussion of the debates accompanying the use of mathematics in the design of bridges, see Eda Kranakis, Constructing a bridge: An exploration of engineering culture, design, and research in nineteenth-century France and America (Cambridge, 1997); and Antoine Picon, L'invention de l'ingénieur moderne: L'École des Ponts et Chaussées 1747-1851 (Paris, 1992), 76.
    • (1805) De l'Impuissance des Mathématiques Pour Assurer la Solidité des Batimens et Recherches sur la Construction des Ponts
    • Viel, C.-F.1
  • 135
    • 0040437433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Charles-François Viel, De l'impuissance des mathématiques pour assurer la solidité des batimens et Recherches sur la construction des ponts (Paris, 1805). For a general discussion of the debates accompanying the use of mathematics in the design of bridges, see Eda Kranakis, Constructing a bridge: An exploration of engineering culture, design, and research in nineteenth-century France and America (Cambridge, 1997); and Antoine Picon, L'invention de l'ingénieur moderne: L'École des Ponts et Chaussées 1747-1851 (Paris, 1992), 76.
    • (1997) Constructing a Bridge: An Exploration of Engineering Culture, Design, and Research in Nineteenth-century France and America
    • Kranakis, E.1
  • 136
    • 0011715234 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • Charles-François Viel, De l'impuissance des mathématiques pour assurer la solidité des batimens et Recherches sur la construction des ponts (Paris, 1805). For a general discussion of the debates accompanying the use of mathematics in the design of bridges, see Eda Kranakis, Constructing a bridge: An exploration of engineering culture, design, and research in nineteenth-century France and America (Cambridge, 1997); and Antoine Picon, L'invention de l'ingénieur moderne: L'École des Ponts et Chaussées 1747-1851 (Paris, 1992), 76.
    • (1992) L'Invention de l'Ingénieur Moderne: L'École des Ponts et Chaussées 1747-1851 , pp. 76
    • Picon, A.1
  • 137
    • 0041601192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 21
    • Heilbron notes, for example, that the Coffee House Physical Society "banned everything that smelt of mathematics", Heilbron, "Experimental natural philosophy" (ref. 21), 364. In Weighing imponderables (ref. 13), 31, he notes that at the end of the 18th century, the German textbook-writer F. A. C. Gren, "who had been brought up in the older qualitative, inclusive natural science ... no doubt felt menaced by the calculators". Other reactions are noted on pp. 147-9. For another example of an exchange over the appropriate use of mathematics in physics, see the discussion between Franz Ernst Newman and Ludwig Moser in Kathryn M. Olesko, Physics as a calling: Discipline and practice in the Königsberg seminar for physics (Ithaca, 1991), 93-95.
    • Experimental Natural Philosophy , pp. 364
    • Heilbron1
  • 138
    • 0043104075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 13
    • Heilbron notes, for example, that the Coffee House Physical Society "banned everything that smelt of mathematics", Heilbron, "Experimental natural philosophy" (ref. 21), 364. In Weighing imponderables (ref. 13), 31, he notes that at the end of the 18th century, the German textbook-writer F. A. C. Gren, "who had been brought up in the older qualitative, inclusive natural science ... no doubt felt menaced by the calculators". Other reactions are noted on pp. 147-9. For another example of an exchange over the appropriate use of mathematics in physics, see the discussion between Franz Ernst Newman and Ludwig Moser in Kathryn M. Olesko, Physics as a calling: Discipline and practice in the Königsberg seminar for physics (Ithaca, 1991), 93-95.
    • Weighing Imponderables , pp. 31
  • 139
    • 0003874482 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca
    • Heilbron notes, for example, that the Coffee House Physical Society "banned everything that smelt of mathematics", Heilbron, "Experimental natural philosophy" (ref. 21), 364. In Weighing imponderables (ref. 13), 31, he notes that at the end of the 18th century, the German textbook-writer F. A. C. Gren, "who had been brought up in the older qualitative, inclusive natural science ... no doubt felt menaced by the calculators". Other reactions are noted on pp. 147-9. For another example of an exchange over the appropriate use of mathematics in physics, see the discussion between Franz Ernst Newman and Ludwig Moser in Kathryn M. Olesko, Physics as a calling: Discipline and practice in the Königsberg seminar for physics (Ithaca, 1991), 93-95.
    • (1991) Physics as a Calling: Discipline and Practice in the Königsberg Seminar for Physics , pp. 93-95
    • Olesko, K.M.1
  • 140
    • 84977233757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The scientific field and the social conditions for the progress of reason
    • Pierre Bourdieu, "The scientific field and the social conditions for the progress of reason", Social science information, xiv/6 (1975), 19-47. The formation of a field necessarily implies a form of "boundary work" concerning the proper attribution of domains and methods to "physics', mathematics' or 'applied mathematics': including or excluding mathematical techniques in the study of physical phenomena was a way of imposing the legitimate definition of a field as well as the legitimate methods of inquiry. On boundary work, see Thomas F. Gieryn, Cultural boundaries of science (Chicago, 1999).
    • (1975) Social Science Information , vol.14 , Issue.6 , pp. 19-47
    • Bourdieu, P.1
  • 141
    • 84977233757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • Pierre Bourdieu, "The scientific field and the social conditions for the progress of reason", Social science information, xiv/6 (1975), 19-47. The formation of a field necessarily implies a form of "boundary work" concerning the proper attribution of domains and methods to "physics', mathematics' or 'applied mathematics': including or excluding mathematical techniques in the study of physical phenomena was a way of imposing the legitimate definition of a field as well as the legitimate methods of inquiry. On boundary work, see Thomas F. Gieryn, Cultural boundaries of science (Chicago, 1999).
    • (1999) Cultural Boundaries of Science
    • Gieryn, T.F.1
  • 142
    • 0042603271 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • Jean-Baptiste Biot, Traité de physique expérimentale et mathématique (Paris 1816), p. xi. On Biot, see Eugene Frankel, "J. B. Biot and the mathematization of experimental physics in Napoleonic France", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 33-72.
    • (1816) Traité de Physique Expérimentale et Mathématique
    • Biot, J.-B.1
  • 143
    • 84968130383 scopus 로고
    • J. B. Biot and the mathematization of experimental physics in Napoleonic France
    • Jean-Baptiste Biot, Traité de physique expérimentale et mathématique (Paris 1816), p. xi. On Biot, see Eugene Frankel, "J. B. Biot and the mathematization of experimental physics in Napoleonic France", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 33-72.
    • (1977) Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.8 , pp. 33-72
    • Frankel, E.1
  • 145
    • 0039692815 scopus 로고
    • Mechanical philosophy and the emergence of physics in Britain
    • J. D. Forbes to W. Whewell, 29 May 1831
    • J. D. Forbes to W. Whewell, 29 May 1831, cited by Crosbie Smith, "Mechanical philosophy and the emergence of physics in Britain", Annals of science, xxxiii (1976), 3-29, p. 25.
    • (1976) Annals of Science , vol.33 , pp. 3-29
    • Smith, C.1
  • 146
    • 0041601193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • J. D. Forbes to W. Whewell, 8 August 1833, op. cit. (ref. 88), 27
    • J. D. Forbes to W. Whewell, 8 August 1833, cited by Smith, op. cit. (ref. 88), 27. On Whewell's attitude towards the relation between physics and mathematics, see Harvey W. Becher, "William Whewell and Cambridge mathematics", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xi (1980), 1-48; Menachem Fish, "A philosopher's coming of age: A study of erotetic intellectual history", in Menachem Fish and Simon Schaffer (eds), William Whewell: A composite portrait (Cambridge, 1991), 31-66.
    • Smith1
  • 147
    • 84968240686 scopus 로고
    • William Whewell and Cambridge mathematics
    • J. D. Forbes to W. Whewell, 8 August 1833, cited by Smith, op. cit. (ref. 88), 27. On Whewell's attitude towards the relation between physics and mathematics, see Harvey W. Becher, "William Whewell and Cambridge mathematics", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xi (1980), 1-48; Menachem Fish, "A philosopher's coming of age: A study of erotetic intellectual history", in Menachem Fish and Simon Schaffer (eds), William Whewell: A composite portrait (Cambridge, 1991), 31-66.
    • (1980) Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.11 , pp. 1-48
    • Becher, H.W.1
  • 148
    • 0142198196 scopus 로고
    • A philosopher's coming of age: A study of erotetic intellectual history
    • Menachem Fish and Simon Schaffer (eds), Cambridge
    • J. D. Forbes to W. Whewell, 8 August 1833, cited by Smith, op. cit. (ref. 88), 27. On Whewell's attitude towards the relation between physics and mathematics, see Harvey W. Becher, "William Whewell and Cambridge mathematics", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xi (1980), 1-48; Menachem Fish, "A philosopher's coming of age: A study of erotetic intellectual history", in Menachem Fish and Simon Schaffer (eds), William Whewell: A composite portrait (Cambridge, 1991), 31-66.
    • (1991) William Whewell: A Composite Portrait , pp. 31-66
    • Fish, M.1
  • 151
    • 84914949584 scopus 로고
    • Different experimental lives: Michael Faraday and William Sturgeon
    • Iwan Rhys Morus, "Different experimental lives: Michael Faraday and William Sturgeon", History of science, xxx (1992), 1-28.
    • (1992) History of Science , vol.30 , pp. 1-28
    • Morus, I.R.1
  • 152
    • 0042102121 scopus 로고
    • On the conservation of force
    • April
    • M. Faraday, "On the conservation of force", Philosophical magazine, 4th ser., xiii, no. 86, April 1857, 225-39, p. 238.
    • (1857) Philosophical Magazine, 4th Ser. , vol.13 , Issue.86 , pp. 225-239
    • Faraday, M.1
  • 153
    • 4244176866 scopus 로고
    • On gravitation and the conservation of force
    • February
    • E. Brücke, "On gravitation and the conservation of force", Philosophical magazine, 4th ser., xv, no. 86, February 1858, 81-90, p. 82.
    • (1858) Philosophical Magazine, 4th Ser. , vol.15 , Issue.86 , pp. 81-90
    • Brücke, E.1
  • 154
    • 0043104077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 90), 429, 671
    • Harman, op. cit. (ref. 90), 429, 671.
    • Harman1
  • 155
    • 84968250191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From galvanism to electrodynamics: The transformation of German physics and its social context
    • On the physics discipline, see Kenneth L. Caneva, "From galvanism to electrodynamics: The transformation of German physics and its social context", Historical studies in the physical sciences, ix (1978), 63-169; David B. Wilson, "Experimentalists among the mathematicians: Physics in the Cambridge natural sciences tripos, 1851-1900", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xii (1982), 325-71; Olesko, op. cit. (ref. 84); Christa Jungnickel and Russell McKormach, Intellectual mastery of nature: Theoretical physics from Ohm to Einstein (Chicago, 1986); Roben Silliman, "Fresnel and the emergence of physics as a discipline", Historical studies in the physical sciences, iv (1974), 137-62; R. Sviedrys, "The rise of physics laboratories in Britain", Historical studies in the physical sciences, vii (1976), 405-36; D. Kevles, The physicists: The history of a scientific community in modern America (New York, 1978): Yves Gingras, Physics and the rise of scientific research in Canada (Montreal and Kingston, 1991).
    • (1978) Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.9 , pp. 63-169
    • Caneva, K.L.1
  • 156
    • 84968298414 scopus 로고
    • Experimentalists among the mathematicians: Physics in the Cambridge natural sciences tripos, 1851-1900
    • On the physics discipline, see Kenneth L. Caneva, "From galvanism to electrodynamics: The transformation of German physics and its social context", Historical studies in the physical sciences, ix (1978), 63-169; David B. Wilson, "Experimentalists among the mathematicians: Physics in the Cambridge natural sciences tripos, 1851-1900", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xii (1982), 325-71; Olesko, op. cit. (ref. 84); Christa Jungnickel and Russell McKormach, Intellectual mastery of nature: Theoretical physics from Ohm to Einstein (Chicago, 1986); Roben Silliman, "Fresnel and the emergence of physics as a discipline", Historical studies in the physical sciences, iv (1974), 137-62; R. Sviedrys, "The rise of physics laboratories in Britain", Historical studies in the physical sciences, vii (1976), 405-36; D. Kevles, The physicists: The history of a scientific community in modern America (New York, 1978): Yves Gingras, Physics and the rise of scientific research in Canada (Montreal and Kingston, 1991).
    • (1982) Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.12 , pp. 325-371
    • Wilson, D.B.1
  • 157
    • 84968250191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 84)
    • On the physics discipline, see Kenneth L. Caneva, "From galvanism to electrodynamics: The transformation of German physics and its social context", Historical studies in the physical sciences, ix (1978), 63-169; David B. Wilson, "Experimentalists among the mathematicians: Physics in the Cambridge natural sciences tripos, 1851-1900", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xii (1982), 325-71; Olesko, op. cit. (ref. 84); Christa Jungnickel and Russell McKormach, Intellectual mastery of nature: Theoretical physics from Ohm to Einstein (Chicago, 1986); Roben Silliman, "Fresnel and the emergence of physics as a discipline", Historical studies in the physical sciences, iv (1974), 137-62; R. Sviedrys, "The rise of physics laboratories in Britain", Historical studies in the physical sciences, vii (1976), 405-36; D. Kevles, The physicists: The history of a scientific community in modern America (New York, 1978): Yves Gingras, Physics and the rise of scientific research in Canada (Montreal and Kingston, 1991).
    • Olesko1
  • 158
    • 84968250191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • On the physics discipline, see Kenneth L. Caneva, "From galvanism to electrodynamics: The transformation of German physics and its social context", Historical studies in the physical sciences, ix (1978), 63-169; David B. Wilson, "Experimentalists among the mathematicians: Physics in the Cambridge natural sciences tripos, 1851-1900", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xii (1982), 325-71; Olesko, op. cit. (ref. 84); Christa Jungnickel and Russell McKormach, Intellectual mastery of nature: Theoretical physics from Ohm to Einstein (Chicago, 1986); Roben Silliman, "Fresnel and the emergence of physics as a discipline", Historical studies in the physical sciences, iv (1974), 137-62; R. Sviedrys, "The rise of physics laboratories in Britain", Historical studies in the physical sciences, vii (1976), 405-36; D. Kevles, The physicists: The history of a scientific community in modern America (New York, 1978): Yves Gingras, Physics and the rise of scientific research in Canada (Montreal and Kingston, 1991).
    • (1986) Intellectual Mastery of Nature: Theoretical Physics from Ohm to Einstein
    • Jungnickel, C.1    McKormach, R.2
  • 159
    • 84968188512 scopus 로고
    • Fresnel and the emergence of physics as a discipline
    • On the physics discipline, see Kenneth L. Caneva, "From galvanism to electrodynamics: The transformation of German physics and its social context", Historical studies in the physical sciences, ix (1978), 63-169; David B. Wilson, "Experimentalists among the mathematicians: Physics in the Cambridge natural sciences tripos, 1851-1900", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xii (1982), 325-71; Olesko, op. cit. (ref. 84); Christa Jungnickel and Russell McKormach, Intellectual mastery of nature: Theoretical physics from Ohm to Einstein (Chicago, 1986); Roben Silliman, "Fresnel and the emergence of physics as a discipline", Historical studies in the physical sciences, iv (1974), 137-62; R. Sviedrys, "The rise of physics laboratories in Britain", Historical studies in the physical sciences, vii (1976), 405-36; D. Kevles, The physicists: The history of a scientific community in modern America (New York, 1978): Yves Gingras, Physics and the rise of scientific research in Canada (Montreal and Kingston, 1991).
    • (1974) Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.4 , pp. 137-162
    • Silliman, R.1
  • 160
    • 84968082016 scopus 로고
    • The rise of physics laboratories in Britain
    • On the physics discipline, see Kenneth L. Caneva, "From galvanism to electrodynamics: The transformation of German physics and its social context", Historical studies in the physical sciences, ix (1978), 63-169; David B. Wilson, "Experimentalists among the mathematicians: Physics in the Cambridge natural sciences tripos, 1851-1900", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xii (1982), 325-71; Olesko, op. cit. (ref. 84); Christa Jungnickel and Russell McKormach, Intellectual mastery of nature: Theoretical physics from Ohm to Einstein (Chicago, 1986); Roben Silliman, "Fresnel and the emergence of physics as a discipline", Historical studies in the physical sciences, iv (1974), 137-62; R. Sviedrys, "The rise of physics laboratories in Britain", Historical studies in the physical sciences, vii (1976), 405-36; D. Kevles, The physicists: The history of a scientific community in modern America (New York, 1978): Yves Gingras, Physics and the rise of scientific research in Canada (Montreal and Kingston, 1991).
    • (1976) Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.7 , pp. 405-436
    • Sviedrys, R.1
  • 161
    • 84968250191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • On the physics discipline, see Kenneth L. Caneva, "From galvanism to electrodynamics: The transformation of German physics and its social context", Historical studies in the physical sciences, ix (1978), 63-169; David B. Wilson, "Experimentalists among the mathematicians: Physics in the Cambridge natural sciences tripos, 1851-1900", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xii (1982), 325-71; Olesko, op. cit. (ref. 84); Christa Jungnickel and Russell McKormach, Intellectual mastery of nature: Theoretical physics from Ohm to Einstein (Chicago, 1986); Roben Silliman, "Fresnel and the emergence of physics as a discipline", Historical studies in the physical sciences, iv (1974), 137-62; R. Sviedrys, "The rise of physics laboratories in Britain", Historical studies in the physical sciences, vii (1976), 405-36; D. Kevles, The physicists: The history of a scientific community in modern America (New York, 1978): Yves Gingras, Physics and the rise of scientific research in Canada (Montreal and Kingston, 1991).
    • (1978) The Physicists: the History of a Scientific Community in Modern America
    • Kevles, D.1
  • 162
    • 84968250191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Montreal and Kingston
    • On the physics discipline, see Kenneth L. Caneva, "From galvanism to electrodynamics: The transformation of German physics and its social context", Historical studies in the physical sciences, ix (1978), 63-169; David B. Wilson, "Experimentalists among the mathematicians: Physics in the Cambridge natural sciences tripos, 1851-1900", Historical studies in the physical sciences, xii (1982), 325-71; Olesko, op. cit. (ref. 84); Christa Jungnickel and Russell McKormach, Intellectual mastery of nature: Theoretical physics from Ohm to Einstein (Chicago, 1986); Roben Silliman, "Fresnel and the emergence of physics as a discipline", Historical studies in the physical sciences, iv (1974), 137-62; R. Sviedrys, "The rise of physics laboratories in Britain", Historical studies in the physical sciences, vii (1976), 405-36; D. Kevles, The physicists: The history of a scientific community in modern America (New York, 1978): Yves Gingras, Physics and the rise of scientific research in Canada (Montreal and Kingston, 1991).
    • (1991) Physics and the Rise of Scientific Research in Canada
    • Gingras, Y.1
  • 164
    • 0042102122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • James E. McLellan III, Science reorganized: Scientific societies in the eighteenth century (New York, 1985), 360 (his chap. 7 deals with tighter control of access to membership in scientific academies); on specialized scientific journals, see ibid., 257-9, and J. E. McLellan, "The scientific press in transition: Rozier's Journal and the scientific societies in the 1770s", Annals of science, xxxvi (1979), 425-419.
    • (1985) Science Reorganized: Scientific Societies in the Eighteenth Century , pp. 360
    • McLellan J.E. III1
  • 165
    • 0042102122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James E. McLellan III, Science reorganized: Scientific societies in the eighteenth century (New York, 1985), 360 (his chap. 7 deals with tighter control of access to membership in scientific academies); on specialized scientific journals, see ibid., 257-9, and J. E. McLellan, "The scientific press in transition: Rozier's Journal and the scientific societies in the 1770s", Annals of science, xxxvi (1979), 425-419.
    • Science Reorganized: Scientific Societies in the Eighteenth Century , pp. 257-259
  • 166
    • 0042102122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The scientific press in transition: Rozier's journal and the scientific societies in the 1770s
    • James E. McLellan III, Science reorganized: Scientific societies in the eighteenth century (New York, 1985), 360 (his chap. 7 deals with tighter control of access to membership in scientific academies); on specialized scientific journals, see ibid., 257-9, and J. E. McLellan, "The scientific press in transition: Rozier's Journal and the scientific societies in the 1770s", Annals of science, xxxvi (1979), 425-419.
    • (1979) Annals of Science , vol.36 , pp. 425-1419
    • McLellan, J.E.1
  • 168
    • 0004103093 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Pierre Brunet, L'introduction des théories de Newton en France au XVIIIe siècle: Avant 1738 (Paris, 1931); A. J. Aiton, The vortex theory of planetary motion (London, 1972); Henry Guerlac, Newton on the Continent (Ithaca, 1981), chap. 3; Alexandre Koyré, Newtonian studies (London, 1965).
    • (1972) The Vortex Theory of Planetary Motion
    • Aiton, A.J.1
  • 169
    • 0004013453 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, chap. 3
    • Pierre Brunet, L'introduction des théories de Newton en France au XVIIIe siècle: Avant 1738 (Paris, 1931); A. J. Aiton, The vortex theory of planetary motion (London, 1972); Henry Guerlac, Newton on the Continent (Ithaca, 1981), chap. 3; Alexandre Koyré, Newtonian studies (London, 1965).
    • (1981) Newton on the Continent
    • Guerlac, H.1
  • 170
    • 0003608719 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Pierre Brunet, L'introduction des théories de Newton en France au XVIIIe siècle: Avant 1738 (Paris, 1931); A. J. Aiton, The vortex theory of planetary motion (London, 1972); Henry Guerlac, Newton on the Continent (Ithaca, 1981), chap. 3; Alexandre Koyré, Newtonian studies (London, 1965).
    • (1965) Newtonian Studies
    • Koyré, A.1
  • 171
    • 0042603289 scopus 로고
    • Hassocks
    • For an excellent discussion of changing notions of explanation in the history of physics, see Stephen Gaukroger, Explanatory structures: Concepts and explanation in early physics and philosophy (Hassocks, 1978). For the case of mathematics, see Michael S. Mahoney, "Changing canons of mathematical and physical intelligibility in the later 17th century", Historia mathematica, ii (1984), 417-23.
    • (1978) Explanatory Structures: Concepts and Explanation in Early Physics and Philosophy
    • Gaukroger, S.1
  • 172
    • 0042603278 scopus 로고
    • Changing canons of mathematical and physical intelligibility in the later 17th century
    • For an excellent discussion of changing notions of explanation in the history of physics, see Stephen Gaukroger, Explanatory structures: Concepts and explanation in early physics and philosophy (Hassocks, 1978). For the case of mathematics, see Michael S. Mahoney, "Changing canons of mathematical and physical intelligibility in the later 17th century", Historia mathematica, ii (1984), 417-23.
    • (1984) Historia Mathematica , vol.2 , pp. 417-423
    • Mahoney, M.S.1
  • 173
    • 0041601168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 11), 142-5
    • For the different interpretations given by historians to the term 'mechanical philosophy", see Floris Cohen, op. cit. (ref. 11), 142-5. Here I mean by 'mechanical explanation' one that provides an efficient cause based on contact forces; two roads were open: if void was admitted, that force could be obtained through corpuscular interactions (as in Lesage's theory of gravitation); if void was excluded it could be through the action of a fluid (as in Euler's theory) or through the movement of corpuscules of different size filling all space as in Descartes's system. From this point of view, Newton's mathematization of gravitation was a demechanization of the world picture and not a mechanization as suggested by E. J. Dijksterhuis, The mechanization of the world picture (Princeton, 1986).
    • Cohen, F.1
  • 174
    • 0003959532 scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • For the different interpretations given by historians to the term 'mechanical philosophy", see Floris Cohen, op. cit. (ref. 11), 142-5. Here I mean by 'mechanical explanation' one that provides an efficient cause based on contact forces; two roads were open: if void was admitted, that force could be obtained through corpuscular interactions (as in Lesage's theory of gravitation); if void was excluded it could be through the action of a fluid (as in Euler's theory) or through the movement of corpuscules of different size filling all space as in Descartes's system. From this point of view, Newton's mathematization of gravitation was a demechanization of the world picture and not a mechanization as suggested by E. J. Dijksterhuis, The mechanization of the world picture (Princeton, 1986).
    • (1986) The Mechanization of the World Picture
    • Dijksterhuis, E.J.1
  • 175
    • 0042603267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Descartes as critic of Galileo
    • Butts and Pitt (eds), ref. 3
    • William R. Shea, "Descartes as critic of Galileo", in Butts and Pitt (eds), New perspectives on Galileo (ref. 3), 139-59.
    • New Perspectives on Galileo , pp. 139-159
    • Shea, W.R.1
  • 176
    • 84965861917 scopus 로고
    • The astronomer's role in the sixteenth century: A preliminary study
    • R. S. Westman, "The astronomer's role in the sixteenth century: A preliminary study", History of science, xviii (1980), 105-47; for a detailed analysis of the sixteenth-century debate on the relation between natural philosophy and astronomy and on the nature of astronomical explanation, see N. Jardine, The birth of history and philosophy of science: Kepler's "A defence of Tycho against Ursus" with essays on its provenance and significance, rev. edn (Cambridge, 1988).
    • (1980) History of Science , vol.18 , pp. 105-147
    • Westman, R.S.1
  • 179
    • 0004326921 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • On Newton's style of mathematical physics, see I. Bernard Cohen, The Newtonian revolution (Cambridge, 1980); P. A. Kroes, "Newton's mathematization of physics in retrospect", in P. B. Scheurer and G. Debrock (eds). Newton's scientific and philosophical legacy (Dordrecht, 1988), 253-67.
    • (1980) The Newtonian Revolution
    • Bernard Cohen, I.1
  • 180
    • 0043104080 scopus 로고
    • Newton's mathematization of physics in retrospect
    • P. B. Scheurer and G. Debrock (eds). Dordrecht
    • On Newton's style of mathematical physics, see I. Bernard Cohen, The Newtonian revolution (Cambridge, 1980); P. A. Kroes, "Newton's mathematization of physics in retrospect", in P. B. Scheurer and G. Debrock (eds). Newton's scientific and philosophical legacy (Dordrecht, 1988), 253-67.
    • (1988) Newton's Scientific and Philosophical Legacy , pp. 253-267
    • Kroes, P.A.1
  • 181
    • 0043104085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is a 'category mistake' from the point of view of the actors. For us of course, it is no longer a category mistake since we have accepted Newton's view of what physics is. The same applies to Kepler's "celestial physics".
  • 182
    • 84864908198 scopus 로고
    • 2 August
    • Journal des sçavans, 2 August 1688, 154; on the first reviews of the Principia, see I. B. Cohen, "The review of the first edition of Newton's Principia in the Acta eruditorium, with notes on the other reviews", in Harman and Shapiro (eds). The investigation of difficult things (ref. 9), 323-53.
    • (1688) Journal des Sçavans , pp. 154
  • 183
    • 0042603283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The review of the first edition of Newton's Principia in the Acta eruditorium, with notes on the other reviews
    • Harman and Shapiro (eds). ref. 9
    • Journal des sçavans, 2 August 1688, 154; on the first reviews of the Principia, see I. B. Cohen, "The review of the first edition of Newton's Principia in the Acta eruditorium, with notes on the other reviews", in Harman and Shapiro (eds). The investigation of difficult things (ref. 9), 323-53.
    • The Investigation of Difficult Things , pp. 323-353
    • Cohen, I.B.1
  • 184
    • 0043104092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 56), 199
    • Cited by Schier, op. cit. (ref. 56), 199.
    • Schier1
  • 185
    • 0041601200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that the actors used the categories of "Cartesians" and "Newtonians" in a variety of ways. A common feature to all is, I think, that the first must involve a mechanical explanation of all phenomena in the sense defined above (ref. 101 ) while the other can content itself with a mathematical formulation and leave unanswered the question of the mechanical action.
  • 187
    • 0042603285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 56), 58
    • Schier, op. cit. (ref. 56), 58.
    • Schier1
  • 188
    • 0043104081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 89
    • Ibid., 89.
  • 189
    • 0041601205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 54), 13
    • Castel. op. cit. (ref. 54), 13.
    • Castel1
  • 191
    • 0042102126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 54), 52
    • Castel, op. cit. (ref. 54), 52.
    • Castel1
  • 192
    • 0042102125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 94
    • Ibid., 94.
  • 193
    • 0041601140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 95, italics in the original
    • Ibid., 95, italics in the original.
  • 194
    • 0042603291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 97
    • Ibid., 97.
  • 195
    • 0042102135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 98-99
    • Ibid., 98-99.
  • 196
    • 0042102136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 121
    • Ibid., 121.
  • 197
    • 0043104089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 121
    • Ibid., 121.
  • 198
    • 0042102134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 253
    • Ibid., 253.
  • 199
    • 0041601207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 304
    • Ibid., 304.
  • 200
    • 0041601206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 302
    • Ibid., 302.
  • 201
    • 0042603292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 348
    • Ibid., 348.
  • 202
    • 0043104091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction aux recherches sur la précession des équinoxes et sur la nutation de l'axe de la Terre dans le système newtonien
    • ref. 65
    • D'Alembert, "Introduction aux recherches sur la précession des équinoxes et sur la nutation de l'axe de la Terre dans le système newtonien", in Oeuvres complètes (ref. 65), i, 437-50, p. 450.
    • Oeuvres Complètes , vol.1 , pp. 437-450
    • D'Alembert1
  • 206
    • 0041601172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • B. le Bovier de Fontenelle, Oeuvres (Paris, 1996), vii, "Préface de l'éditeur", 377-82, p. 377.
    • Préface de l'Éditeur , pp. 377-382
  • 208
    • 0042603260 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • Baron de Marivetz et Goussier, Physique du monde (Paris, 1780), v, 57, cited by Bachelard, La formation de l'esprit scientifique (ref. 30), 231.
    • (1780) Physique du Monde , vol.5 , pp. 57
    • De Marivetz, B.1    Goussier2
  • 210
    • 0042603258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 127), i, 341
    • D'Alembert, op. cit. (ref. 127), i, 341. This views recalls Max Planck's when he wrote: "A new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing its opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it"; Planck's own scientific autobiography and other papers, transl. by F. Gaynor (New York, 1949), 33-34.
    • D'Alembert1
  • 211
    • 0003618988 scopus 로고
    • A new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing its opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it
    • transl. by F. Gaynor New York
    • D'Alembert, op. cit. (ref. 127), i, 341. This views recalls Max Planck's when he wrote: "A new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing its opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it"; Planck's own scientific autobiography and other papers, transl. by F. Gaynor (New York, 1949), 33-34.
    • (1949) Planck's Own Scientific Autobiography and Other Papers , pp. 33-34
    • Planck's, M.1
  • 213
    • 0042102080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 6 ), 216
    • Diderot, op. cit. (ref. 6 ), 216.
    • Diderot1
  • 216
    • 0042102077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 135
    • Biot. Traité (ref. 135), p. xiv.
    • Traité
    • Biot1
  • 217
  • 219
    • 0043104029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit. (ref. 90), i, 671
    • Harman (ed.), op. cit. (ref. 90), i, 671.
    • Harman1
  • 220
    • 0043104027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 671
    • Ibid., 671.
  • 221
    • 0042102078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 672
    • Ibid., 672.
  • 223
    • 0042102079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • University College London, Fleming Coll. Ms Add 122/37. My thanks to Sungook Hong for giving me access to his notes taken from this manuscript.
  • 227
    • 84989462410 scopus 로고
    • Mechanical explanations at the end of the nineteenth century
    • On the meaning of the use of Lagrangian formulations, see Martin J. Klein, "Mechanical explanations at the end of the nineteenth century", Centaurus, xvii (1972), 58-82;
    • (1972) Centaurus , vol.17 , pp. 58-82
    • Klein, M.J.1
  • 228
    • 22644434940 scopus 로고
    • Lagrangian formulation and mechanical explanation
    • Mario Bunge, "Lagrangian formulation and mechanical explanation", American journal of physics, xxv (1957), 211-18.
    • (1957) American Journal of Physics , vol.25 , pp. 211-218
    • Bunge, M.1
  • 231
    • 0043104025 scopus 로고
    • Considerations on gravity
    • H. A. Lorentz, "Considerations on gravity", Amsterdam Koninklijke Akademie Physica, ii (1900). 559-74. On Le Sage, see Samuel Aronson, "The gravitational theory of Georges-Louis Le Sage", The natural philosopher, iii ( 1964), 53-74.
    • (1900) Amsterdam Koninklijke Akademie Physica , vol.2 , pp. 559-574
    • Lorentz, H.A.1
  • 232
    • 0040705135 scopus 로고
    • The gravitational theory of Georges-Louis Le Sage
    • H. A. Lorentz, "Considerations on gravity", Amsterdam Koninklijke Akademie Physica, ii (1900). 559-74. On Le Sage, see Samuel Aronson, "The gravitational theory of Georges-Louis Le Sage", The natural philosopher, iii ( 1964), 53-74.
    • (1964) The Natural Philosopher , vol.3 , pp. 53-74
    • Aronson, S.1
  • 233
    • 0041601132 scopus 로고
    • Gravitation and nineteenth-century physical worldviews
    • P. B. Scheurer and G. Debrock (eds), Dordrecht
    • For the period from 1700 to 1900, very few proposed explanations of gravity were published in journals controlled by the physics community. I will later publish a more detailed history of the various attempts at a mechanical explanation of gravity. For a brief survey, see F. H. van Lunteren, "Gravitation and nineteenth-century physical worldviews", in P. B. Scheurer and G. Debrock (eds), Newton's scientific and philosophical legacy (Dordrecht, 1988), 161-73. Outside the field of physics, attempts at providing a mechanical explanation still goes on; for relatively recent examples, see Dewey B. Larson, Beyond Newton: An explanation of gravity (Portland, 1964); René de Puymorin, L'origine de la gravitation (Paris, 1975).
    • (1988) Newton's Scientific and Philosophical Legacy , pp. 161-173
    • Van Lunteren, F.H.1
  • 234
    • 0041601134 scopus 로고
    • Portland
    • For the period from 1700 to 1900, very few proposed explanations of gravity were published in journals controlled by the physics community. I will later publish a more detailed history of the various attempts at a mechanical explanation of gravity. For a brief survey, see F. H. van Lunteren, "Gravitation and nineteenth-century physical worldviews", in P. B. Scheurer and G. Debrock (eds), Newton's scientific and philosophical legacy (Dordrecht, 1988), 161-73. Outside the field of physics, attempts at providing a mechanical explanation still goes on; for relatively recent examples, see Dewey B. Larson, Beyond Newton: An explanation of gravity (Portland, 1964); René de Puymorin, L'origine de la gravitation (Paris, 1975).
    • (1964) Beyond Newton: An Explanation of Gravity
    • Larson, D.B.1
  • 235
    • 0041601116 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • For the period from 1700 to 1900, very few proposed explanations of gravity were published in journals controlled by the physics community. I will later publish a more detailed history of the various attempts at a mechanical explanation of gravity. For a brief survey, see F. H. van Lunteren, "Gravitation and nineteenth-century physical worldviews", in P. B. Scheurer and G. Debrock (eds), Newton's scientific and philosophical legacy (Dordrecht, 1988), 161-73. Outside the field of physics, attempts at providing a mechanical explanation still goes on; for relatively recent examples, see Dewey B. Larson, Beyond Newton: An explanation of gravity (Portland, 1964); René de Puymorin, L'origine de la gravitation (Paris, 1975).
    • (1975) L'Origine de la Gravitation
    • De Puymorin, R.1
  • 236
    • 0004075791 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • H. A. Lorentz, The theory of the electron (New York, 1953), 43; cited by M. Jammer, Concepts of mass in contemporary physics and philosophy (Princeton, 2000), 36.
    • (1953) The Theory of the Electron , pp. 43
    • Lorentz, H.A.1
  • 238
    • 0013051966 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass., and his more recent Concepts of mass in contemporary physics and philosophy (ref. 151)
    • For the conceptual evolution of the concept of mass, see Max Jammer, Concepts of mass in classical and modern physics (Cambridge, Mass., 1961) and his more recent Concepts of mass in contemporary physics and philosophy (ref. 151).
    • (1961) Concepts of Mass in Classical and Modern Physics
    • Jammer, M.1
  • 240
    • 84980078034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences
    • E. P. Wigner, "The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences", Communications on pure and applied mathematics, xiii (1960), 1-14. For more examples of such preoccupations by scientists and for a philosophical approach to the question, see Mark Steiner, The application of mathematics as a philosophical problem (Cambridge, Mass., 1998). Husserl also provided a philosophical analysis of the meaning of the mathematization of nature in Edmund Husserl, The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology (Evanston, 1970), 21-59.
    • (1960) Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics , vol.13 , pp. 1-14
    • Wigner, E.P.1
  • 241
    • 84980078034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.
    • E. P. Wigner, "The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences", Communications on pure and applied mathematics, xiii (1960), 1-14. For more examples of such preoccupations by scientists and for a philosophical approach to the question, see Mark Steiner, The application of mathematics as a philosophical problem (Cambridge, Mass., 1998). Husserl also provided a philosophical analysis of the meaning of the mathematization of nature in Edmund Husserl, The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology (Evanston, 1970), 21-59.
    • (1998) The Application of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem
    • Steiner, M.1
  • 242
    • 84980078034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evanston
    • E. P. Wigner, "The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences", Communications on pure and applied mathematics, xiii (1960), 1-14. For more examples of such preoccupations by scientists and for a philosophical approach to the question, see Mark Steiner, The application of mathematics as a philosophical problem (Cambridge, Mass., 1998). Husserl also provided a philosophical analysis of the meaning of the mathematization of nature in Edmund Husserl, The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology (Evanston, 1970), 21-59.
    • (1970) The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology , pp. 21-59
    • Husserl, E.1
  • 243
    • 0043104009 scopus 로고
    • Redefining anschaulichkeif
    • Abner Shimony and Herman Feshbach (eds). Cambridge, Mass.
    • Arthur I. Miller, "Redefining anschaulichkeif", in Abner Shimony and Herman Feshbach (eds). Physics and natural philosophy (Cambridge, Mass., 1982), 376-411; Daniel Serwer, "Unmechanischer zwang: Pauli, Heisenberg, and the rejection of the mechanical atom, 1923-1925", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 189-256.
    • (1982) Physics and Natural Philosophy , pp. 376-411
    • Miller, A.I.1
  • 244
    • 84968126531 scopus 로고
    • Unmechanischer zwang: Pauli, Heisenberg, and the rejection of the mechanical atom, 1923-1925
    • Arthur I. Miller, "Redefining anschaulichkeif", in Abner Shimony and Herman Feshbach (eds). Physics and natural philosophy (Cambridge, Mass., 1982), 376-411; Daniel Serwer, "Unmechanischer zwang: Pauli, Heisenberg, and the rejection of the mechanical atom, 1923-1925", Historical studies in the physical sciences, viii (1977), 189-256.
    • (1977) Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences , vol.8 , pp. 189-256
    • Serwer, D.1
  • 246
    • 0003766184 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Bohm's view are now undergoing a revival; see Peter R. Holland, The quantum theory of motion (Cambridge, 1993), and Russell Olwell, "Physical isolation and marginalization in physics: David Bohm's cold war exile", Isis, xc (1999), 738-56.
    • (1993) The Quantum Theory of Motion
    • Holland, P.R.1
  • 247
    • 0042603173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Physical isolation and marginalization in physics: David Bohm's cold war exile
    • Bohm's view are now undergoing a revival; see Peter R. Holland, The quantum theory of motion (Cambridge, 1993), and Russell Olwell, "Physical isolation and marginalization in physics: David Bohm's cold war exile", Isis, xc (1999), 738-56.
    • (1999) Isis , vol.90 , pp. 738-756
    • Olwell, R.1
  • 249
    • 0042603194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • issue of 2 March
    • For very recent examples, see Nature, cccciv, issue of 2 March 2000, 28-29; Science, cclxxxvii, issue of 7 January 2000, 49-50.
    • (2000) Nature , vol.404 , pp. 28-29
  • 250
    • 0042102069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • issue of 7 January
    • For very recent examples, see Nature, cccciv, issue of 2 March 2000, 28-29; Science, cclxxxvii, issue of 7 January 2000, 49-50.
    • (2000) Science , vol.287 , pp. 49-50
  • 251
    • 0043104008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chemistry through invariant theory? James Joseph Sylvester's mathematization of the atomic theory
    • Paul H. Therman and Karen Hunger Parshall (eds). Dordrecht
    • See, for example, Karen Hunger Parshall, "Chemistry through invariant theory? James Joseph Sylvester's mathematization of the atomic theory", in Paul H. Therman and Karen Hunger Parshall (eds). Experiencing nature (Dordrecht, 1997), 81-111; Ana Simoes and Kostas Gavroglu, "Quantum chemistry qua applied mathematics: The contributions of Charles Alfred Coulson (1910-1974)", Historical studies in the physical and biological sciences, xxix (1999), 363-406, and idem, "Quantum chemistry in Great Britain: Developing a mathematical framework for quantum chemistry", Studies in history and philosophy of modern physics, xxxi (2000), 511-48; Giorgio Israel, "The emergence of biomathematics and the case of population dynamics: A revival of mechanical reductionism and darwinism", Science in context, vi (1993), 469-509.
    • (1997) Experiencing Nature , pp. 81-111
    • Parshall, K.H.1
  • 252
    • 0040115543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quantum chemistry qua applied mathematics: The contributions of Charles Alfred Coulson (1910-1974)
    • See, for example, Karen Hunger Parshall, "Chemistry through invariant theory? James Joseph Sylvester's mathematization of the atomic theory", in Paul H. Therman and Karen Hunger Parshall (eds). Experiencing nature (Dordrecht, 1997), 81-111; Ana Simoes and Kostas Gavroglu, "Quantum chemistry qua applied mathematics: The contributions of Charles Alfred Coulson (1910-1974)", Historical studies in the physical and biological sciences, xxix (1999), 363-406, and idem, "Quantum chemistry in Great Britain: Developing a mathematical framework for quantum chemistry", Studies in history and philosophy of modern physics, xxxi (2000), 511-48; Giorgio Israel, "The emergence of biomathematics and the case of population dynamics: A revival of mechanical reductionism and darwinism", Science in context, vi (1993), 469-509.
    • (1999) Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences , vol.29 , pp. 363-406
    • Simoes, A.1    Gavroglu, K.2
  • 253
    • 33846583510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quantum chemistry in Great Britain: Developing a mathematical framework for quantum chemistry
    • See, for example, Karen Hunger Parshall, "Chemistry through invariant theory? James Joseph Sylvester's mathematization of the atomic theory", in Paul H. Therman and Karen Hunger Parshall (eds). Experiencing nature (Dordrecht, 1997), 81-111; Ana Simoes and Kostas Gavroglu, "Quantum chemistry qua applied mathematics: The contributions of Charles Alfred Coulson (1910-1974)", Historical studies in the physical and biological sciences, xxix (1999), 363-406, and idem, "Quantum chemistry in Great Britain: Developing a mathematical framework for quantum chemistry", Studies in history and philosophy of modern physics, xxxi (2000), 511-48; Giorgio Israel, "The emergence of biomathematics and the case of population dynamics: A revival of mechanical reductionism and darwinism", Science in context, vi (1993), 469-509.
    • (2000) Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics , vol.31 , pp. 511-548
    • Simoes, A.1    Gavroglu, K.2
  • 254
    • 0027662265 scopus 로고
    • The emergence of biomathematics and the case of population dynamics: A revival of mechanical reductionism and darwinism
    • See, for example, Karen Hunger Parshall, "Chemistry through invariant theory? James Joseph Sylvester's mathematization of the atomic theory", in Paul H. Therman and Karen Hunger Parshall (eds). Experiencing nature (Dordrecht, 1997), 81-111; Ana Simoes and Kostas Gavroglu, "Quantum chemistry qua applied mathematics: The contributions of Charles Alfred Coulson (1910-1974)", Historical studies in the physical and biological sciences, xxix (1999), 363-406, and idem, "Quantum chemistry in Great Britain: Developing a mathematical framework for quantum chemistry", Studies in history and philosophy of modern physics, xxxi (2000), 511-48; Giorgio Israel, "The emergence of biomathematics and the case of population dynamics: A revival of mechanical reductionism and darwinism", Science in context, vi (1993), 469-509.
    • (1993) Science in Context , vol.6 , pp. 469-509
    • Israel, G.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.