메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 40, Issue 1, 2002, Pages 63-89

Voluntarism and Early Modern Science

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0042529291     PISSN: 00732753     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/007327530204000103     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (66)

References (203)
  • 1
    • 0010963519 scopus 로고
    • The Christian doctrine of creation and the rise of modern natural science
    • M. B. Foster, "The Christian doctrine of creation and the rise of modern natural science", Mind, xliii (1934), 446-68, reprinted in Science and religious belief: A selection of recent history studies, ed. by C. A. Russell (London, 1975), 294-315.
    • (1934) Mind , vol.43 , pp. 446-468
    • Foster, M.B.1
  • 3
    • 84918500869 scopus 로고
    • Christian theology and the Newtonian science: The rise of the concept of laws of nature
    • Francis Oakley, "Christian theology and the Newtonian science: The rise of the concept of laws of nature", Church history, xxx (1961), 433-57, p. 438.
    • (1961) Church History , vol.30 , pp. 433-457
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 4
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boyle's conception of nature
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1972) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.33 , pp. 523-542
    • McGuire, J.E.1
  • 5
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grand Rapids
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1977) Religious Origins of Modern Science
    • Klaaren, E.1
  • 6
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1978) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.39 , pp. 271-283
    • Heimann, P.1
  • 7
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1991) The Janus Faces of Genius: the Role of Alchemy in Newton's Thought
    • Dobbs, B.J.T.1
  • 8
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1994) Divine Will and the Mechanical Philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on Contingency and Necessity in the Created World
    • Osler, M.1
  • 9
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Henry More versus Robert Boyle
    • ed. by Sarah Hutton Dordrecht
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1990) Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary Essays , pp. 55-76
    • Henry, J.1
  • 10
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dordrecht
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1990) Essays on the Context, Nature, and Influence of Isaac Newton's Theology
    • Force, J.E.1    Popkin, R.H.2
  • 11
    • 0007227969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1997) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.58 , pp. 265-287
    • Malet, A.1
  • 12
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism
    • ed. by Margaret Osler Cambridge
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1991) Atoms, Pneuma, and Tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic Themes in European Thought
    • Osler, M.1
  • 13
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature
    • ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin Cambridge
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1991) Philosophy Science, and Religion, 1640-1700
    • Osler, M.1
  • 14
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths
    • ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene Chicago
    • J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; Eugene Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science (Grand Rapids, 1977); Peter Heimann, "Voluntarism and immanence: Conceptions of nature in eighteenth-century thought", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxix (1978), 271-83; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus faces of genius: The role of alchemy in Newton's thought (Cambridge, 1991); Margaret Osler, Divine will and the mechanical philosophy: Gassendi and Descartes on contingency and necessity in the created world (Cambridge, 1994). See also J. Henry, "Henry More versus Robert Boyle", in Henry More (1614-87): Tercentenary essays, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Dordrecht, 1990), 55-76; James E. Force and Richard H. Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Isaac Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990); Antoni Malet, "Isaac Barrow on the mathematization of nature: Theological voluntarism and the rise of geometrical optics", Journal of the history of ideas, lviii (1997), 265-87; Margaret Osler, "Fortune, fate, and divination: Gassendi's voluntarist theology and the baptism of Epicureanism", in Atoms, pneuma, and tranquility: Epicurean and Stoic themes in European thought, ed. by Margaret Osler (Cambridge, 1991); Idem, "The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle's philosophy of nature", in Philosophy science, and religion, 1640-1700, ed. by Richard Ashcroft, Richard Kroll and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1991); "Divine will and mathematical truths: Gassendi and Descartes on the status of eternal truths", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago, 1996), 145-58.
    • (1996) Descartes and His Contemporaries , pp. 145-158
  • 15
    • 0042813990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking with Clark
    • John Bossy, "Thinking with Clark", Past and present, clxvi (2000), 242-50, p. 244.
    • (2000) Past and Present , vol.166 , pp. 242-250
    • Bossy, J.1
  • 16
    • 85034526765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus Oakley: "from Ockham's fundamental insistence upon the omnipotence and freedom of God follows, not only his ethical and legal voluntarism, but also his empiricism" ("Christian theology and the Newtonian science" (ref. 2), 442). Foster also makes this logic explicit in "Creation and the rise of science" (ref. 1), 311
    • Thus Oakley: "from Ockham's fundamental insistence upon the omnipotence and freedom of God follows, not only his ethical and legal voluntarism, but also his empiricism" ("Christian theology and the Newtonian science" (ref. 2), 442). Foster also makes this logic explicit in "Creation and the rise of science" (ref. 1), 311.
  • 17
    • 0346313103 scopus 로고
    • De legibus, ac Deo legislatore
    • I.v.8, ed. by James Scott 2 vols, Washington
    • Francis Suárez, De legibus, ac Deo legislatore (1612), I.v.8, in Three works of Francis Suárez, ed. by James Scott (2 vols, Washington, 1944), i, 26f.
    • (1612) Three Works of Francis Suárez , vol.1
    • Suárez, F.1
  • 18
    • 0041311506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tilburg
    • These medieval thinkers did not designate themselves 'voluntarists', neither did their early-modern successors. Until quite recently, 'voluntarism' has meant 'doxastic voluntarism' - the view according to which choice plays a significant role in belief. This position is contrasted with 'evidentialism', according to which belief is determined by evidence. Theological voluntarism in this sense is another term for fideism. See, e.g., Belief, cognition and the will, ed. by Anthonie Meijers (Tilburg, 1999). The article "Voluntarism" by Richard Taylor in The encyclopaedia of philosophy associates this view with Ockham and Kierkegaard and notes that voluntarism is associated with "various forms of fideism". Encyclopaedia of philosophy, ed. by Paul Edwards (8 vols, New York, 1967), viii, 271. Also stressing the link with fideism, the more recent Cambridge dictionary of philosophy (1995) offers this definition of "theological voluntarism": "A special case of doxastic voluntarism ... which implies that religious belief requires a substantial element of choice; the evidence alone cannot decide the issue. This is a view that is closely associated with Pascal, Kierkegaard, and James." Cambridge dictionary of philosophy, ed. by Robert Audi (Cambridge, 1995), s.v. "Voluntarism", 845a.
    • (1999) Belief, Cognition and the Will
    • Meijers, A.1
  • 19
    • 85034523217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Voluntarism
    • These medieval thinkers did not designate themselves 'voluntarists', neither did their early-modern successors. Until quite recently, 'voluntarism' has meant 'doxastic voluntarism' - the view according to which choice plays a significant role in belief. This position is contrasted with 'evidentialism', according to which belief is determined by evidence. Theological voluntarism in this sense is another term for fideism. See, e.g., Belief, cognition and the will, ed. by Anthonie Meijers (Tilburg, 1999). The article "Voluntarism" by Richard Taylor in The encyclopaedia of philosophy associates this view with Ockham and Kierkegaard and notes that voluntarism is associated with "various forms of fideism". Encyclopaedia of philosophy, ed. by Paul Edwards (8 vols, New York, 1967), viii, 271. Also stressing the link with fideism, the more recent Cambridge dictionary of philosophy (1995) offers this definition of "theological voluntarism": "A special case of doxastic voluntarism ... which implies that religious belief requires a substantial element of choice; the evidence alone cannot decide the issue. This is a view that is closely associated with Pascal, Kierkegaard, and James." Cambridge dictionary of philosophy, ed. by Robert Audi (Cambridge, 1995), s.v. "Voluntarism", 845a.
    • The Encyclopaedia of Philosophy
    • Taylor, R.1
  • 20
    • 85034525192 scopus 로고
    • 8 vols, New York
    • These medieval thinkers did not designate themselves 'voluntarists', neither did their early-modern successors. Until quite recently, 'voluntarism' has meant 'doxastic voluntarism' - the view according to which choice plays a significant role in belief. This position is contrasted with 'evidentialism', according to which belief is determined by evidence. Theological voluntarism in this sense is another term for fideism. See, e.g., Belief, cognition and the will, ed. by Anthonie Meijers (Tilburg, 1999). The article "Voluntarism" by Richard Taylor in The encyclopaedia of philosophy associates this view with Ockham and Kierkegaard and notes that voluntarism is associated with "various forms of fideism". Encyclopaedia of philosophy, ed. by Paul Edwards (8 vols, New York, 1967), viii, 271. Also stressing the link with fideism, the more recent Cambridge dictionary of philosophy (1995) offers this definition of "theological voluntarism": "A special case of doxastic voluntarism ... which implies that religious belief requires a substantial element of choice; the evidence alone cannot decide the issue. This is a view that is closely associated with Pascal, Kierkegaard, and James." Cambridge dictionary of philosophy, ed. by Robert Audi (Cambridge, 1995), s.v. "Voluntarism", 845a.
    • (1967) Encyclopaedia of Philosophy , vol.8 , pp. 271
    • Edwards, P.1
  • 21
    • 0004055950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. by Robert Audi Cambridge, s.v. "Voluntarism", 845a
    • These medieval thinkers did not designate themselves 'voluntarists', neither did their early-modern successors. Until quite recently, 'voluntarism' has meant 'doxastic voluntarism' - the view according to which choice plays a significant role in belief. This position is contrasted with 'evidentialism', according to which belief is determined by evidence. Theological voluntarism in this sense is another term for fideism. See, e.g., Belief, cognition and the will, ed. by Anthonie Meijers (Tilburg, 1999). The article "Voluntarism" by Richard Taylor in The encyclopaedia of philosophy associates this view with Ockham and Kierkegaard and notes that voluntarism is associated with "various forms of fideism". Encyclopaedia of philosophy, ed. by Paul Edwards (8 vols, New York, 1967), viii, 271. Also stressing the link with fideism, the more recent Cambridge dictionary of philosophy (1995) offers this definition of "theological voluntarism": "A special case of doxastic voluntarism ... which implies that religious belief requires a substantial element of choice; the evidence alone cannot decide the issue. This is a view that is closely associated with Pascal, Kierkegaard, and James." Cambridge dictionary of philosophy, ed. by Robert Audi (Cambridge, 1995), s.v. "Voluntarism", 845a.
    • (1995) Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy
    • Pascal1    Kierkegaard2    James3
  • 22
    • 0042813989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 17. Elsewhere, however, Osler defines intellectualism as "the view that there are some elements of necessity in the creation" (p. 11). This is a presumed implication of intellectualism, rather than a definition of it.
    • Divine Will , pp. 17
    • Osler1
  • 25
    • 0041311503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Christianity and early modern science: The Foster thesis reconsidered
    • ed. by David N. Livingstone, D. G. Hart and Mark A. Noll Oxford
    • In an article also critical of the voluntarism and science thesis, Edward B. Davis makes a good case that Galileo, too, is an important exception to the voluntarism and science thesis. "Christianity and early modern science: The Foster thesis reconsidered", in Evangelicals in historical perspective, ed. by David N. Livingstone, D. G. Hart and Mark A. Noll (Oxford, 1999), 75-95. Davis points out that Galileo was clearly not averse to experimentation, yet expressed little interest in speculations about the divine will. He posited the existence of at least some necessary relations in nature, stressing that natural truths must follow "necessarily, in such a way that it would be impossible for them to take place in any other manner". Dialogue concerning the two chief world systems, transl. by Stillman Drake (Berkeley, 1953), 406. Elsewhere he insisted that mathematical demonstrations could be produced only for properties that are "eternal and necessary". Discourses on the two new sciences, transl. by Stillman Drake (Madison, 1974), 13.
    • (1999) Evangelicals in Historical Perspective , pp. 75-95
  • 26
    • 84969275668 scopus 로고
    • transl. by Stillman Drake Berkeley
    • In an article also critical of the voluntarism and science thesis, Edward B. Davis makes a good case that Galileo, too, is an important exception to the voluntarism and science thesis. "Christianity and early modern science: The Foster thesis reconsidered", in Evangelicals in historical perspective, ed. by David N. Livingstone, D. G. Hart and Mark A. Noll (Oxford, 1999), 75-95. Davis points out that Galileo was clearly not averse to experimentation, yet expressed little interest in speculations about the divine will. He posited the existence of at least some necessary relations in nature, stressing that natural truths must follow "necessarily, in such a way that it would be impossible for them to take place in any other manner". Dialogue concerning the two chief world systems, transl. by Stillman Drake (Berkeley, 1953), 406. Elsewhere he insisted that mathematical demonstrations could be produced only for properties that are "eternal and necessary". Discourses on the two new sciences, transl. by Stillman Drake (Madison, 1974), 13.
    • (1953) Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems , pp. 406
  • 27
    • 0003954555 scopus 로고
    • transl. by Stillman Drake Madison
    • In an article also critical of the voluntarism and science thesis, Edward B. Davis makes a good case that Galileo, too, is an important exception to the voluntarism and science thesis. "Christianity and early modern science: The Foster thesis reconsidered", in Evangelicals in historical perspective, ed. by David N. Livingstone, D. G. Hart and Mark A. Noll (Oxford, 1999), 75-95. Davis points out that Galileo was clearly not averse to experimentation, yet expressed little interest in speculations about the divine will. He posited the existence of at least some necessary relations in nature, stressing that natural truths must follow "necessarily, in such a way that it would be impossible for them to take place in any other manner". Dialogue concerning the two chief world systems, transl. by Stillman Drake (Berkeley, 1953), 406. Elsewhere he insisted that mathematical demonstrations could be produced only for properties that are "eternal and necessary". Discourses on the two new sciences, transl. by Stillman Drake (Madison, 1974), 13.
    • (1974) Discourses on the Two New Sciences , pp. 13
  • 28
    • 85034523027 scopus 로고
    • Descartes to Mersenne, 15 April 1630, transl. by J. Cottingham et al. 3 vols, Cambridge
    • Descartes to Mersenne, 15 April 1630, in The philosophical writings of Descartes, transl. by J. Cottingham et al. (3 vols, Cambridge, 1984-91), iii, 23.
    • (1984) The Philosophical Writings of Descartes , vol.3 , pp. 23
  • 31
  • 33
    • 85034523307 scopus 로고
    • Paris, cols. 3313f. (s.v. "Volontarisme, en Dieu")
    • The Dictionnaire de théologie Catholique identifies Descartes as a voluntarist and a case is made for the direct influence of scholastic voluntarism on Descartes. Texts of Duns Scotus, Gabriel Biel, and Jean Gerson are placed side by side with Descartes's declarations of voluntarism, such that the case for a direct influence is difficult to deny. Dictionnaire de theologie Catholique (Paris, 1941), xv, cols. 3313f. (s.v. "Volontarisme, en Dieu").
    • (1941) Dictionnaire de Theologie Catholique , vol.15
  • 34
    • 85034528231 scopus 로고
    • The voluntaristic Christianity of Blaise Pascal was set in opposition to the rationalistic humanism of René Descartes
    • New York, s.v. "Voluntarism"
    • Doxastic voluntarists hold that belief is an act of the will. This appears to be the sense in which the expression is used in the New Catholic encyclopaedia, which sets out the lineage of voluntarist philosophers beginning with Augustine and progressing through Scotus and Pascal to Kant. The state of play in the early modern period is represented thus: "The voluntaristic Christianity of Blaise Pascal was set in opposition to the rationalistic humanism of René Descartes." New Catholic encyclopaedia (New York, 1967), xiv, s.v. "Voluntarism".
    • (1967) New Catholic Encyclopaedia , vol.14
  • 35
    • 33747394607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • The Cambridge Platonist Ralph Cudworth, for example, contested Descartes's claim that "moral good and evil" and "the essences of things depend upon an arbitrary will in God", asserting the intellectualist position that the divine will was "guided and determined by wisdom and truth". Treatise concerning eternal and immutable morality with A treatise of freewill, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Cambridge, 1996), 22, 24, 26. Interestingly, Oakley also notes that Cudworth regarded Descartes as "one of the principal advocates" of voluntarism. "Christian theology and the Newtonian science" (ref. 2), 441. See also Leibniz: "However, we should not imagine, as some do, that since the eternal truths depend on God, they are arbitrary and depend on his will, as Descartes appears to have held, and after him Mr. Poiret." G. W. Leibniz, The principles of philosophy, or, the monadology, 46, in Philosophical essays, ed. and transl. by Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber, (Cambridge, 1989), I.29, 218. Boyle also regarded Descartes as a voluntarist and Peter Anstey goes so far as to suggest that Boyle's own voluntarism (if he is so to be characterized) was possibly a consequence of Cartesian influence. Peter Anstey, 'The Christian Virtuoso and the Reformers: Are there Reformation roots to Boyle's natural philosophy?', forthcoming; Boyle, Some considerations about the reconcileableness of reason and religion (London, 1675), 25f. Cf. Robert Desgabets, Supplément à la philosophie de M. Descartes, Opuscule 6, in Oeuvres philosophiques (Amsterdam, 1983), 249: Susan James, "Reason, the passions, and the good life", in The Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy, ed. by Daniel Garber and Michael Ayers (2 vols, Cambridge, 1998), ii, 1358-96, p. 1371.
    • (1996) Treatise Concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality with a Treatise of Freewill , pp. 22
    • Hutton, S.1
  • 36
    • 84909012326 scopus 로고
    • The principles of philosophy, or, the monadology
    • 46, ed. and transl. by Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber, Cambridge, I.29
    • The Cambridge Platonist Ralph Cudworth, for example, contested Descartes's claim that "moral good and evil" and "the essences of things depend upon an arbitrary will in God", asserting the intellectualist position that the divine will was "guided and determined by wisdom and truth". Treatise concerning eternal and immutable morality with A treatise of freewill, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Cambridge, 1996), 22, 24, 26. Interestingly, Oakley also notes that Cudworth regarded Descartes as "one of the principal advocates" of voluntarism. "Christian theology and the Newtonian science" (ref. 2), 441. See also Leibniz: "However, we should not imagine, as some do, that since the eternal truths depend on God, they are arbitrary and depend on his will, as Descartes appears to have held, and after him Mr. Poiret." G. W. Leibniz, The principles of philosophy, or, the monadology, 46, in Philosophical essays, ed. and transl. by Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber, (Cambridge, 1989), I.29, 218. Boyle also regarded Descartes as a voluntarist and Peter Anstey goes so far as to suggest that Boyle's own voluntarism (if he is so to be characterized) was possibly a consequence of Cartesian influence. Peter Anstey, 'The Christian Virtuoso and the Reformers: Are there Reformation roots to Boyle's natural philosophy?', forthcoming; Boyle, Some considerations about the reconcileableness of reason and religion (London, 1675), 25f. Cf. Robert Desgabets, Supplément à la philosophie de M. Descartes, Opuscule 6, in Oeuvres philosophiques (Amsterdam, 1983), 249: Susan James, "Reason, the passions, and the good life", in The Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy, ed. by Daniel Garber and Michael Ayers (2 vols, Cambridge, 1998), ii, 1358-96, p. 1371.
    • (1989) Philosophical Essays , pp. 218
    • Leibniz, G.W.1
  • 37
    • 25544449812 scopus 로고
    • London
    • The Cambridge Platonist Ralph Cudworth, for example, contested Descartes's claim that "moral good and evil" and "the essences of things depend upon an arbitrary will in God", asserting the intellectualist position that the divine will was "guided and determined by wisdom and truth". Treatise concerning eternal and immutable morality with A treatise of freewill, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Cambridge, 1996), 22, 24, 26. Interestingly, Oakley also notes that Cudworth regarded Descartes as "one of the principal advocates" of voluntarism. "Christian theology and the Newtonian science" (ref. 2), 441. See also Leibniz: "However, we should not imagine, as some do, that since the eternal truths depend on God, they are arbitrary and depend on his will, as Descartes appears to have held, and after him Mr. Poiret." G. W. Leibniz, The principles of philosophy, or, the monadology, 46, in Philosophical essays, ed. and transl. by Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber, (Cambridge, 1989), I.29, 218. Boyle also regarded Descartes as a voluntarist and Peter Anstey goes so far as to suggest that Boyle's own voluntarism (if he is so to be characterized) was possibly a consequence of Cartesian influence. Peter Anstey, 'The Christian Virtuoso and the Reformers: Are there Reformation roots to Boyle's natural philosophy?', forthcoming; Boyle, Some considerations about the reconcileableness of reason and religion (London, 1675), 25f. Cf. Robert Desgabets, Supplément à la philosophie de M. Descartes, Opuscule 6, in Oeuvres philosophiques (Amsterdam, 1983), 249: Susan James, "Reason, the passions, and the good life", in The Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy, ed. by Daniel Garber and Michael Ayers (2 vols, Cambridge, 1998), ii, 1358-96, p. 1371.
    • (1675) Some Considerations about the Reconcileableness of Reason and Religion
    • Boyle1
  • 38
    • 85034526581 scopus 로고
    • Supplément à la philosophie de M. Descartes
    • Opuscule 6, Amsterdam
    • The Cambridge Platonist Ralph Cudworth, for example, contested Descartes's claim that "moral good and evil" and "the essences of things depend upon an arbitrary will in God", asserting the intellectualist position that the divine will was "guided and determined by wisdom and truth". Treatise concerning eternal and immutable morality with A treatise of freewill, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Cambridge, 1996), 22, 24, 26. Interestingly, Oakley also notes that Cudworth regarded Descartes as "one of the principal advocates" of voluntarism. "Christian theology and the Newtonian science" (ref. 2), 441. See also Leibniz: "However, we should not imagine, as some do, that since the eternal truths depend on God, they are arbitrary and depend on his will, as Descartes appears to have held, and after him Mr. Poiret." G. W. Leibniz, The principles of philosophy, or, the monadology, 46, in Philosophical essays, ed. and transl. by Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber, (Cambridge, 1989), I.29, 218. Boyle also regarded Descartes as a voluntarist and Peter Anstey goes so far as to suggest that Boyle's own voluntarism (if he is so to be characterized) was possibly a consequence of Cartesian influence. Peter Anstey, 'The Christian Virtuoso and the Reformers: Are there Reformation roots to Boyle's natural philosophy?', forthcoming; Boyle, Some considerations about the reconcileableness of reason and religion (London, 1675), 25f. Cf. Robert Desgabets, Supplément à la philosophie de M. Descartes, Opuscule 6, in Oeuvres philosophiques (Amsterdam, 1983), 249: Susan James, "Reason, the passions, and the good life", in The Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy, ed. by Daniel Garber and Michael Ayers (2 vols, Cambridge, 1998), ii, 1358-96, p. 1371.
    • (1983) Oeuvres Philosophiques , pp. 249
    • Desgabets, R.1
  • 39
    • 84932637259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reason, the passions, and the good life
    • ed. by Daniel Garber and Michael Ayers 2 vols, Cambridge
    • The Cambridge Platonist Ralph Cudworth, for example, contested Descartes's claim that "moral good and evil" and "the essences of things depend upon an arbitrary will in God", asserting the intellectualist position that the divine will was "guided and determined by wisdom and truth". Treatise concerning eternal and immutable morality with A treatise of freewill, ed. by Sarah Hutton (Cambridge, 1996), 22, 24, 26. Interestingly, Oakley also notes that Cudworth regarded Descartes as "one of the principal advocates" of voluntarism. "Christian theology and the Newtonian science" (ref. 2), 441. See also Leibniz: "However, we should not imagine, as some do, that since the eternal truths depend on God, they are arbitrary and depend on his will, as Descartes appears to have held, and after him Mr. Poiret." G. W. Leibniz, The principles of philosophy, or, the monadology, 46, in Philosophical essays, ed. and transl. by Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber, (Cambridge, 1989), I.29, 218. Boyle also regarded Descartes as a voluntarist and Peter Anstey goes so far as to suggest that Boyle's own voluntarism (if he is so to be characterized) was possibly a consequence of Cartesian influence. Peter Anstey, 'The Christian Virtuoso and the Reformers: Are there Reformation roots to Boyle's natural philosophy?', forthcoming; Boyle, Some considerations about the reconcileableness of reason and religion (London, 1675), 25f. Cf. Robert Desgabets, Supplément à la philosophie de M. Descartes, Opuscule 6, in Oeuvres philosophiques (Amsterdam, 1983), 249: Susan James, "Reason, the passions, and the good life", in The Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy, ed. by Daniel Garber and Michael Ayers (2 vols, Cambridge, 1998), ii, 1358-96, p. 1371.
    • (1998) The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-century Philosophy , vol.2 , pp. 1358-1396
    • James, S.1
  • 40
    • 85071074948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Descartes opticien
    • ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton London
    • See, e.g., John Schuster, "Descartes opticien", in Descartes' natural philosophy, ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton (London, 2000), 258-312, and "Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618-1634", Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, 1977, esp. pp. 622-47; Martha Bolton, "Universals, essences, and abstract entities", in Cambridge history of seventeenth- century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 178-211, p. 197; John Etchemendy, "The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 5-42, esp. pp. 32-39; Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, "Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 105-23; T. M. Lennon, "Pandora: or essence and reference", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 159-81, p. 180; Jean-Luc Marion, Sur l'ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris, 1981), 220; "Volontarisme, en Dieu" (ref. 17). This brief list shows that the identification of Descartes as a voluntarist is not a peculiarity of Anglo-American interpreters who are of analytical persuasion, as Osler suggests, Divine will (ref. 3), 146.
    • (2000) Descartes' Natural Philosophy , pp. 258-312
    • Schuster, J.1
  • 41
    • 0342439623 scopus 로고
    • Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, esp.
    • See, e.g., John Schuster, "Descartes opticien", in Descartes' natural philosophy, ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton (London, 2000), 258-312, and "Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618-1634", Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, 1977, esp. pp. 622-47; Martha Bolton, "Universals, essences, and abstract entities", in Cambridge history of seventeenth- century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 178-211, p. 197; John Etchemendy, "The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 5-42, esp. pp. 32-39; Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, "Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 105-23; T. M. Lennon, "Pandora: or essence and reference", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 159-81, p. 180; Jean-Luc Marion, Sur l'ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris, 1981), 220; "Volontarisme, en Dieu" (ref. 17). This brief list shows that the identification of Descartes as a voluntarist is not a peculiarity of Anglo-American interpreters who are of analytical persuasion, as Osler suggests, Divine will (ref. 3), 146.
    • (1977) Descartes and the Scientific Revolution, 1618-1634 , pp. 622-647
  • 42
    • 84858209401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Universals, essences, and abstract entities
    • (ref. 19)
    • See, e.g., John Schuster, "Descartes opticien", in Descartes' natural philosophy, ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton (London, 2000), 258-312, and "Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618-1634", Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, 1977, esp. pp. 622-47; Martha Bolton, "Universals, essences, and abstract entities", in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 178-211, p. 197; John Etchemendy, "The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 5-42, esp. pp. 32-39; Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, "Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 105-23; T. M. Lennon, "Pandora: or essence and reference", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 159-81, p. 180; Jean-Luc Marion, Sur l'ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris, 1981), 220; "Volontarisme, en Dieu" (ref. 17). This brief list shows that the identification of Descartes as a voluntarist is not a peculiarity of Anglo-American interpreters who are of analytical persuasion, as Osler suggests, Divine will (ref. 3), 146.
    • Cambridge History of Seventeenth-century Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 178-211
    • Bolton, M.1
  • 43
    • 0042312894 scopus 로고
    • The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore
    • Amsterdam
    • See, e.g., John Schuster, "Descartes opticien", in Descartes' natural philosophy, ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton (London, 2000), 258-312, and "Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618-1634", Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, 1977, esp. pp. 622-47; Martha Bolton, "Universals, essences, and abstract entities", in Cambridge history of seventeenth- century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 178-211, p. 197; John Etchemendy, "The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 5-42, esp. pp. 32-39; Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, "Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 105-23; T. M. Lennon, "Pandora: or essence and reference", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 159-81, p. 180; Jean-Luc Marion, Sur l'ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris, 1981), 220; "Volontarisme, en Dieu" (ref. 17). This brief list shows that the identification of Descartes as a voluntarist is not a peculiarity of Anglo-American interpreters who are of analytical persuasion, as Osler suggests, Divine will (ref. 3), 146.
    • (1981) Studia Cartesiana , vol.2 , pp. 5-42
    • Etchemendy, J.1
  • 44
    • 0042312862 scopus 로고
    • Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne
    • Amsterdam
    • See, e.g., John Schuster, "Descartes opticien", in Descartes' natural philosophy, ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton (London, 2000), 258-312, and "Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618-1634", Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, 1977, esp. pp. 622-47; Martha Bolton, "Universals, essences, and abstract entities", in Cambridge history of seventeenth- century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 178-211, p. 197; John Etchemendy, "The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 5-42, esp. pp. 32-39; Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, "Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 105-23; T. M. Lennon, "Pandora: or essence and reference", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 159-81, p. 180; Jean-Luc Marion, Sur l'ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris, 1981), 220; "Volontarisme, en Dieu" (ref. 17). This brief list shows that the identification of Descartes as a voluntarist is not a peculiarity of Anglo-American interpreters who are of analytical persuasion, as Osler suggests, Divine will (ref. 3), 146.
    • (1981) Studia Cartesiana , vol.2 , pp. 105-123
    • Rodis-Lewis, G.1
  • 45
    • 0042312852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pandora: Or essence and reference
    • ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3)
    • See, e.g., John Schuster, "Descartes opticien", in Descartes' natural philosophy, ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton (London, 2000), 258-312, and "Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618-1634", Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, 1977, esp. pp. 622-47; Martha Bolton, "Universals, essences, and abstract entities", in Cambridge history of seventeenth- century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 178-211, p. 197; John Etchemendy, "The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 5-42, esp. pp. 32-39; Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, "Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 105-23; T. M. Lennon, "Pandora: or essence and reference", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 159-81, p. 180; Jean-Luc Marion, Sur l'ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris, 1981), 220; "Volontarisme, en Dieu" (ref. 17). This brief list shows that the identification of Descartes as a voluntarist is not a peculiarity of Anglo-American interpreters who are of analytical persuasion, as Osler suggests, Divine will (ref. 3), 146.
    • Descartes and His Contemporaries , pp. 159-181
    • Lennon, T.M.1
  • 46
    • 0042813928 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • See, e.g., John Schuster, "Descartes opticien", in Descartes' natural philosophy, ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton (London, 2000), 258-312, and "Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618-1634", Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, 1977, esp. pp. 622-47; Martha Bolton, "Universals, essences, and abstract entities", in Cambridge history of seventeenth- century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 178-211, p. 197; John Etchemendy, "The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 5-42, esp. pp. 32-39; Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, "Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 105-23; T. M. Lennon, "Pandora: or essence and reference", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 159-81, p. 180; Jean-Luc Marion, Sur l'ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris, 1981), 220; "Volontarisme, en Dieu" (ref. 17). This brief list shows that the identification of Descartes as a voluntarist is not a peculiarity of Anglo-American interpreters who are of analytical persuasion, as Osler suggests, Divine will (ref. 3), 146.
    • (1981) Sur L'ontologie Grise de Descartes , pp. 220
    • Marion, J.-L.1
  • 47
    • 85034522418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 17
    • See, e.g., John Schuster, "Descartes opticien", in Descartes' natural philosophy, ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton (London, 2000), 258-312, and "Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618-1634", Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, 1977, esp. pp. 622-47; Martha Bolton, "Universals, essences, and abstract entities", in Cambridge history of seventeenth- century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 178-211, p. 197; John Etchemendy, "The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 5-42, esp. pp. 32-39; Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, "Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 105-23; T. M. Lennon, "Pandora: or essence and reference", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 159-81, p. 180; Jean-Luc Marion, Sur l'ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris, 1981), 220; "Volontarisme, en Dieu" (ref. 17). This brief list shows that the identification of Descartes as a voluntarist is not a peculiarity of Anglo-American interpreters who are of analytical persuasion, as Osler suggests, Divine will (ref. 3), 146.
    • Volontarisme, en Dieu
  • 48
    • 0042813989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • See, e.g., John Schuster, "Descartes opticien", in Descartes' natural philosophy, ed. by S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster and J. Sutton (London, 2000), 258-312, and "Descartes and the scientific revolution, 1618-1634", Ph.D. Diss., Princeton University, 1977, esp. pp. 622-47; Martha Bolton, "Universals, essences, and abstract entities", in Cambridge history of seventeenth- century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 178-211, p. 197; John Etchemendy, "The Cartesian circle: Circulus ex tempore", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 5-42, esp. pp. 32-39; Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, "Polémiques sur la création des possibles et sur l'impossible dans l'école cartésienne", in Studia cartesiana (Amsterdam, 1981), ii, 105-23; T. M. Lennon, "Pandora: or essence and reference", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 159-81, p. 180; Jean-Luc Marion, Sur l'ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris, 1981), 220; "Volontarisme, en Dieu" (ref. 17). This brief list shows that the identification of Descartes as a voluntarist is not a peculiarity of Anglo-American interpreters who are of analytical persuasion, as Osler suggests, Divine will (ref. 3), 146.
    • Divine will , pp. 146
  • 49
    • 85034524540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Descartes to Mersenne, ref. 12
    • Descartes to Mersenne, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), iii, 23.
    • Philosophical Writings , vol.3 , pp. 23
  • 51
    • 0042312906 scopus 로고
    • Descartes on the creation of eternal truths
    • It is possible to think of Descartes expressing, somewhat vaguely, a doctrine of iterated modalities, which distinguishes necessary truths about necessary beings from necessary truths about contingent beings. For this, and alternative readings see E. M. Curley, "Descartes on the creation of eternal truths", The philosophical review, xciii (1984), 569-97; Harry Frankfurt, "Descartes on the creation of eternal truths", The philosophical review, lxxxvi (1977), 36-57; Thomas M. Lennon, "The Cartesian dialectic of creation", in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 331-62.
    • (1984) The Philosophical Review , vol.93 , pp. 569-597
    • Curley, E.M.1
  • 52
    • 0041812136 scopus 로고
    • Descartes on the creation of eternal truths
    • It is possible to think of Descartes expressing, somewhat vaguely, a doctrine of iterated modalities, which distinguishes necessary truths about necessary beings from necessary truths about contingent beings. For this, and alternative readings see E. M. Curley, "Descartes on the creation of eternal truths", The philosophical review, xciii (1984), 569-97; Harry Frankfurt, "Descartes on the creation of eternal truths", The philosophical review, lxxxvi (1977), 36-57; Thomas M. Lennon, "The Cartesian dialectic of creation", in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 331-62.
    • (1977) The Philosophical Review , vol.86 , pp. 36-57
    • Frankfurt, H.1
  • 53
    • 0041577685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Cartesian dialectic of creation
    • ref. 19
    • It is possible to think of Descartes expressing, somewhat vaguely, a doctrine of iterated modalities, which distinguishes necessary truths about necessary beings from necessary truths about contingent beings. For this, and alternative readings see E. M. Curley, "Descartes on the creation of eternal truths", The philosophical review, xciii (1984), 569-97; Harry Frankfurt, "Descartes on the creation of eternal truths", The philosophical review, lxxxvi (1977), 36-57; Thomas M. Lennon, "The Cartesian dialectic of creation", in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 331-62.
    • Cambridge History of Seventeenth-century Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 331-362
    • Lennon, T.M.1
  • 54
    • 0041311498 scopus 로고
    • Apologia compendiaria
    • ed. by William Huffman London
    • Robert Fludd, Apologia compendiaria, in Robert Fludd: Essential readings, ed. by William Huffman (London, 1992), 46.
    • (1992) Robert Fludd: Essential Readings , pp. 46
    • Fludd, R.1
  • 55
    • 0041775477 scopus 로고
    • Some considerations touching the usefulness of natural philosophy
    • ed. by Thomas Birch 6 vols, London
    • Robert Boyle, Some considerations touching the usefulness of natural philosophy, in The works of the honourable Robert Boyle, ed. by Thomas Birch (6 vols, London, 1722), ii, 1-246, p. 61.
    • (1722) The Works of the Honourable Robert Boyle , vol.2 , pp. 1-246
    • Boyle, R.1
  • 56
    • 85034524289 scopus 로고
    • A new organon
    • 1.65, ed. by James Spedding, Robert Ellis and Douglas Heath 14 vols, London
    • Bacon, A new organon, 1.65, in The works of Francis Bacon, ed. by James Spedding, Robert Ellis and Douglas Heath (14 vols, London, 1857-74), iv, 66. Cf. Advancement of learning, ed. by Arthur Johnston (Oxford, 1974), II.xxv.16 (pp. 207f.).
    • (1857) The Works of Francis Bacon , vol.4 , pp. 66
    • Bacon1
  • 57
    • 0003934483 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, II.xxv.16
    • Bacon, A new organon, 1.65, in The works of Francis Bacon, ed. by James Spedding, Robert Ellis and Douglas Heath (14 vols, London, 1857-74), iv, 66. Cf. Advancement of learning, ed. by Arthur Johnston (Oxford, 1974), II.xxv.16 (pp. 207f.).
    • (1974) Advancement of Learning
    • Johnston, A.1
  • 58
    • 84966610036 scopus 로고
    • Amsterdam
    • Pierre Poiret. L'oeconomie divine (Amsterdam, 1687); English translation, The divine economy; or, an universal system of the works and purposes of God (6 vols, London, 1713). See T. M. Lennon's discussion of Poiret's position in "The Cartesian dialectic of creation", in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 349-50.
    • (1687) L'oeconomie Divine
    • Poiret, P.1
  • 59
    • 0042312904 scopus 로고
    • English translation, 6 vols, London
    • Pierre Poiret. L'oeconomie divine (Amsterdam, 1687); English translation, The divine economy; or, an universal system of the works and purposes of God (6 vols, London, 1713). See T. M. Lennon's discussion of Poiret's position in "The Cartesian dialectic of creation", in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 349-50.
    • (1713) The Divine Economy; Or, an Universal System of the Works and Purposes of God
  • 60
    • 85034522669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Cartesian dialectic of creation
    • ref. 19
    • Pierre Poiret. L'oeconomie divine (Amsterdam, 1687); English translation, The divine economy; or, an universal system of the works and purposes of God (6 vols, London, 1713). See T. M. Lennon's discussion of Poiret's position in "The Cartesian dialectic of creation", in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 349-50.
    • Cambridge History of Seventeenth-century Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 349-350
  • 61
    • 85034524106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Usefulness of natural philosophy
    • ref. 25
    • Boyle, for example, allowed some role for divine inspiration, albeit combined with the necessary experimental labours. He thought that from time to time God had inspired "Heroicke Spirits" who wrought some required revolution in theology or natural philosophy. Usefulness of natural philosophy, in Works (ref. 25), ii, 61. Boyle also thought that corpuscularian philosophy was "knowable by the light of nature, improved by the information of the scriptures". The excellency of theology, in Works (ref. 25), iv, 18. Henry More had for a time thought Descartes to have been divinely inspired, and considered the Cartesian philosophy to have been a restatement of the "physiology" which Moses had recorded in the book of Genesis. A defence of the three-fold cabbala, in A collection of several philosophical writings (London, 1662), 79-104. Part of the background to these ideas was the view, widespread during the Middle Ages and Renaissance, that Adam had enjoyed an encyclopaedic knowledge of nature. The task of the sciences was to re-establish this knowledge. Adamic science was presumably of contingent truths yet was unlikely to have been accumulated through the methods of empirical research, making divine inspiration the most likely source of his knowledge. Thus Aquinas: "The first man had knowledge of all things by divinely infused species." Summa theologiae 1a. 94, 3.
    • Works , vol.2 , pp. 61
  • 62
    • 0043272031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The excellency of theology
    • ref. 25
    • Boyle, for example, allowed some role for divine inspiration, albeit combined with the necessary experimental labours. He thought that from time to time God had inspired "Heroicke Spirits" who wrought some required revolution in theology or natural philosophy. Usefulness of natural philosophy, in Works (ref. 25), ii, 61. Boyle also thought that corpuscularian philosophy was "knowable by the light of nature, improved by the information of the scriptures". The excellency of theology, in Works (ref. 25), iv, 18. Henry More had for a time thought Descartes to have been divinely inspired, and considered the Cartesian philosophy to have been a restatement of the "physiology" which Moses had recorded in the book of Genesis. A defence of the three-fold cabbala, in A collection of several philosophical writings (London, 1662), 79-104. Part of the background to these ideas was the view, widespread during the Middle Ages and Renaissance, that Adam had enjoyed an encyclopaedic knowledge of nature. The task of the sciences was to re-establish this knowledge. Adamic science was presumably of contingent truths yet was unlikely to have been accumulated through the methods of empirical research, making divine inspiration the most likely source of his knowledge. Thus Aquinas: "The first man had knowledge of all things by divinely infused species." Summa theologiae 1a. 94, 3.
    • Works , vol.4 , pp. 18
  • 63
    • 0041812138 scopus 로고
    • A defence of the three-fold cabbala
    • London
    • Boyle, for example, allowed some role for divine inspiration, albeit combined with the necessary experimental labours. He thought that from time to time God had inspired "Heroicke Spirits" who wrought some required revolution in theology or natural philosophy. Usefulness of natural philosophy,
    • (1662) A Collection of Several Philosophical Writings , pp. 79-104
  • 64
    • 84952768170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The first man had knowledge of all things by divinely infused species
    • Boyle, for example, allowed some role for divine inspiration, albeit combined with the necessary experimental labours. He thought that from time to time God had inspired "Heroicke Spirits" who wrought some required revolution in theology or natural philosophy. Usefulness of natural philosophy, in Works (ref. 25), ii, 61. Boyle also thought that corpuscularian philosophy was "knowable by the light of nature, improved by the information of the scriptures". The excellency of theology, in Works (ref. 25), iv, 18. Henry More had for a time thought Descartes to have been divinely inspired, and considered the Cartesian philosophy to have been a restatement of the "physiology" which Moses had recorded in the book of Genesis. A defence of the three-fold cabbala, in A collection of several philosophical writings (London, 1662), 79-104. Part of the background to these ideas was the view, widespread during the Middle Ages and Renaissance, that Adam had enjoyed an encyclopaedic knowledge of nature. The task of the sciences was to re-establish this knowledge. Adamic science was presumably of contingent truths yet was unlikely to have been accumulated through the methods of empirical research, making divine inspiration the most likely source of his knowledge. Thus Aquinas: "The first man had knowledge of all things by divinely infused species." Summa theologiae 1a. 94, 3.
    • Summa Theologiae , vol.1 A , pp. 94
    • Aquinas, T.1
  • 65
    • 0041812137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas on Necessity
    • Hence Aquinas used 'necessary' in a number of different senses. See J. J. MacIntosh, "Aquinas on Necessity", American Catholic philosophical quarterly, lxxii (1998), 371-404.
    • (1998) American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly , vol.72 , pp. 371-404
    • MacIntosh, J.J.1
  • 66
    • 0004055950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • s.v. "contingency".
    • 2O"), despite being true in all possible worlds, can only be known a posteriori. See Saul Kripke, Naming and necessity (Cambridge, Mass., 1980). While seventeenth-century thinkers did not trouble themselves with metaphysical necessity, there was some understanding of the difference between logical and nomic necessity. Malebranche's occasionalism arose out of his view that nomically necessary relations were actually logically necessary, because only in the case of God is it impossible to conceive of his willing something and that something not eventuating. See Steven Nadler, "Malebranche on causation", in The Cambridge companion to Malebranche, ed. by Steven Nadler (Cambridge, 2000), 112-38. Hume was subsequently to deny that laws of nature were in any genuine sense necessary.
    • Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy
  • 67
    • 85047316500 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • 2O"), despite being true in all possible worlds, can only be known a posteriori. See Saul Kripke, Naming and necessity (Cambridge, Mass., 1980). While seventeenth-century thinkers did not trouble themselves with metaphysical necessity, there was some understanding of the difference between logical and nomic necessity. Malebranche's occasionalism arose out of his view that nomically necessary relations were actually logically necessary, because only in the case of God is it impossible to conceive of his willing something and that something not eventuating. See Steven Nadler, "Malebranche on causation", in The Cambridge companion to Malebranche, ed. by Steven Nadler (Cambridge, 2000), 112-38. Hume was subsequently to deny that laws of nature were in any genuine sense necessary.
    • (1983) What Is a Law of Nature?
    • Armstrong, D.M.1
  • 68
    • 0004178922 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.
    • 2O"), despite being true in all possible worlds, can only be known a posteriori. See Saul Kripke, Naming and necessity (Cambridge, Mass., 1980). While seventeenth-century thinkers did not trouble themselves with metaphysical necessity, there was some understanding of the difference between logical and nomic necessity. Malebranche's occasionalism arose out of his view that nomically necessary relations were actually logically necessary, because only in the case of God is it impossible to conceive of his willing something and that something not eventuating. See Steven Nadler, "Malebranche on causation", in The Cambridge companion to Malebranche, ed. by Steven Nadler (Cambridge, 2000), 112-38. Hume was subsequently to deny that laws of nature were in any genuine sense necessary.
    • (1980) Naming and Necessity
    • Kripke, S.1
  • 69
    • 0042813931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Malebranche on causation
    • ed. by Steven Nadler Cambridge
    • 2O"), despite being true in all possible worlds, can only be known a posteriori. See Saul Kripke, Naming and necessity (Cambridge, Mass., 1980). While seventeenth-century thinkers did not trouble themselves with metaphysical necessity, there was some understanding of the difference between logical and nomic necessity. Malebranche's occasionalism arose out of his view that nomically necessary relations were actually logically necessary, because only in the case of God is it impossible to conceive of his willing something and that something not eventuating. See Steven Nadler, "Malebranche on causation", in The Cambridge companion to Malebranche, ed. by Steven Nadler (Cambridge, 2000), 112-38. Hume was subsequently to deny that laws of nature were in any genuine sense necessary.
    • (2000) The Cambridge Companion to Malebranche , pp. 112-138
    • Nadler, S.1
  • 72
    • 0347798520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Syntagma philosophicum
    • 6 vols, Lyons
    • Pierre Gassendi, Syntagma philosophicum, in Opera omnia (6 vols, Lyons, 1658), i, 323; Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 57.
    • (1658) Opera Omnia , vol.1 , pp. 323
    • Gassendi, P.1
  • 73
    • 0042813989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • Pierre Gassendi, Syntagma philosophicum, in Opera omnia (6 vols, Lyons, 1658), i, 323; Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 57.
    • Divine Will , pp. 57
    • Osler1
  • 75
    • 85034521731 scopus 로고
    • Maker of heaven and earth
    • (Sermon XII), 3 vols, London
    • Isaac Barrow, "Maker of heaven and earth" (Sermon XII), in Theological works (3 vols, London, 1885), ii, 303.
    • (1885) Theological Works , vol.2 , pp. 303
    • Barrow, I.1
  • 76
    • 85034525853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MS Yahuda 21, fol. 1r
    • Newton, MS Yahuda 21, fol. 1r. Cf.: "it must be agreed that God, by the sole action of thinking and willing, can prevent a body from penetrating any space defined by Certain limits." Unpublished scientific papers of Isaac Newton, ed. and transl. by A. Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall (Cambridge, 1962), 139. For the association of this view with Newton's voluntarism, see James Force, "Newton's God of dominion", in James Force and Richard Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990), 85f., and E. B. Davis, "Newton's rejection of the Newtonian world view", Science and Christian belief, iii (1991), 103-17.
    • Newton1
  • 77
    • 0010856401 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Newton, MS Yahuda 21, fol. 1r. Cf.: "it must be agreed that God, by the sole action of thinking and willing, can prevent a body from penetrating any space defined by Certain limits." Unpublished scientific papers of Isaac Newton, ed. and transl. by A. Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall (Cambridge, 1962), 139. For the association of this view with Newton's voluntarism, see James Force, "Newton's God of dominion", in James Force and Richard Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990), 85f., and E. B. Davis, "Newton's rejection of the Newtonian world view", Science and Christian belief, iii (1991), 103-17.
    • (1962) Unpublished Scientific Papers of Isaac Newton , pp. 139
    • Rupert Hall, A.1    Hall, M.B.2
  • 78
    • 0346380707 scopus 로고
    • Newton's God of dominion
    • James Force and Richard Popkin, Dordrecht
    • Newton, MS Yahuda 21, fol. 1r. Cf.: "it must be agreed that God, by the sole action of thinking and willing, can prevent a body from penetrating any space defined by Certain limits." Unpublished scientific papers of Isaac Newton, ed. and transl. by A. Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall (Cambridge, 1962), 139. For the association of this view with Newton's voluntarism, see James Force, "Newton's God of dominion", in James Force and Richard Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990), 85f., and E. B. Davis, "Newton's rejection of the Newtonian world view", Science and Christian belief, iii (1991), 103-17.
    • (1990) Essays on the Context, Nature, and Influence of Newton's Theology
    • Force, J.1
  • 79
    • 77957264900 scopus 로고
    • Newton's rejection of the Newtonian world view
    • Newton, MS Yahuda 21, fol. 1r. Cf.: "it must be agreed that God, by the sole action of thinking and willing, can prevent a body from penetrating any space defined by Certain limits." Unpublished scientific papers of Isaac Newton, ed. and transl. by A. Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall (Cambridge, 1962), 139. For the association of this view with Newton's voluntarism, see James Force, "Newton's God of dominion", in James Force and Richard Popkin, Essays on the context, nature, and influence of Newton's theology (Dordrecht, 1990), 85f., and E. B. Davis, "Newton's rejection of the Newtonian world view", Science and Christian belief, iii (1991), 103-17.
    • (1991) Science and Christian Belief , vol.3 , pp. 103-117
    • Davis, E.B.1
  • 80
    • 85034522180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The evidences of natural and revealed religion
    • 2 vols, London
    • Samuel Clarke, "The evidences of natural and revealed religion", The works of Samuel Clarke, D.D. (2 vols, London, 1738), ii, 698.
    • (1738) The Works of Samuel Clarke, D.D. , vol.2 , pp. 698
    • Clarke, S.1
  • 81
    • 0004213577 scopus 로고
    • London
    • William Whiston, A new theory of the earth (London, 1696), 6. Elsewhere Whiston states that the "Effects of Nature" are nothing but divine power "acting according to fixt and certain Laws" (p. 211).
    • (1696) A New Theory of the Earth , pp. 6
    • Whiston, W.1
  • 82
    • 84988406676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • God does not maintain things in existence by any new action, but by the continuation of the act whereby he bestows being
    • Thus Aquinas: "God does not maintain things in existence by any new action, but by the continuation of the act whereby he bestows being." Summa theologiae 1a. 104, 1.
    • Summa Theologiae , vol.1 A , pp. 104
    • Aquinas, T.1
  • 83
    • 0010098350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objections and replies
    • ref. 12
    • Descartes, Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293. This idea is repeated in a number of places: "In the beginning {in his omnipotence} he [God] created matter, along with its motion and rest; and now, merely by his regular concurrence [concursum ordinarium], he preserves the same amount of motion and rest in the material universe as he put there in the beginning" (Principles of philosophy, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 240); "For to occur 'naturally' is nothing other than to occur through the ordinary power of God, which in no way differs from his extraordinary power - the effect on the real world is exactly the same" (Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293); "This rule is based on the same foundation as the other two: it depends solely on God's preserving each thing by a continuous action, and consequently on his preserving it not as it may have been some time earlier but precisely as it is at the very instant that he preserves it" (The world, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 96); "But if there were any bodies in the world, or any intelligences or other natures that were not wholly perfect, their being must depend on God's power in such a manner that they could not subsist for a single moment without him" (Discourse, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 127).
    • Philosophical Writings , vol.2 , pp. 293
    • Descartes1
  • 84
    • 0009637097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of philosophy
    • ref. 12
    • Descartes, Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293. This idea is repeated in a number of places: "In the beginning {in his omnipotence} he [God] created matter, along with its motion and rest; and now, merely by his regular concurrence [concursum ordinarium], he preserves the same amount of motion and rest in the material universe as he put there in the beginning" (Principles of philosophy, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 240); "For to occur 'naturally' is nothing other than to occur through the ordinary power of God, which in no way differs from his extraordinary power - the effect on the real world is exactly the same" (Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293); "This rule is based on the same foundation as the other two: it depends solely on God's preserving each thing by a continuous action, and consequently on his preserving it not as it may have been some time earlier but precisely as it is at the very instant that he preserves it" (The world, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 96); "But if there were any bodies in the world, or any intelligences or other natures that were not wholly perfect, their being must depend on God's power in such a manner that they could not subsist for a single moment without him" (Discourse, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 127).
    • Philosophical Writings , vol.1 , pp. 240
  • 85
    • 0010098350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objections and replies
    • ref. 12
    • Descartes, Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293. This idea is repeated in a number of places: "In the beginning {in his omnipotence} he [God] created matter, along with its motion and rest; and now, merely by his regular concurrence [concursum ordinarium], he preserves the same amount of motion and rest in the material universe as he put there in the beginning" (Principles of philosophy, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 240); "For to occur 'naturally' is nothing other than to occur through the ordinary power of God, which in no way differs from his extraordinary power - the effect on the real world is exactly the same" (Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293); "This rule is based on the same foundation as the other two: it depends solely on God's preserving each thing by a continuous action, and consequently on his preserving it not as it may have been some time earlier but precisely as it is at the very instant that he preserves it" (The world, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 96); "But if there were any bodies in the world, or any intelligences or other natures that were not wholly perfect, their being must depend on God's power in such a manner that they could not subsist for a single moment without him" (Discourse, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 127).
    • Philosophical Writings , vol.2 , pp. 293
  • 86
    • 85034527393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Descartes, Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293. This idea is repeated in a number of places: "In the beginning {in his omnipotence} he [God] created matter, along with its motion and rest; and now, merely by his regular concurrence [concursum ordinarium], he preserves the same amount of motion and rest in the material universe as he put there in the beginning" (Principles of philosophy, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 240); "For to occur 'naturally' is nothing other than to occur through the ordinary power of God, which in no way differs from his extraordinary power - the effect on the real world is exactly the same" (Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293); "This rule is based on the same foundation as the other two: it depends solely on God's preserving each thing by a continuous action, and consequently on his preserving it not as it may have been some time earlier but precisely as it is at the very instant that he preserves it" (The world, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 96); "But if there were any bodies in the world, or any intelligences or other natures that were not wholly perfect, their being must depend on God's power in such a manner that they could not subsist for a single moment without him" (Discourse, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 127).
    • The World, in Philosophical Writings , vol.1 , pp. 96
  • 87
    • 85034527681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Descartes, Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293. This idea is repeated in a number of places: "In the beginning {in his omnipotence} he [God] created matter, along with its motion and rest; and now, merely by his regular concurrence [concursum ordinarium], he preserves the same amount of motion and rest in the material universe as he put there in the beginning" (Principles of philosophy, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 240); "For to occur 'naturally' is nothing other than to occur through the ordinary power of God, which in no way differs from his extraordinary power - the effect on the real world is exactly the same" (Objections and replies, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), ii, 293); "This rule is based on the same foundation as the other two: it depends solely on God's preserving each thing by a continuous action, and consequently on his preserving it not as it may have been some time earlier but precisely as it is at the very instant that he preserves it" (The world, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 96); "But if there were any bodies in the world, or any intelligences or other natures that were not wholly perfect, their being must depend on God's power in such a manner that they could not subsist for a single moment without him" (Discourse, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 127).
    • Discourse, in Philosophical Writings , vol.1 , pp. 127
  • 88
    • 0041812132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • VII.8, transl. by Nicholas Jolley and David Scott Cambridge
    • Nicolas Malebranche, Dialogues on metaphysics, VII.8, transl. by Nicholas Jolley and David Scott (Cambridge, 1997), 113. Cf. The search after truth, transl. and ed. by Thomas Lennon and Paul Olscamp (Cambridge, 1997), 450.
    • (1997) Dialogues on Metaphysics , pp. 113
    • Malebranche, N.1
  • 89
    • 0010774046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • transl. and ed. by Thomas Lennon and Paul Olscamp Cambridge
    • Nicolas Malebranche, Dialogues on metaphysics, VII.8, transl. by Nicholas Jolley and David Scott (Cambridge, 1997), 113. Cf. The search after truth, transl. and ed. by Thomas Lennon and Paul Olscamp (Cambridge, 1997), 450.
    • (1997) The Search after Truth , pp. 450
  • 92
    • 85071095651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Casual powers and occasionalism from Descartes to Malebranche
    • ref. 20
    • On the Cartesians and occasionalism, see Desmond Clarke, "Casual powers and occasionalism from Descartes to Malebranche", in Descartes' natural philosophy (ref. 20), 131-48; Daniel Garber, "Descartes and occasionalism", in Causation in early modern philosophy, ed. by Steven Nadler (University Park, 1993), 9-26; Steven Nadler, "Occasionalism and the question of Arnauld's Cartesianism", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 129-44; "Doctrines of explanation in late scholasticism and in the mechanical philosophy", 541, in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 513-52; Daniel Garber, "How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism", Journal of philosophy, lxxxiv (1987), 567-80.
    • Descartes' Natural Philosophy , pp. 131-148
    • Clarke, D.1
  • 93
    • 0040869152 scopus 로고
    • Descartes and occasionalism
    • ed. by Steven Nadler University Park
    • On the Cartesians and occasionalism, see Desmond Clarke, "Casual powers and occasionalism from Descartes to Malebranche", in Descartes' natural philosophy (ref. 20), 131-48; Daniel Garber, "Descartes and occasionalism", in Causation in early modern philosophy, ed. by Steven Nadler (University Park, 1993), 9-26; Steven Nadler, "Occasionalism and the question of Arnauld's Cartesianism", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 129-44; "Doctrines of explanation in late scholasticism and in the mechanical philosophy", 541, in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 513-52; Daniel Garber, "How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism", Journal of philosophy, lxxxiv (1987), 567-80.
    • (1993) Causation in Early Modern Philosophy , pp. 9-26
    • Garber, D.1
  • 94
    • 0042312902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Occasionalism and the question of Arnauld's Cartesianism
    • ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3)
    • On the Cartesians and occasionalism, see Desmond Clarke, "Casual powers and occasionalism from Descartes to Malebranche", in Descartes' natural philosophy (ref. 20), 131-48; Daniel Garber, "Descartes and occasionalism", in Causation in early modern philosophy, ed. by Steven Nadler (University Park, 1993), 9-26; Steven Nadler, "Occasionalism and the question of Arnauld's Cartesianism", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 129-44; "Doctrines of explanation in late scholasticism and in the mechanical philosophy", 541, in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 513-52; Daniel Garber, "How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism", Journal of philosophy, lxxxiv (1987), 567-80.
    • Descartes and His Contemporaries , pp. 129-144
    • Nadler, S.1
  • 95
    • 47749103061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doctrines of explanation in late scholasticism and in the mechanical philosophy
    • 541, ref. 19
    • On the Cartesians and occasionalism, see Desmond Clarke, "Casual powers and occasionalism from Descartes to Malebranche", in Descartes' natural philosophy (ref. 20), 131-48; Daniel Garber, "Descartes and occasionalism", in Causation in early modern philosophy, ed. by Steven Nadler (University Park, 1993), 9-26; Steven Nadler, "Occasionalism and the question of Arnauld's Cartesianism", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 129-44; "Doctrines of explanation in late scholasticism and in the mechanical philosophy", 541, in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 513-52; Daniel Garber, "How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism", Journal of philosophy, lxxxiv (1987), 567-80.
    • Cambridge History of Seventeenth-century Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 513-552
  • 96
    • 0039430520 scopus 로고
    • How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism
    • On the Cartesians and occasionalism, see Desmond Clarke, "Casual powers and occasionalism from Descartes to Malebranche", in Descartes' natural philosophy (ref. 20), 131-48; Daniel Garber, "Descartes and occasionalism", in Causation in early modern philosophy, ed. by Steven Nadler (University Park, 1993), 9-26; Steven Nadler, "Occasionalism and the question of Arnauld's Cartesianism", in Descartes and his contemporaries, ed. by Ariew and Grene (ref. 3), 129-44; "Doctrines of explanation in late scholasticism and in the mechanical philosophy", 541, in Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy (ref. 19), i, 513-52; Daniel Garber, "How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism", Journal of philosophy, lxxxiv (1987), 567-80.
    • (1987) Journal of Philosophy , vol.84 , pp. 567-580
    • Garber, D.1
  • 98
    • 85071141228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The invention of nature
    • ref. 20
    • On Descartes's contribution to this notion of laws of nature, see Theo Verbeek, "The invention of nature", in Descartes' natural philosophy (ref. 20), 149-67. See also Daniel Garber, "How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism", The journal of philosophy, lxxxiv (1987), 567-80; Hans van Ruler, "Minds, forms, and spirits: The nature of Cartesian disenchantment", Journal of the history of ideas, lxi (2000), 381-95.
    • Descartes' Natural Philosophy , pp. 149-167
    • Verbeek, T.1
  • 99
    • 0039430520 scopus 로고
    • How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism
    • On Descartes's contribution to this notion of laws of nature, see Theo Verbeek, "The invention of nature", in Descartes' natural philosophy (ref. 20), 149-67. See also Daniel Garber, "How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism", The journal of philosophy, lxxxiv (1987), 567-80; Hans van Ruler, "Minds, forms, and spirits: The nature of Cartesian disenchantment", Journal of the history of ideas, lxi (2000), 381-95.
    • (1987) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.84 , pp. 567-580
    • Garber, D.1
  • 100
    • 0041110538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Minds, forms, and spirits: The nature of Cartesian disenchantment
    • On Descartes's contribution to this notion of laws of nature, see Theo Verbeek, "The invention of nature", in Descartes' natural philosophy (ref. 20), 149-67. See also Daniel Garber, "How God causes motion: Descartes, divine substance, and occasionalism", The journal of philosophy, lxxxiv (1987), 567-80; Hans van Ruler, "Minds, forms, and spirits: The nature of Cartesian disenchantment", Journal of the history of ideas, lxi (2000), 381-95.
    • (2000) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.61 , pp. 381-395
    • Van Ruler, H.1
  • 101
    • 84970479356 scopus 로고
    • Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy
    • Keith Hutchison has spoken in this context about a possible influence of the "radical supernaturalism" of the Protestant reformers. "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333.
    • (1983) History of Science , vol.21 , pp. 297-333
  • 103
    • 0007361567 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • On the distinction and its history see Lawrence Moonan, Divine power: The medieval power distinction and its adoption by Albert, Bonaventure, and Aquinas (Oxford, 1994); Francis Oakley, "The absolute and ordained power of God in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century theology", Journal of the history of ideas, lix (1998), 437-61; idem, "The absolute and ordained power of God and king in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries: Philosophy, science, politics, and law", Journal of the history of ideas, lix (1998), 669-89; William Courtenay, Capacity and volition: A history of the distinction of absolute and ordained power (Bergamo, 1990).
    • (1994) Divine Power: the Medieval Power Distinction and Its Adoption by Albert, Bonaventure, and Aquinas
    • Moonan, L.1
  • 104
    • 0007363790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The absolute and ordained power of God in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century theology
    • On the distinction and its history see Lawrence Moonan, Divine power: The medieval power distinction and its adoption by Albert, Bonaventure, and Aquinas (Oxford, 1994); Francis Oakley, "The absolute and ordained power of God in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century theology", Journal of the history of ideas, lix (1998), 437-61; idem, "The absolute and ordained power of God and king in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries: Philosophy, science, politics, and law", Journal of the history of ideas, lix (1998), 669-89; William Courtenay, Capacity and volition: A history of the distinction of absolute and ordained power (Bergamo, 1990).
    • (1998) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.59 , pp. 437-461
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 105
    • 0007416425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The absolute and ordained power of God and king in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries: Philosophy, science, politics, and law
    • On the distinction and its history see Lawrence Moonan, Divine power: The medieval power distinction and its adoption by Albert, Bonaventure, and Aquinas (Oxford, 1994); Francis Oakley, "The absolute and ordained power of God in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century theology", Journal of the history of ideas, lix (1998), 437-61; idem, "The absolute and ordained power of God and king in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries: Philosophy, science, politics, and law", Journal of the history of ideas, lix (1998), 669-89; William Courtenay, Capacity and volition: A history of the distinction of absolute and ordained power (Bergamo, 1990).
    • (1998) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.59 , pp. 669-689
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 106
    • 0003987967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bergamo
    • On the distinction and its history see Lawrence Moonan, Divine power: The medieval power distinction and its adoption by Albert, Bonaventure, and Aquinas (Oxford, 1994); Francis Oakley, "The absolute and ordained power of God in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century theology", Journal of the history of ideas, lix (1998), 437-61; idem, "The absolute and ordained power of God and king in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries: Philosophy, science, politics, and law", Journal of the history of ideas, lix (1998), 669-89; William Courtenay, Capacity and volition: A history of the distinction of absolute and ordained power (Bergamo, 1990).
    • (1990) Capacity and Volition: a History of the Distinction of Absolute and Ordained Power
    • Courtenay, W.1
  • 107
    • 0004296633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas is careful to stress, however, that the essential attributes of the Deity are not really distinct from one another or, to put it another way, that God and his essence are not distinct. Summa theologiae 1a. 3, 3; cf. 1a. 13, 4. Descartes says something similar, when he argues that the act by which God understands, wills, and brings about all things is one "perfectly simply act". Principles I, 23, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 200.
    • Summa Theologiae , vol.1 A , pp. 3
  • 108
    • 85034523519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas is careful to stress, however, that the essential attributes of the Deity are not really distinct from one another or, to put it another way, that God and his essence are not distinct. Summa theologiae 1a. 3, 3; cf. 1a. 13, 4. Descartes says something similar, when he argues that the act by which God understands, wills, and brings about all things is one "perfectly simply act". Principles I, 23, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 200.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 23
  • 109
    • 85034523553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Aquinas is careful to stress, however, that the essential attributes of the Deity are not really distinct from one another or, to put it another way, that God and his essence are not distinct. Summa theologiae 1a. 3, 3; cf. 1a. 13, 4. Descartes says something similar, when he argues that the act by which God understands, wills, and brings about all things is one "perfectly simply act". Principles I, 23, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), i, 200.
    • Philosophical Writings , vol.1 , pp. 200
  • 113
    • 0042312897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature" (ref. 3), 526. Cf. Force, "Newton's God" (ref. 36), 85; Malet, "Isaac Barrow" (ref. 3), 270.
    • Boyle's Conception of Nature , pp. 526
    • McGuire1
  • 114
    • 85034524129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 36
    • McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature" (ref. 3), 526. Cf. Force, "Newton's God" (ref. 36), 85; Malet, "Isaac Barrow" (ref. 3), 270.
    • Newton's God , pp. 85
    • Force1
  • 115
    • 0042312845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature" (ref. 3), 526. Cf. Force, "Newton's God" (ref. 36), 85; Malet, "Isaac Barrow" (ref. 3), 270.
    • Isaac Barrow , pp. 270
    • Malet1
  • 117
    • 85034523410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 2
    • Oakley, "Christian theology" (ref. 2), 448; and again in "The absolute and ordained power of God" (ref. 49), 452.
    • Christian Theology , pp. 448
    • Oakley1
  • 118
  • 119
    • 85034525908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 49
    • Oakley, "The absolute power of God and king" (ref. 49), 677f. Oakley gives his source as Dobbs, Janus faces of genius (ref. 3), 110. Cf. Force, "Newton's God" (ref. 36).
    • The Absolute Power of God and King
    • Oakley1
  • 120
    • 0009112833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • Oakley, "The absolute power of God and king" (ref. 49), 677f. Oakley gives his source as Dobbs, Janus faces of genius (ref. 3), 110. Cf. Force, "Newton's God" (ref. 36).
    • Janus Faces of Genius , pp. 110
  • 121
    • 85034524129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 36
    • Oakley, "The absolute power of God and king" (ref. 49), 677f. Oakley gives his source as Dobbs, Janus faces of genius (ref. 3), 110. Cf. Force, "Newton's God" (ref. 36).
    • Newton's God
    • Force1
  • 124
    • 85034523410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 2
    • Oakley, "Christian theology" (ref. 2), 448; "The absolute and ordained power of God" (ref. 49), 452.
    • Christian Theology , pp. 448
    • Oakley1
  • 127
    • 0040312688 scopus 로고
    • Ringwood
    • Gordon Leff, Medieval thought from St Augustine to Ockham (Ringwood, 1958), 289; Erwin Iserloh, Gnade und Eucharistie in der philosophischen Theologie des Wilhelm von Ockham (Wiesbaden, 1956), 67-79. See Oakley, "The absolute and ordained power of God" (ref. 49), 442f., for the history of such interpretations.
    • (1958) Medieval Thought from St Augustine to Ockham , pp. 289
    • Leff, G.1
  • 129
    • 0042312896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 49, for the history of such interpretations
    • Gordon Leff, Medieval thought from St Augustine to Ockham (Ringwood, 1958), 289; Erwin Iserloh, Gnade und Eucharistie in der philosophischen Theologie des Wilhelm von Ockham (Wiesbaden, 1956), 67-79. See Oakley, "The absolute and ordained power of God" (ref. 49), 442f., for the history of such interpretations.
    • The Absolute and Ordained Power of God
    • Oakley1
  • 130
    • 0011277779 scopus 로고
    • Nominalism and later medieval religion
    • ed. by Charles Trinkaus with Heiko Oberman Leiden
    • William J. Courtenay, "Nominalism and later medieval religion", in The pursuit of holiness in late medieval and renaissance religion, ed. by Charles Trinkaus with Heiko Oberman (Leiden, 1974), 26-58, pp. 37, 42, 43. See also Courtenay, Capacity and volition (ref. 49), 16-20. Cf. Heiko Oberman who, while sympathetic to Oakley's reading, states that "the sharp contrasts between the conclusions of studies of nominalist thought are largely reducible to a difference in interpretation of these terms". The harvest of medieval theology: Gabriel Biel and late medieval nominalism (Cambridge, Mass., 1963), 30. See also Thomas Williams, "A most methodical lover: On Scotus's arbitrary creator", Journal of the history of philosophy, xxxviii (2000), 169-202, and "Reason, morality, and voluntarism in Duns Scotus", The modern schoolman, lxxiv (1977), 84-93. The literature also contains related discussions about whether certain individuals can be properly classified as voluntarists. See, e.g., John A. Laumakis, "The voluntarism of William of Auvergne and some evidence to the contrary", The modern schoolman, lxxvi (1999), 303-12.
    • (1974) The Pursuit of Holiness in Late Medieval and Renaissance Religion , pp. 26-58
    • Courtenay, W.J.1
  • 131
    • 0003987967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 49
    • William J. Courtenay, "Nominalism and later medieval religion", in The pursuit of holiness in late medieval and renaissance religion, ed. by Charles Trinkaus with Heiko Oberman (Leiden, 1974), 26-58, pp. 37, 42, 43. See also Courtenay, Capacity and volition (ref. 49), 16-20. Cf. Heiko Oberman who, while sympathetic to Oakley's reading, states that "the sharp contrasts between the conclusions of studies of nominalist thought are largely reducible to a difference in interpretation of these terms". The harvest of medieval theology: Gabriel Biel and late medieval nominalism (Cambridge, Mass., 1963), 30. See also Thomas Williams, "A most methodical lover: On Scotus's arbitrary creator", Journal of the history of philosophy, xxxviii (2000), 169-202, and "Reason, morality, and voluntarism in Duns Scotus", The modern schoolman, lxxiv (1977), 84-93. The literature also contains related discussions about whether certain individuals can be properly classified as voluntarists. See, e.g., John A. Laumakis, "The voluntarism of William of Auvergne and some evidence to the contrary", The modern schoolman, lxxvi (1999), 303-12.
    • Capacity and Volition , pp. 16-20
    • Courtenay1
  • 132
    • 0009284636 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.
    • William J. Courtenay, "Nominalism and later medieval religion", in The pursuit of holiness in late medieval and renaissance religion, ed. by Charles Trinkaus with Heiko Oberman (Leiden, 1974), 26-58, pp. 37, 42, 43. See also Courtenay, Capacity and volition (ref. 49), 16-20. Cf. Heiko Oberman who, while sympathetic to Oakley's reading, states that "the sharp contrasts between the conclusions of studies of nominalist thought are largely reducible to a difference in interpretation of these terms". The harvest of medieval theology: Gabriel Biel and late medieval nominalism (Cambridge, Mass., 1963), 30. See also Thomas Williams, "A most methodical lover: On Scotus's arbitrary creator", Journal of the history of philosophy, xxxviii (2000), 169-202, and "Reason, morality, and voluntarism in Duns Scotus", The modern schoolman, lxxiv (1977), 84-93. The literature also contains related discussions about whether certain individuals can be properly classified as voluntarists. See, e.g., John A. Laumakis, "The voluntarism of William of Auvergne and some evidence to the contrary", The modern schoolman, lxxvi (1999), 303-12.
    • (1963) The Harvest of Medieval Theology: Gabriel Biel and Late Medieval Nominalism , pp. 30
  • 133
    • 0041812097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A most methodical lover: On Scotus's arbitrary creator
    • William J. Courtenay, "Nominalism and later medieval religion", in The pursuit of holiness in late medieval and renaissance religion, ed. by Charles Trinkaus with Heiko Oberman (Leiden, 1974), 26-58, pp. 37, 42, 43. See also Courtenay, Capacity and volition (ref. 49), 16-20. Cf. Heiko Oberman who, while sympathetic to Oakley's reading, states that "the sharp contrasts between the conclusions of studies of nominalist thought are largely reducible to a difference in interpretation of these terms". The harvest of medieval theology: Gabriel Biel and late medieval nominalism (Cambridge, Mass., 1963), 30. See also Thomas Williams, "A most methodical lover: On Scotus's arbitrary creator", Journal of the history of philosophy, xxxviii (2000), 169-202, and "Reason, morality, and voluntarism in Duns Scotus", The modern schoolman, lxxiv (1977), 84-93. The literature also contains related discussions about whether certain individuals can be properly classified as voluntarists. See, e.g., John A. Laumakis, "The voluntarism of William of Auvergne and some evidence to the contrary", The modern schoolman, lxxvi (1999), 303-12.
    • (2000) Journal of the History of Philosophy , vol.38 , pp. 169-202
    • Williams, T.1
  • 134
    • 0042312891 scopus 로고
    • Reason, morality, and voluntarism in Duns Scotus
    • William J. Courtenay, "Nominalism and later medieval religion", in The pursuit of holiness in late medieval and renaissance religion, ed. by Charles Trinkaus with Heiko Oberman (Leiden, 1974), 26-58, pp. 37, 42, 43. See also Courtenay, Capacity and volition (ref. 49), 16-20. Cf. Heiko Oberman who, while sympathetic to Oakley's reading, states that "the sharp contrasts between the conclusions of studies of nominalist thought are largely reducible to a difference in interpretation of these terms". The harvest of medieval theology: Gabriel Biel and late medieval nominalism (Cambridge, Mass., 1963), 30. See also Thomas Williams, "A most methodical lover: On Scotus's arbitrary creator", Journal of the history of philosophy, xxxviii (2000), 169-202, and "Reason, morality, and voluntarism in Duns Scotus", The modern schoolman, lxxiv (1977), 84-93. The literature also contains related discussions about whether certain individuals can be properly classified as voluntarists. See, e.g., John A. Laumakis, "The voluntarism of William of Auvergne and some evidence to the contrary", The modern schoolman, lxxvi (1999), 303-12.
    • (1977) The Modern Schoolman , vol.74 , pp. 84-93
  • 135
    • 0041812095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The voluntarism of William of Auvergne and some evidence to the contrary
    • William J. Courtenay, "Nominalism and later medieval religion", in The pursuit of holiness in late medieval and renaissance religion, ed. by Charles Trinkaus with Heiko Oberman (Leiden, 1974), 26-58, pp. 37, 42, 43. See also Courtenay, Capacity and volition (ref. 49), 16-20. Cf. Heiko Oberman who, while sympathetic to Oakley's reading, states that "the sharp contrasts between the conclusions of studies of nominalist thought are largely reducible to a difference in interpretation of these terms". The harvest of medieval theology: Gabriel Biel and late medieval nominalism (Cambridge, Mass., 1963), 30. See also Thomas Williams, "A most methodical lover: On Scotus's arbitrary creator", Journal of the history of philosophy, xxxviii (2000), 169-202, and "Reason, morality, and voluntarism in Duns Scotus", The modern schoolman, lxxiv (1977), 84-93. The literature also contains related discussions about whether certain individuals can be properly classified as voluntarists. See, e.g., John A. Laumakis, "The voluntarism of William of Auvergne and some evidence to the contrary", The modern schoolman, lxxvi (1999), 303-12.
    • (1999) The Modern Schoolman , vol.76 , pp. 303-312
    • Laumakis, J.A.1
  • 136
    • 85034526511 scopus 로고
    • Quod de absoluta potestata nugantur scholastici, non solum repudio, sed etiam detestor, quia justitiam eius ab imperio separant
    • reply to art. I, Corpus reformatorum Berlin
    • "quod de absoluta potestata nugantur scholastici, non solum repudio, sed etiam detestor, quia justitiam eius ab imperio separant." Calumniae nebulonis cuiusdum de occulta providentia Dei, reply to art. I, Corpus reformatorum (Berlin, 1834- ), ix, 288.
    • (1834) Calumniae Nebulonis Cuiusdum de Occulta Providentia dei , vol.9 , pp. 288
  • 137
    • 79251569495 scopus 로고
    • III.xxiii.3, ed. by J. McNeill, transl. by Ford Lewis Battles 2 vols, Philadelphia
    • Calvin, Institutes of the Christian religion, III.xxiii.3, ed. by J. McNeill, transl. by Ford Lewis Battles (2 vols, Philadelphia, 1960), ii, 950. For a discussion of Calvin's position on potentia absoluta see François Wendel, Calvin: Origins and development of his religious thought, transl. by Philip Mairet (New York, 1963), 127f.; cf. Emile Doumergue, Jean Calvin, les hommes et les choses de son temps (7 vols, Lausanne, 1899-1927), iv, 120f.; Henri Bois, La philosophie de Calvin (Paris, 1919), 18ff.
    • (1960) Institutes of the Christian Religion , vol.2 , pp. 950
    • Calvin1
  • 138
    • 25544431623 scopus 로고
    • transl. by Philip Mairet New York
    • Calvin, Institutes of the Christian religion, III.xxiii.3, ed. by J. McNeill, transl. by Ford Lewis Battles (2 vols, Philadelphia, 1960), ii, 950. For a discussion of Calvin's position on potentia absoluta see François Wendel, Calvin: Origins and development of his religious thought, transl. by Philip Mairet (New York, 1963), 127f.; cf. Emile Doumergue, Jean Calvin, les hommes et les choses de son temps (7 vols, Lausanne, 1899-1927), iv, 120f.; Henri Bois, La philosophie de Calvin (Paris, 1919), 18ff.
    • (1963) Calvin: Origins and Development of His Religious Thought
    • Wendel, F.1
  • 139
    • 85034526256 scopus 로고
    • 7 vols, Lausanne
    • Calvin, Institutes of the Christian religion, III.xxiii.3, ed. by J. McNeill, transl. by Ford Lewis Battles (2 vols, Philadelphia, 1960), ii, 950. For a discussion of Calvin's position on potentia absoluta see François Wendel, Calvin: Origins and development of his religious thought, transl. by Philip Mairet (New York, 1963), 127f.; cf. Emile Doumergue, Jean Calvin, les hommes et les choses de son temps (7 vols, Lausanne, 1899-1927), iv, 120f.; Henri Bois, La philosophie de Calvin (Paris, 1919), 18ff.
    • (1899) Jean Calvin, les Hommes et les Choses de Son Temps , vol.4
    • Doumergue, E.1
  • 140
    • 85034522985 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • Calvin, Institutes of the Christian religion, III.xxiii.3, ed. by J. McNeill, transl. by Ford Lewis Battles (2 vols, Philadelphia, 1960), ii, 950. For a discussion of Calvin's position on potentia absoluta see François Wendel, Calvin: Origins and development of his religious thought, transl. by Philip Mairet (New York, 1963), 127f.; cf. Emile Doumergue, Jean Calvin, les hommes et les choses de son temps (7 vols, Lausanne, 1899-1927), iv, 120f.; Henri Bois, La philosophie de Calvin (Paris, 1919), 18ff.
    • (1919) La Philosophie de Calvin
    • Bois, H.1
  • 141
    • 85034527725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Randbemerkungen zu Sentenzen des Petrus Lombardus
    • (ref. 49)
    • Luther, Randbemerkungen zu Sentenzen des Petrus Lombardus, in Werke (ref. 49), ix, 31.
    • Werke , vol.9 , pp. 31
    • Luther1
  • 142
    • 0042312888 scopus 로고
    • Ph.D. Dissertation, Catholic University of America
    • Richard Desharnais, "The history of the distinction between God's absolute and ordained power and its influence on Martin Luther", Ph.D. Dissertation, Catholic University of America, 1966, 248. Desharnais's final conclusion is that Luther "arrived at a position never held by any scholastic" (p. 257), Luther does seem to be a voluntarist in this respect, that goodness is so because of God's willing it. See De servo arbitrio in Werke (ref. 48), xviii, 712.
    • (1966) The History of the Distinction between God's Absolute and Ordained Power and Its Influence on Martin Luther , pp. 248
    • Desharnais, R.1
  • 143
    • 85034524547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 48
    • Richard Desharnais, "The history of the distinction between God's absolute and ordained power and its influence on Martin Luther", Ph.D. Dissertation, Catholic University of America, 1966, 248. Desharnais's final conclusion is that Luther "arrived at a position never held by any scholastic" (p. 257), Luther does seem to be a voluntarist in this respect, that goodness is so because of God's willing it. See De servo arbitrio in Werke (ref. 48), xviii, 712.
    • De Servo Arbitrio in Werke , vol.18 , pp. 712
  • 145
    • 4243392355 scopus 로고
    • London
    • William Perkins, A golden chaine, or, the description of theology (London, 1621), 17f. (I have referred to one of the many later editions of this work.) Cf. An exposition of the symbole or creede of the apostles (London, 1611), 37. The same distinction is made here. Perkins also notes that "the father is and was able to haue created another world, yea a thousand worlds, but he would not, nor will not".
    • (1621) A Golden Chaine, Or, the Description of Theology
    • Perkins, W.1
  • 146
    • 0042312856 scopus 로고
    • London
    • William Perkins, A golden chaine, or, the description of theology (London, 1621), 17f. (I have referred to one of the many later editions of this work.) Cf. An exposition of the symbole or creede of the apostles (London, 1611), 37. The same distinction is made here. Perkins also notes that "the father is and was able to haue created another world, yea a thousand worlds, but he would not, nor will not".
    • (1611) An Exposition of the Symbole or Creede of the Apostles , pp. 37
  • 148
    • 0042312853 scopus 로고
    • "Westminster Confession", ch. 3, "Of God's Eternal Decree"
    • art. 1, 3 vols, New York
    • "Westminster Confession", ch. 3, "Of God's Eternal Decree", art. 1, Creeds of Christendom, ed. by Philip Schaff (3 vols, New York, 1878), iii, 608. Cf. ch. 5, "Of Providence", art. 3 "God, in His ordinary providence, makes use of means, yet is free to work without, above, and against them, at His pleasure" (ibid., iii, 612f.).
    • (1878) Creeds of Christendom , vol.3 , pp. 608
    • Schaff, P.1
  • 149
    • 85034524629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "of Providence", art. 3 "God, in His ordinary providence, makes use of means, yet is free to work without, above, and against them, at His pleasure"
    • "Westminster Confession", ch. 3, "Of God's Eternal Decree", art. 1, Creeds of Christendom, ed. by Philip Schaff (3 vols, New York, 1878), iii, 608. Cf. ch. 5, "Of Providence", art. 3 "God, in His ordinary providence, makes use of means, yet is free to work without, above, and against them, at His pleasure" (ibid., iii, 612f.).
    • Creeds of Christendom , vol.3
  • 150
    • 84858433469 scopus 로고
    • London
    • The restatement of the classical view of the divine powers was not limited to puritan writers. In his controversy with Hobbes, the Anglican divine Bishop Bramhall also articulates the distinction and its classical interpretation: "By his absolute power, he can do all things which do not implie imperfection or contradiction: but by his ordinate power he cannot change his decrees, nor alter what he hath ordained." Bramhall uses the same example as Perkins to illustrate the difference - God could have raised up children of Abraham out of stones, but did not, and will not do so. John Bramhall, Castigations of Mr. Hobbes his last animadversions (London, 1657), 46, cf. 407f. Also see 247f. where Bramhall problematically seems to imply that God's absolute power has the potential to be presently exercised. This apparent contradiction is to be accounted for by Bramhall's conception of time.
    • (1657) Castigations of Mr. Hobbes His Last Animadversions , pp. 46
    • Bramhall, J.1
  • 152
    • 24144438900 scopus 로고
    • De cive
    • ch. 14, Sec. 8, ed. by Sir William Molesworth 7 vols, London
    • Hobbes, De cive, ch. 14, Sec. 8, in The English works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, ed. by Sir William Molesworth (7 vols, London, 1839-45), ii, 189.
    • (1839) The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury , vol.2 , pp. 189
    • Hobbes1
  • 153
    • 0042813940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (ref. 19), ch. 14, 189
    • Cudworth, Treatise of freewill (ref. 19), ch. 14, 189. Samuel Clarke, whom as we shall see is not a voluntarist, also speaks of God's "abitrary will". "The evidences of natural and revealed religion", Works (ref. 37), ii, 698.
    • Treatise of Freewill
    • Cudworth1
  • 154
    • 85034522180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The evidences of natural and revealed religion
    • (ref. 37)
    • Cudworth, Treatise of freewill (ref. 19), ch. 14, 189. Samuel Clarke, whom as we shall see is not a voluntarist, also speaks of God's "abitrary will". "The evidences of natural and revealed religion", Works (ref. 37), ii, 698.
    • Works , vol.2 , pp. 698
    • Clarke, S.1
  • 155
    • 84884004434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 70
    • Ames, Marrow (ref. 70), 46.
    • Marrow , pp. 46
    • Ames1
  • 156
    • 85034527987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 47.
    • Marrow , pp. 47
  • 158
    • 85034522291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 102, 103f. Cf. 7: "Whatsoever God willeth he willeth from Eternity, and always willeth."
    • The Orthodox Evangelist , pp. 102
  • 160
    • 85034528936 scopus 로고
    • transl. by Edwin Curley Princeton
    • Thus Spinoza: "We divide the power of God, therefore, into absolute and ordained, and we call God's power absolute, when we consider his omnipotence without attending to his decree, but ordained, when we do consider his decrees. Then there is the ordinary power of God, and his extraordinary power. The ordinary is that by which he preserves the world in a certain order; the extraordinary is exercised when he does something beyond the order of nature, e.g., all miracles, such as the speaking of an ass, the appearance of angels, and the like." Spinoza, Descartes' principles of philosophy II.9, The collected works of Spinoza, transl. by Edwin Curley (Princeton, 1985), i, 333. Spinoza had reservations about the latter distinction, wishing to deny miracles: "Concerning this last there could, not without reason, be considerable doubt. For it seems a greater miracle if God always governs the world with one and the same fixed and immutable order, than if, on account of human folly, he abrogates the laws which (as only one thoroughly blinded could deny) he himself has most excellently decreed in nature, from sheer freedom. But we leave this for the Theologians to settle." Ibid. 82. William Courtenay, "The dialectic of divine omnipotence", 8, in Covenant and causality within medieval thought (London, 1984).
    • (1985) Descartes' Principles of Philosophy II.9, the Collected Works of Spinoza , vol.1 , pp. 333
    • Spinoza1
  • 161
    • 85034524031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus Spinoza: "We divide the power of God, therefore, into absolute and ordained, and we call God's power absolute, when we consider his omnipotence without attending to his decree, but ordained, when we do consider his decrees. Then there is the ordinary power of God, and his extraordinary power. The ordinary is that by which he preserves the world in a certain order; the extraordinary is exercised when he does something beyond the order of nature, e.g., all miracles, such as the speaking of an ass, the appearance of angels, and the like." Spinoza, Descartes' principles of philosophy II.9, The collected works of Spinoza, transl. by Edwin Curley (Princeton, 1985), i, 333. Spinoza had reservations about the latter distinction, wishing to deny miracles: "Concerning this last there could, not without reason, be considerable doubt. For it seems a greater miracle if God always governs the world with one and the same fixed and immutable order, than if, on account of human folly, he abrogates the laws which (as only one thoroughly blinded could deny) he himself has most excellently decreed in nature, from sheer freedom. But we leave this for the Theologians to settle." Ibid. 82. William Courtenay, "The dialectic of divine omnipotence", 8, in Covenant and causality within medieval thought (London, 1984).
    • Descartes' Principles of Philosophy II.9, the Collected Works of Spinoza , pp. 82
  • 162
    • 67649314707 scopus 로고
    • The dialectic of divine omnipotence
    • 8, London
    • Thus Spinoza: "We divide the power of God, therefore, into absolute and ordained, and we call God's power absolute, when we consider his omnipotence without attending to his decree, but ordained, when we do consider his decrees. Then there is the ordinary power of God, and his extraordinary power. The ordinary is that by which he preserves the world in a certain order; the extraordinary is exercised when he does something beyond the order of nature, e.g., all miracles, such as the speaking of an ass, the appearance of angels, and the like." Spinoza, Descartes' principles of philosophy II.9, The collected works of Spinoza, transl. by Edwin Curley (Princeton, 1985), i, 333. Spinoza had reservations about the latter distinction, wishing to deny miracles: "Concerning this last there could, not without reason, be considerable doubt. For it seems a greater miracle if God always governs the world with one and the same fixed and immutable order, than if, on account of human folly, he abrogates the laws which (as only one thoroughly blinded could deny) he himself has most excellently decreed in nature, from sheer freedom. But we leave this for the Theologians to settle." Ibid. 82. William Courtenay, "The dialectic of divine omnipotence", 8, in Covenant and causality within medieval thought (London, 1984).
    • (1984) Covenant and Causality Within Medieval Thought
    • Courtenay, W.1
  • 163
    • 0040344894 scopus 로고
    • Newtonian science, miracles, and the laws of nature
    • Thus Clarke, Whiston, and Newton regarded miracles as unusual, but within the ambit of a general divine plan. See Peter Harrison, "Newtonian science, miracles, and the laws of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, lvi (1995), 531-53.
    • (1995) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.56 , pp. 531-553
    • Harrison, P.1
  • 164
    • 0009112833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • On Newton's voluntarism see Dobbs, Janus faces of genius (ref. 3), 110; Matt Goldish, Judaism in the theology of Isaac Newton (Dordrecht, 1998), 159; Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 151; James Force, "The God of Abraham and Isaac (Newton)", in James Force and Richard Popkin (eds), The books of nature and scripture (Dordrecht, 1994), 179-200, p. 183.
    • Janus Faces of Genius , pp. 110
    • Dobbs1
  • 165
    • 0042312807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dordrecht
    • On Newton's voluntarism see Dobbs, Janus faces of genius (ref. 3), 110; Matt Goldish, Judaism in the theology of Isaac Newton (Dordrecht, 1998), 159; Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 151; James Force, "The God of Abraham and Isaac (Newton)", in James Force and Richard Popkin (eds), The books of nature and scripture (Dordrecht, 1994), 179-200, p. 183.
    • (1998) Judaism in the Theology of Isaac Newton , pp. 159
    • Goldish, M.1
  • 166
    • 0042813989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • On Newton's voluntarism see Dobbs, Janus faces of genius (ref. 3), 110; Matt Goldish, Judaism in the theology of Isaac Newton (Dordrecht, 1998), 159; Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 151; James Force, "The God of Abraham and Isaac (Newton)", in James Force and Richard Popkin (eds), The books of nature and scripture (Dordrecht, 1994), 179-200, p. 183.
    • Divine Will , pp. 151
    • Osler1
  • 167
    • 0042813942 scopus 로고
    • The God of Abraham and Isaac (Newton)
    • James Force and Richard Popkin (eds), Dordrecht
    • On Newton's voluntarism see Dobbs, Janus faces of genius (ref. 3), 110; Matt Goldish, Judaism in the theology of Isaac Newton (Dordrecht, 1998), 159; Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 151; James Force, "The God of Abraham and Isaac (Newton)", in James Force and Richard Popkin (eds), The books of nature and scripture (Dordrecht, 1994), 179-200, p. 183.
    • (1994) The Books of Nature and Scripture , pp. 179-200
    • Force, J.1
  • 169
    • 85034526440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of the immutability of God
    • ref. 37
    • Clarke, "Of the immutability of God", Works (ref. 37), i, 41. Clarke's subtle analysis of the relation of divine goodness and the divine will is given on p. 40.
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 41
    • Clarke1
  • 171
    • 85034526911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Royal Society, Miscellaneous MS 185, fol. 29
    • Boyle, Royal Society, Miscellaneous MS 185, fol. 29.
    • Boyle1
  • 172
    • 0041311465 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Walter Charleton, The darkness of atheism dispelled (London, 1652), 113. Charleton later added that "the Divine Will is absolutely Free, knowing no circumspection, but that of the Divine Wisdome" (p. 216).
    • (1652) The Darkness of Atheism Dispelled , pp. 113
    • Charleton, W.1
  • 174
    • 85034525975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 83
    • It might be objected that for any natural philosopher who believed in the possibility of miracles there would always be a problem. However, Newton and a number of his contemporaries believed that even God's miraculous "interventions" ultimately conformed to some coherent, ordained plan, albeit one which was only partially apparent. See Harrison, "Newtonian science" (ref. 83); Malet, "Isaac Barrow" (ref. 3), 271.
    • Newtonian Science
    • Harrison1
  • 175
    • 0042312845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • It might be objected that for any natural philosopher who believed in the possibility of miracles there would always be a problem. However, Newton and a number of his contemporaries believed that even God's miraculous "interventions" ultimately conformed to some coherent, ordained plan, albeit one which was only partially apparent. See Harrison, "Newtonian science" (ref. 83); Malet, "Isaac Barrow" (ref. 3), 271.
    • Isaac Barrow , pp. 271
    • Malet1
  • 176
    • 85034527022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 34
    • Barrow, Usefulness (ref. 34), 73-74.
    • Usefulness , pp. 73-74
    • Barrow1
  • 177
    • 85034528095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Descartes to Mersenne, ref. 12
    • "It will be said that if God had established these truths He could change them as a king changes his laws. To this the answer is: 'Yes he can, if his will can change.' - "But I understand them to be eternal and unchangeable.' - 'I make the same judgment about God.' - 'But his will is free.' 'Yes, but his power is incomprehensible.'" Descartes to Mersenne, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), iii, 23. Cf.: "Now there are some changes whose occurrence is guaranteed either by our own plain experience or by divine revelation, and either our perception or our faith shows us that these take place without any change in the creator; but apart from these we should not suppose that any other changes occur in God's works, in case this suggests some inconstancy in God." Principles of philosophy, in ibid., i, 240.
    • Philosophical Writings , vol.3 , pp. 23
  • 178
    • 0009637097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of philosophy
    • ref. 12
    • "It will be said that if God had established these truths He could change them as a king changes his laws. To this the answer is: 'Yes he can, if his will can change.' - "But I understand them to be eternal and unchangeable.' - 'I make the same judgment about God.' - 'But his will is free.' 'Yes, but his power is incomprehensible.'" Descartes to Mersenne, in Philosophical writings (ref. 12), iii, 23. Cf.: "Now there are some changes whose occurrence is guaranteed either by our own plain experience or by divine revelation, and either our perception or our faith shows us that these take place without any change in the creator; but apart from these we should not
    • Philosophical Writings , vol.1 , pp. 240
  • 179
    • 0042813943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Newton and the Guaranteeing God
    • James Force and Richard Popkin (eds), Dordrecht
    • Arguably induction is not a problem until after Hume had endorsed Malebranche's position stripped of its theism. G. A. J. Rogers has also written about a religious solution to the problem of induction, arguing that for Newton, the notion of the simplicity of nature vitiated the problem of induction. See "Newton and the Guaranteeing God", in James Force and Richard Popkin (eds), Newton and religion: Context, nature, and influence (Dordrecht, 1999), 221-36.
    • (1999) Newton and Religion: Context, Nature, and Influence , pp. 221-236
  • 180
    • 0042312845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • This question is also raised by Malet, "Isaac Barrow" (ref. 3), 265.
    • Isaac Barrow , pp. 265
    • Malet1
  • 181
    • 85034528607 scopus 로고
    • ed. by Jaroslav Pelikan and Helmut Lehman 55 vols, St Louis
    • Luther, Heidelberg disputation, 22, Luther's works, ed. by Jaroslav Pelikan and Helmut Lehman (55 vols, St Louis, 1955-75), xxxi, 40f. Cf. the "Proofs of the disputation", Luther's works, xxxi, 52f.
    • (1955) Heidelberg Disputation, 22, Luther's Works , vol.31
    • Luther1
  • 182
    • 85034526690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Proofs of the disputation
    • Luther, Heidelberg disputation, 22, Luther's works, ed. by Jaroslav Pelikan and Helmut Lehman (55 vols, St Louis, 1955-75), xxxi, 40f. Cf. the "Proofs of the disputation", Luther's works, xxxi, 52f.
    • Luther's Works , vol.31
  • 183
    • 85034526392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to Peter Anstey for this point
    • I am grateful to Peter Anstey for this point.
  • 185
    • 85034528210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The being of God proved from the frame of the world
    • ref. 35
    • Isaac Barrow, Sermon VI; "The being of God proved from the frame of the world", Works (ref. 35), i, 232. See also Sermon LXVIII: "Of the goodness of God", ibid., ii, 52.
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 232
    • Barrow, I.1    Sermon VI2
  • 186
    • 85034526232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of the goodness of God
    • Isaac Barrow, Sermon VI; "The being of God proved from the frame of the world", Works (ref. 35), i, 232. See also Sermon LXVIII: "Of the goodness of God", ibid., ii, 52.
    • Works , vol.2 , pp. 52
    • Lxviii, S.1
  • 188
    • 0040786153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By 'miracle' I mean the effects which depend on general laws which are not known to us naturally
    • (ref. 41), XII.xiii.
    • Thus Malebranche: "By 'miracle' I mean the effects which depend on general laws which are not known to us naturally." Dialogues (ref. 41), XII.xiii. Cf. Oeuvres complètes, ed. by André Robine (22 vols, Paris, 1958), viii, 231n. John Norton distinguishes between God's "decree" and the "Law of Nature", and notes that we may not understand the former on account of "the error of our understanding". Orthodox evangelist (ref. 78), 102-4, 7. It also significant that the possibility of legitimate prophecy required that events be necessitated but in ways unknown to most individuals. Nehemiah Grew wrote that: "The Being of Prophecies, supposeth, the Non-being of Contingents, Tho things seem contingent to us." Cosmologia sacra: or, a Discourse of the universe as it is the creature and kingdom of God (London, 1701), 209. See Peter Harrison, "Prophecy, early-modern apologetics, and Hume's argument against miracles", Journal of the history of ideas, lx (1999), 241-57.
    • Dialogues
    • Malebranche, T.1
  • 189
    • 0040786153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 22 vols, Paris
    • Thus Malebranche: "By 'miracle' I mean the effects which depend on general laws which are not known to us naturally." Dialogues (ref. 41), XII.xiii. Cf. Oeuvres complètes, ed. by André Robine (22 vols, Paris, 1958), viii, 231n. John Norton distinguishes between God's "decree" and the "Law of Nature", and notes that we may not understand the former on account of "the error of our understanding". Orthodox evangelist (ref. 78), 102-4, 7. It also significant that the possibility of legitimate prophecy required that events be necessitated but in ways unknown to most individuals. Nehemiah Grew wrote that: "The Being of Prophecies, supposeth, the Non-being of Contingents, Tho things seem contingent to us." Cosmologia sacra: or, a Discourse of the universe as it is the creature and kingdom of God (London, 1701), 209. See Peter Harrison, "Prophecy, early-modern apologetics, and Hume's argument against miracles", Journal of the history of ideas, lx (1999), 241-57.
    • (1958) Oeuvres Complètes , vol.8
    • Robine, A.1
  • 190
    • 0040786153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 78
    • Thus Malebranche: "By 'miracle' I mean the effects which depend on general laws which are not known to us naturally." Dialogues (ref. 41), XII.xiii. Cf. Oeuvres complètes, ed. by André Robine (22 vols, Paris, 1958), viii, 231n. John Norton distinguishes between God's "decree" and the "Law of Nature", and notes that we may not understand the former on account of "the error of our understanding". Orthodox evangelist (ref. 78), 102-4, 7. It also significant that the possibility of legitimate prophecy required that events be necessitated but in ways unknown to most individuals. Nehemiah Grew wrote that: "The Being of Prophecies, supposeth, the Non-being of Contingents, Tho things seem contingent to us." Cosmologia sacra: or, a Discourse of the universe as it is the creature and kingdom of God (London, 1701), 209. See Peter Harrison, "Prophecy, early-modern apologetics, and Hume's argument against miracles", Journal of the history of ideas, lx (1999), 241-57.
    • Orthodox Evangelist , pp. 102-104
  • 191
    • 0040786153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Being of Prophecies, supposeth, the Non-being of Contingents, Tho things seem contingent to us
    • London
    • Thus Malebranche: "By 'miracle' I mean the effects which depend on general laws which are not known to us naturally." Dialogues (ref. 41), XII.xiii. Cf. Oeuvres complètes, ed. by André Robine (22 vols, Paris, 1958), viii, 231n. John Norton distinguishes between God's "decree" and the "Law of Nature", and notes that we may not understand the former on account of "the error of our understanding". Orthodox evangelist (ref. 78), 102-4, 7. It also significant that the possibility of legitimate prophecy required that events be necessitated but in ways unknown to most individuals. Nehemiah Grew wrote that: "The Being of Prophecies, supposeth, the Non-being of Contingents, Tho things seem contingent to us." Cosmologia sacra: or, a Discourse of the universe as it is the creature and kingdom of God (London, 1701), 209. See Peter Harrison, "Prophecy, early-modern apologetics, and Hume's argument against miracles", Journal of the history of ideas, lx (1999), 241-57.
    • (1701) Cosmologia Sacra: Or, a Discourse of the Universe as it Is the Creature and Kingdom of God , pp. 209
    • Grew, N.1
  • 192
    • 0040786153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prophecy, early-modern apologetics, and Hume's argument against miracles
    • Thus Malebranche: "By 'miracle' I mean the effects which depend on general laws which are not known to us naturally." Dialogues (ref. 41), XII.xiii. Cf. Oeuvres complètes, ed. by André Robine (22 vols, Paris, 1958), viii, 231n. John Norton distinguishes between God's "decree" and the "Law of Nature", and notes that we may not understand the former on account of "the error of our understanding". Orthodox evangelist (ref. 78), 102-4, 7. It also significant that the possibility of legitimate prophecy required that events be necessitated but in ways unknown to most individuals. Nehemiah Grew wrote that: "The Being of Prophecies, supposeth, the Non-being of Contingents, Tho things seem contingent to us." Cosmologia sacra: or, a Discourse of the universe as it is the creature and kingdom of God (London, 1701), 209. See Peter Harrison, "Prophecy, early-modern apologetics, and Hume's argument against miracles", Journal of the history of ideas, lx (1999), 241-57.
    • (1999) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.60 , pp. 241-257
    • Harrison, P.1
  • 193
    • 85034528539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (ref. 65), I.xvi.3
    • Calvin, Institutes (ref. 65), I.xvi.3, i, 201. Cf.: "I acknowledge that the Lord, as the Sovereign Prince and ruler of all, brings good out of evil; in short, directs all things as by a kind of secret reins, and overrules them by a certain admirable method, which it becomes us to adore with all submissiveness of mind, since we cannot embrace it in thought." "Brief confession of faith", Tracts and treatises on the reformation of the Church (Grand Rapids, 1958), transl. by Henry Beveridge, ii, 131.
    • Institutes , vol.1 , pp. 201
    • Calvin1
  • 194
    • 0041812103 scopus 로고
    • Brief confession of faith
    • Grand Rapids, transl. by Henry Beveridge
    • Calvin, Institutes (ref. 65), I.xvi.3, i, 201. Cf.: "I acknowledge that the Lord, as the Sovereign Prince and ruler of all, brings good out of evil; in short, directs all things as by a kind of secret reins, and overrules them by a certain admirable method, which it becomes us to adore with all submissiveness of mind, since we cannot embrace it in thought." "Brief confession of faith", Tracts and treatises on the reformation of the Church (Grand Rapids, 1958), transl. by Henry Beveridge, ii, 131.
    • (1958) Tracts and Treatises on the Reformation of the Church , vol.2 , pp. 131
  • 195
    • 0042813927 scopus 로고
    • London, Sermon
    • Isaac Barrow, Sermons preached upon several occasions, 2nd edn (London, 1679), Sermon 11, 414. Cf.: "God designeth not commonly to exert his hand in a notorious way, but often purposely doth conceal it" (p. 412).
    • (1679) Sermons Preached Upon Several Occasions, 2nd Edn , pp. 11
    • Barrow, I.1
  • 197
    • 84972294648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Appendix to the first part of the Christian virtuoso
    • Royal Society MS 185, fol. 29: (ref. 25)
    • Boyle, Royal Society MS 185, fol. 29: Appendix to the first part of The Christian virtuoso, in Works (ref. 25), vi, 673-715, pp. 676f. (my emphasis). For a thoroughgoing account of Boyle on the limitations of human reason, see Jan Wojcik, Robert Boyle and the limits of reason (Cambridge, 1997).
    • Works , vol.6 , pp. 673-715
    • Boyle1
  • 198
    • 0003816195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Boyle, Royal Society MS 185, fol. 29: Appendix to the first part of The Christian virtuoso, in Works (ref. 25), vi, 673-715, pp. 676f. (my emphasis). For a thoroughgoing account of Boyle on the limitations of human reason, see Jan Wojcik, Robert Boyle and the limits of reason (Cambridge, 1997).
    • (1997) Robert Boyle and the Limits of Reason
    • Wojcik, J.1
  • 199
    • 0347798520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Syntagma philosophicum
    • ref. 33
    • Pierre Gassendi, Syntagma philosophicum, in Opera omnia (ref. 33), i, 326; Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 54. Cf. William Whiston: "And this I take to be the Secret of Divine Providence in the Government of the World, whereby the Rewards and Punishments of God's mercy and Justice are distributed to his Rational Creatures without any disturbance of the setled Course of Nature, or a miraculous interposition on every occasion." New theory (ref. 38), 359.
    • Opera Omnia , vol.1 , pp. 326
    • Gassendi, P.1
  • 200
    • 0042813989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 3
    • Pierre Gassendi, Syntagma philosophicum, in Opera omnia (ref. 33), i, 326; Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 54. Cf. William Whiston: "And this I take to be the Secret of Divine Providence in the Government of the World, whereby the Rewards and Punishments of God's mercy and Justice are distributed to his Rational Creatures without any disturbance of the setled Course of Nature, or a miraculous interposition on every occasion." New theory (ref. 38), 359.
    • Divine Will , pp. 54
    • Osler1
  • 201
    • 84893288806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 38
    • Pierre Gassendi, Syntagma philosophicum, in Opera omnia (ref. 33), i, 326; Osler, Divine will (ref. 3), 54. Cf. William Whiston: "And this I take to be the Secret of Divine Providence in the Government of the World, whereby the Rewards and Punishments of God's mercy and Justice are distributed to his Rational Creatures without any disturbance of the setled Course of Nature, or a miraculous interposition on every occasion." New theory (ref. 38), 359.
    • New Theory , pp. 359
    • Whiston, W.1
  • 203
    • 0041849706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Original sin and the problem of knowledge in early modern Europe
    • forthcoming
    • I have developed this theme in more detail in "Original sin and the problem of knowledge in early modern Europe", Journal of the history of ideas, lxiii (2002), forthcoming.
    • (2002) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.63


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.