메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 110, Issue 2, 2000, Pages 251-258

The Possibility of a Fair Paretian

(1)  Chang, Howard F a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0042320192     PISSN: 00440094     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/797573     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (4)

References (57)
  • 1
    • 0041886887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Liberal Theory of Social Welfare: Fairness, Utility, and the Pareto Principle
    • Howard F. Chang, A Liberal Theory of Social Welfare: Fairness, Utility, and the Pareto Principle, 110 YALE L.J. 173 (2000).
    • (2000) YALE L.J. , vol.110 , pp. 173
    • Chang, H.F.1
  • 3
    • 0034993690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Any Non-Welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle
    • forthcoming hereinafter KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC;
    • forthcoming as Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Any Non-Welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle, 109 J. POL. ECON. (2001) [hereinafter KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC];
    • (2001) J. POL. ECON. , vol.109
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 4
    • 0001780601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle
    • hereinafter Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict;
    • Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, The Conflict Between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle, 1 AM. L. & ECON. REV. 63 (1999) [hereinafter Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict];
    • (1999) AM. L. & ECON. REV. , vol.1 , pp. 63
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 6
    • 0041372337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming hereinafter KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE
    • forthcoming in 114 HARV. L. REV. (2001) [hereinafter KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE].
    • (2001) HARV. L. REV. , vol.114
  • 7
    • 0000654038 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism and Welfarism
    • defining "welfarism" as the view that "[t]he judgment of the relative goodness of alternative states of affairs must be based exclusively on, and taken as an increasing function of, the respective collections of individual utilities in these states"
    • E.g., Amartya Sen, Utilitarianism and Welfarism, 76 J. PHIL. 463, 468 (1979) (defining "welfarism" as the view that "[t]he judgment of the relative goodness of alternative states of affairs must be based exclusively on, and taken as an increasing function of, the respective collections of individual utilities in these states").
    • (1979) J. PHIL. , vol.76 , pp. 463
    • Sen, A.1
  • 8
    • 0004066412 scopus 로고
    • ROBIN BOADWAY & NEIL BRUCE, WELFARE ECONOMICS 143 (1984). Social choice theorists also use the term "strong neutrality" to refer to this concept. Id.
    • (1984) WELFARE ECONOMICS , pp. 143
    • Boadway, R.1    Bruce, N.2
  • 9
    • 0004089426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social choice theorists also use the term "strong neutrality" to refer to this concept.
    • ROBIN BOADWAY & NEIL BRUCE, WELFARE ECONOMICS 143 (1984). Social choice theorists also use the term "strong neutrality" to refer to this concept. Id.
    • WELFARE ECONOMICS
  • 10
    • 84923736069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2
    • They express this concept in the same algebraic form in each of their papers. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2; Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 66 n.5; KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 20 n.31. In each paper, their algebraic expression indicates that social welfare is a function of only individual utility; no other variable appears as an argument in the social welfare function. An ambiguity arises when Kaplow and Shavell, without making explicit any further assumptions, assert as an "observation" that their notion of welfarism is equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2. Welfarism, as social choice theorists use the term, however, is not equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule unless one makes "quite demanding" assumptions. Chang, supra note 1, at 222 n.193; Amartya Sen, Social Choice Theory, in 3 HANDBOOK OF MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS 1073, 1155 (Kenneth J. Arrow & Michael D. Intriligator eds., 1986). In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell state that if the Pareto indifference rule applies, then "there is no sense in which the notion of fairness is receiving any independent weight." Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Notions of Fairness Versus the Pareto Principle: On the Role of Logical Consistency, 110 YALE L.J. 237, 241 n.10 (2000). This statement, however, is true only in the context in which everyone is indifferent between the alternatives in question. The premise that fairness information is irrelevant in that particular context does not imply that fairness information is irrelevant outside that context. Thus, Kaplow and Shavell cannot derive welfarism from the Pareto indifference rule without also assuming that an independence condition applies over an unrestricted domain. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 4, at 143-44; Sen, supra, at 1122.
    • NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC , pp. 2
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 11
    • 84923721818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2, n.5
    • They express this concept in the same algebraic form in each of their papers. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2; Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 66 n.5; KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 20 n.31. In each paper, their algebraic expression indicates that social welfare is a function of only individual utility; no other variable appears as an argument in the social welfare function. An ambiguity arises when Kaplow and Shavell, without making explicit any further assumptions, assert as an "observation" that their notion of welfarism is equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2. Welfarism, as social choice theorists use the term, however, is not equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule unless one makes "quite demanding" assumptions. Chang, supra note 1, at 222 n.193; Amartya Sen, Social Choice Theory, in 3 HANDBOOK OF MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS 1073, 1155 (Kenneth J. Arrow & Michael D. Intriligator eds., 1986). In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell state that if the Pareto indifference rule applies, then "there is no sense in which the notion of fairness is receiving any independent weight." Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Notions of Fairness Versus the Pareto Principle: On the Role of Logical Consistency, 110 YALE L.J. 237, 241 n.10 (2000). This statement, however, is true only in the context in which everyone is indifferent between the alternatives in question. The premise that fairness information is irrelevant in that particular context does not imply that fairness information is irrelevant outside that context. Thus, Kaplow and Shavell cannot derive welfarism from the Pareto indifference rule without also assuming that an independence condition applies over an unrestricted domain. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 4, at 143-44; Sen, supra, at 1122.
    • Conflict , pp. 66
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 12
    • 84923758781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2, n.31. In each paper, their algebraic expression indicates that social welfare is a function of only individual utility; no other variable appears as an argument in the social welfare function. An ambiguity arises when Kaplow and Shavell, without making explicit any further assumptions, assert as an "observation" that their notion of welfarism is equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule
    • They express this concept in the same algebraic form in each of their papers. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2; Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 66 n.5; KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 20 n.31. In each paper, their algebraic expression indicates that social welfare is a function of only individual utility; no other variable appears as an argument in the social welfare function. An ambiguity arises when Kaplow and Shavell, without making explicit any further assumptions, assert as an "observation" that their notion of welfarism is equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2. Welfarism, as social choice theorists use the term, however, is not equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule unless one makes "quite demanding" assumptions. Chang, supra note 1, at 222 n.193; Amartya Sen, Social Choice Theory, in 3 HANDBOOK OF MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS 1073, 1155 (Kenneth J. Arrow & Michael D. Intriligator eds., 1986). In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell state that if the Pareto indifference rule applies, then "there is no sense in which the notion of fairness is receiving any independent weight." Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Notions of Fairness Versus the Pareto Principle: On the Role of Logical Consistency, 110 YALE L.J. 237, 241 n.10 (2000). This statement, however, is true only in the context in which everyone is indifferent between the alternatives in question. The premise that fairness information is irrelevant in that particular context does not imply that fairness information is irrelevant outside that context. Thus, Kaplow and Shavell cannot derive welfarism from the Pareto indifference rule without also assuming that an independence condition applies over an unrestricted domain. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 4, at 143-44; Sen, supra, at 1122.
    • HUMAN WELFARE , pp. 20
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 13
    • 84923736069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2, Welfarism, as social choice theorists use the term, however, is not equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule unless one makes "quite demanding" assumptions. Chang, supra note 1, at 222 n.193;
    • They express this concept in the same algebraic form in each of their papers. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2; Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 66 n.5; KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 20 n.31. In each paper, their algebraic expression indicates that social welfare is a function of only individual utility; no other variable appears as an argument in the social welfare function. An ambiguity arises when Kaplow and Shavell, without making explicit any further assumptions, assert as an "observation" that their notion of welfarism is equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2. Welfarism, as social choice theorists use the term, however, is not equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule unless one makes "quite demanding" assumptions. Chang, supra note 1, at 222 n.193; Amartya Sen, Social Choice Theory, in 3 HANDBOOK OF MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS 1073, 1155 (Kenneth J. Arrow & Michael D. Intriligator eds., 1986). In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell state that if the Pareto indifference rule applies, then "there is no sense in which the notion of fairness is receiving any independent weight." Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Notions of Fairness Versus the Pareto Principle: On the Role of Logical Consistency, 110 YALE L.J. 237, 241 n.10 (2000). This statement, however, is true only in the context in which everyone is indifferent between the alternatives in question. The premise that fairness information is irrelevant in that particular context does not imply that fairness information is irrelevant outside that context. Thus, Kaplow and Shavell cannot derive welfarism from the Pareto indifference rule without also assuming that an independence condition applies over an unrestricted domain. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 4, at 143-44; Sen, supra, at 1122.
    • NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC , pp. 2
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 14
    • 77956861814 scopus 로고
    • Social Choice Theory
    • Kenneth J. Arrow & Michael D. Intriligator eds., In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell state that if the Pareto indifference rule applies, then "there is no sense in which the notion of fairness is receiving any independent weight."
    • They express this concept in the same algebraic form in each of their papers. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2; Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 66 n.5; KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 20 n.31. In each paper, their algebraic expression indicates that social welfare is a function of only individual utility; no other variable appears as an argument in the social welfare function. An ambiguity arises when Kaplow and Shavell, without making explicit any further assumptions, assert as an "observation" that their notion of welfarism is equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2. Welfarism, as social choice theorists use the term, however, is not equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule unless one makes "quite demanding" assumptions. Chang, supra note 1, at 222 n.193; Amartya Sen, Social Choice Theory, in 3 HANDBOOK OF MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS 1073, 1155 (Kenneth J. Arrow & Michael D. Intriligator eds., 1986). In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell state that if the Pareto indifference rule applies, then "there is no sense in which the notion of fairness is receiving any independent weight." Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Notions of Fairness Versus the Pareto Principle: On the Role of Logical Consistency, 110 YALE L.J. 237, 241 n.10 (2000). This statement, however, is true only in the context in which everyone is indifferent between the alternatives in question. The premise that fairness information is irrelevant in that particular context does not imply that fairness information is irrelevant outside that context. Thus, Kaplow and Shavell cannot derive welfarism from the Pareto indifference rule without also assuming that an independence condition applies over an unrestricted domain. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 4, at 143-44; Sen, supra, at 1122.
    • (1986) HANDBOOK of MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS , vol.3 , pp. 1073
    • Sen, A.1
  • 15
    • 0041386048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notions of Fairness Versus the Pareto Principle: On the Role of Logical Consistency
    • This statement, however, is true only in the context in which everyone is indifferent between the alternatives in question. The premise that fairness information is irrelevant in that particular context does not imply that fairness information is irrelevant outside that context. Thus, Kaplow and Shavell cannot derive welfarism from the Pareto indifference rule without also assuming that an independence condition applies over an unrestricted domain. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 4, at 143-44; Sen, supra, at 1122
    • They express this concept in the same algebraic form in each of their papers. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2; Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 66 n.5; KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 20 n.31. In each paper, their algebraic expression indicates that social welfare is a function of only individual utility; no other variable appears as an argument in the social welfare function. An ambiguity arises when Kaplow and Shavell, without making explicit any further assumptions, assert as an "observation" that their notion of welfarism is equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule. KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2, at 2. Welfarism, as social choice theorists use the term, however, is not equivalent to the Pareto indifference rule unless one makes "quite demanding" assumptions. Chang, supra note 1, at 222 n.193; Amartya Sen, Social Choice Theory, in 3 HANDBOOK OF MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS 1073, 1155 (Kenneth J. Arrow & Michael D. Intriligator eds., 1986). In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell state that if the Pareto indifference rule applies, then "there is no sense in which the notion of fairness is receiving any independent weight." Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Notions of Fairness Versus the Pareto Principle: On the Role of Logical Consistency, 110 YALE L.J. 237, 241 n.10 (2000). This statement, however, is true only in the context in which everyone is indifferent between the alternatives in question. The premise that fairness information is irrelevant in that particular context does not imply that fairness information is irrelevant outside that context. Thus, Kaplow and Shavell cannot derive welfarism from the Pareto indifference rule without also assuming that an independence condition applies over an unrestricted domain. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 4, at 143-44; Sen, supra, at 1122.
    • (2000) YALE L.J. , vol.110 , pp. 237
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 16
    • 84923721818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2
    • Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 65; see KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 35 ("Notions of fairness have the property that evaluations relying on them are not based exclusively . . . on how legal policies affect individuals' well-being.").
    • Conflict , pp. 65
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 17
    • 84923758781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2, "Notions of fairness have the property that evaluations relying on them are not based exclusively . . . on how legal policies affect individuals' well-being."
    • Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 65; see KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 35 ("Notions of fairness have the property that evaluations relying on them are not based exclusively . . . on how legal policies affect individuals' well-being.").
    • HUMAN WELFARE , pp. 35
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 18
    • 84923721818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2, n.5
    • Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 66 n.5.
    • Conflict , pp. 66
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 20
    • 84923714620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A welfarist theory must ignore such information. BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 4, at 143 (noting that under welfarism, "information about how the utility levels are obtained is irrelevant for determining how the social states should be ordered").
  • 21
    • 84923714618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Suppose, for example, we want to rank two alternatives, x and y, neither of which Pareto- dominates the other. If fairness information indicates that x is the unique fairness optimum under F, then both F* and F** would rank x over y. If, however, fairness information indicates instead that y is the unique fairness optimum, then both F* and F** would rank y over x, even if the utility information regarding the alternatives is unchanged.
  • 23
    • 84923736069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • revised draft supra note 2
    • LOUIS KAPLOW & STEVEN SHAVELL, ANY NON-WELFARIST METHOD OF POLICY ASSESSMENT VIOLATES THE PARETO PRINCIPLE (Harvard Law Sch., Public Law and Legal Theory Working Paper No. 3, 1999) (revised draft of KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2), forthcoming in 109 J. POL. ECON. (2001).
    • NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 24
    • 0041372292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming
    • LOUIS KAPLOW & STEVEN SHAVELL, ANY NON-WELFARIST METHOD OF POLICY ASSESSMENT VIOLATES THE PARETO PRINCIPLE (Harvard Law Sch., Public Law and Legal Theory Working Paper No. 3, 1999) (revised draft of KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON- INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2), forthcoming in 109 J. POL. ECON. (2001).
    • (2001) J. POL. ECON. , vol.109
  • 25
    • 84923714616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Each condition is necessary for the weak Pareto principle to imply welfarism. If we relax the requirement of continuity, for example, then we can add a fairness principle as a tiebreaker to an otherwise welfarist theory. The result is a fair Paretian theory that complies with independence conditions. Similarly, if we relax the requirement of independence, then we can produce a fair Paretian theory of social welfare that is continuous in individual utilities. Consider a theory that produces standard downward-sloping social indifference curves in utility space. This theory of social welfare would be both continuous and Paretian. If we make the shape and position of these curves in utility space a function of fairness information, however, as the shape and position of the partitions under F* or F** are, then the underlying theory of social welfare is a fairness theory.
  • 26
    • 84923714613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 246
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 246.
  • 27
    • 84923714610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 237 n.2
    • Id. at 237 n.2.
  • 28
    • 84923714598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 246 n.24
    • Id. at 246 n.24.
  • 29
    • 84923721818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2, citing the theory that "marginal utility of income is greater for the poor" as an example of an idea "based only on individuals' well-being";
    • Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 67 (citing the theory that "marginal utility of income is greater for the poor" as an example of an idea "based only on individuals' well-being"); see also, e.g., KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 24-26.
    • Conflict , pp. 67
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 30
    • 84923758781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2
    • Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 67 (citing the theory that "marginal utility of income is greater for the poor" as an example of an idea "based only on individuals' well- being"); see also, e.g., KAPLOW & SHAVELL, HUMAN WELFARE, supra note 2, at 24-26.
    • HUMAN WELFARE , pp. 24-26
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 31
    • 84923721818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2, n.9
    • Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 67 n.9.
    • Conflict , pp. 67
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 32
    • 84887482403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (citing KAPLOW & SHAVELL, NON-INDIVIDUALISTIC, supra note 2).
    • Conflict
  • 35
    • 84923714597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The concept that remains, which apparently includes F* and F** as well as utilitarianism, would seem to be mere Paretianism. If so, then Kaplow and Shavell's claim reduces to a tautology: The Pareto principle implies the Pareto principle.
  • 37
    • 84923731218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Presumably for this reason, Kaplow and Shavell state in their reply that allowing any distributive principle into their definition of welfarism violates "the spirit of some of our arguments." Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 237 n.2. This statement leaves unclear precisely what they mean to include in their notion of welfarism. In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell also invoke their "symmetric case," which they claim is "by itself sufficient to establish that there is a conflict between any notion of fairness and the Pareto principle." Id. at 239 (emphasis added). This case, however, at most demonstrates a potential conflict between a crude fairness principle like F and the Pareto principle. Under either F* or F**, if all individuals in the world were somehow to find themselves in this imaginary symmetric case, they could unanimously agree to waive their rights to the fairness optimum under F
    • Id. at 454. Presumably for this reason, Kaplow and Shavell state in their reply that allowing any distributive principle into their definition of welfarism violates "the spirit of some of our arguments." Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 237 n.2. This statement leaves unclear precisely what they mean to include in their notion of welfarism. In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell also invoke their "symmetric case," which they claim is "by itself sufficient to establish that there is a conflict between any notion of fairness and the Pareto principle." Id. at 239 (emphasis added). This case, however, at most demonstrates a potential conflict between a crude fairness principle like F and the Pareto principle. Under either F* or F**, if all individuals in the world were somehow to find themselves in this imaginary symmetric case, they could unanimously agree to waive their rights to the fairness optimum under F. This demonstration does not prevent a Paretian from applying fairness principles in the real world, in which individuals do not find themselves in that symmetric setting. Thus, I question the relevance of this hypothetical and the conclusions that Kaplow and Shavell seek to draw from it. See Chang, supra note 1, at 190 n.69.
    • HUMAN WELFARE , pp. 454
  • 38
    • 84923714596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kaplow and Shavell seek to distinguish their independence assumption from that of Kenneth Arrow by noting that their assumption does not share all of the controversial features of Arrow's. Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 243 n.17. Like Arrow's assumption, however, Kaplow and Shavell's assumption includes the controversial feature of "pairwise choice," which "means that in socially ranking any pair of candidates a device cannot respond to information about other candidates."
    • Kaplow and Shavell seek to distinguish their independence assumption from that of Kenneth Arrow by noting that their assumption does not share all of the controversial features of Arrow's. Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 243 n.17. Like Arrow's assumption, however, Kaplow and Shavell's assumption includes the controversial feature of "pairwise choice," which "means that in socially ranking any pair of candidates a device cannot respond to information about other candidates." ALFRED F. MACKAY, ARROW'S THEOREM: THE PARADOX OF SOCIAL CHOICE 93 (1980). Theorists have questioned this particular aspect of Arrow's assumption. Id. at 92 (noting that pairwise choice "does not appear to have much intrinsically to recommend it"); DENNIS C. MUELLER, PUBLIC CHOICE II 394 (1989) (questioning the "normative value" of the assumption that "'social choices made in pairwise comparisons'" should determine "'the entire social ordering'" (quoting KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES 28 (2d ed. 1963))).
  • 39
    • 84923742178 scopus 로고
    • Theorists have questioned this particular aspect of Arrow's assumption. Id. at 92 (noting that pairwise choice "does not appear to have much intrinsically to recommend it")
    • Kaplow and Shavell seek to distinguish their independence assumption from that of Kenneth Arrow by noting that their assumption does not share all of the controversial features of Arrow's. Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 243 n.17. Like Arrow's assumption, however, Kaplow and Shavell's assumption includes the controversial feature of "pairwise choice," which "means that in socially ranking any pair of candidates a device cannot respond to information about other candidates." ALFRED F. MACKAY, ARROW'S THEOREM: THE PARADOX OF SOCIAL CHOICE 93 (1980). Theorists have questioned this particular aspect of Arrow's assumption. Id. at 92 (noting that pairwise choice "does not appear to have much intrinsically to recommend it"); DENNIS C. MUELLER, PUBLIC CHOICE II 394 (1989) (questioning the "normative value" of the assumption that "'social choices made in pairwise comparisons'" should determine "'the entire social ordering'" (quoting KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES 28 (2d ed. 1963))).
    • (1980) ARROW'S THEOREM: the PARADOX of SOCIAL CHOICE , pp. 93
    • Mackay, A.F.1
  • 40
    • 0004294469 scopus 로고
    • questioning the "normative value" of the assumption that "'social choices made in pairwise comparisons'" should determine "'the entire social ordering'"
    • Kaplow and Shavell seek to distinguish their independence assumption from that of Kenneth Arrow by noting that their assumption does not share all of the controversial features of Arrow's. Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 243 n.17. Like Arrow's assumption, however, Kaplow and Shavell's assumption includes the controversial feature of "pairwise choice," which "means that in socially ranking any pair of candidates a device cannot respond to information about other candidates." ALFRED F. MACKAY, ARROW'S THEOREM: THE PARADOX OF SOCIAL CHOICE 93 (1980). Theorists have questioned this particular aspect of Arrow's assumption. Id. at 92 (noting that pairwise choice "does not appear to have much intrinsically to recommend it"); DENNIS C. MUELLER, PUBLIC CHOICE II 394 (1989) (questioning the "normative value" of the assumption that "'social choices made in pairwise comparisons'" should determine "'the entire social ordering'" (quoting KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES 28 (2d ed. 1963))).
    • (1989) PUBLIC CHOICE II , pp. 394
    • Mueller, D.C.1
  • 41
    • 0003917730 scopus 로고
    • 2d ed.
    • Kaplow and Shavell seek to distinguish their independence assumption from that of Kenneth Arrow by noting that their assumption does not share all of the controversial features of Arrow's. Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 243 n.17. Like Arrow's assumption, however, Kaplow and Shavell's assumption includes the controversial feature of "pairwise choice," which "means that in socially ranking any pair of candidates a device cannot respond to information about other candidates." ALFRED F. MACKAY, ARROW'S THEOREM: THE PARADOX OF SOCIAL CHOICE 93 (1980). Theorists have questioned this particular aspect of Arrow's assumption. Id. at 92 (noting that pairwise choice "does not appear to have much intrinsically to recommend it"); DENNIS C. MUELLER, PUBLIC CHOICE II 394 (1989) (questioning the "normative value" of the assumption that "'social choices made in pairwise comparisons'" should determine "'the entire social ordering'" (quoting KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES 28 (2d ed. 1963))).
    • (1963) SOCIAL CHOICE and INDIVIDUAL VALUES , pp. 28
    • Arrow, K.J.1
  • 42
    • 84923714595 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 238
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 238.
  • 43
    • 84923714593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 242
    • Id. at 242.
  • 44
    • 84923714591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 244
    • Id. at 244.
  • 45
    • 0001138010 scopus 로고
    • The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal
    • See Chang, supra note 1, at 196-98 citing
    • See Chang, supra note 1, at 196-98 (citing Amartya Sen, The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal, 78 J. POL. ECON. 152, 155 (1970)).
    • (1970) J. POL. ECON. , vol.78 , pp. 152
    • Sen, A.1
  • 46
    • 84923714589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The feasibility of the third alternative would be relevant only if it represents a fairness optimum (like l) and thus represents an alternative to which individuals are entitled. Only then would the alternative be a credible threat as a social choice that would induce individuals to waive their rights to object to a Pareto superior alternative (like p). Nevertheless, Kaplow and Shavell complain that the feasibility of alternatives may be costly to determine or may be influenced by the expenditures of individuals. Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5 at 244-45 Theories like F* or F**, however, could take these costs into account. For example if L can credibly threaten to make l feasible, say, by learning the language used in the book in question, then l is already feasible in the relevant sense. Thus, if everyone prefers that we choose p rather than requiring L to make l feasible (because it would not be chosen anyway), then under F* or F** we would do so. Similarly, the decision to investigate the feasibility of l would itself be a social choice. Under liberal consequentialism, the cost of this investigation would itself be morally relevant. First, an individual like L, who is entitled to the alternative in question if it is feasible, would be entitled to this investigation only if it is not too costly compared with the expected increase in the satisfaction of personal preferences under l. Second, if the feasibility of l is so likely that everyone would prefer to choose p without an investigation of l's feasibility, then under F* or F*" we would do so.
  • 47
    • 84923714587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thus I suggest that our ranking of a pair of feasible alternatives may depend on the feasibility of a third alternative. I also criticize the suggestion that the infeasibility of a hypothetical alternative implies that it would not be desirable if it were feasible. Chang, supra note 1 at 202. Kaplow and Shavell's reply to my article confuses these two distinct suggestions regarding the moral relevance of feasibility. Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 243-44 & n.19.
  • 48
    • 84923714584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To support their claim, Kaplow and Shavell offer a hypothetical that supposedly illustrates the problems raised by violations of the independence condition. Id. at 245 n.21. Their example however, is disturbing only because it assumes an unreasonable fairness theory, one that gives "Bill, the richest . . . person in the society," the right to veto a move that would alleviate the "misery" of "every other person," who is "on the brink of starvation." Id. Here Kaplow and Shavell attack a straw man; they derive an unreasonable result by making an unreasonable assumption. A reasonable fairness theory, like liberal consequentialism, would make "starvation" of so many people morally relevant in the determination of the fairness optimum. Bill, like everyone else in society, would be entitled to the fairness optimum, which would consider the personal preferences of everyone, not to the "starvation" regime described by Kaplow and Shavell.
  • 49
    • 84923714582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 246. They further claim that F** is "impossible," because if we assign "real numbers" to the ranks under F, and the ranks fully occupy the real line, then there is no room left on the real line to allow the creation of more ranks. Id. at 246 & n.25. They incorrectly assume, however, that the creation of more ranks requires the assignment of new numbers on the real line. Consider for example, the addition of a tiebreaking rule, which can create new ranks notwithstanding the fact that the old ranks fully occupied the real line. The "lexirrun" rule, for example multiplies ranks through the use of such tiebreakers. Chang, supra note 1, at 225 n.198. Similarly under F**, we can replace rank 10 with ranks 10a, 10b, and 10c. We can transfer the alternatives remaining in rank 10 to rank 10b, place alternatives that rank higher than 10 but lower than any higher rank in 10a, and place alternatives that rank lower than 10 but higher than any lower rank in 10c.
  • 50
    • 84923714569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For example, if we find the possibility of infinite iterations in theory to be a disturbing prospect then we can replace step (4) of F** with the following: "(4a) To rank alternatives within these newly created sets, apply a welfarist principle." The resulting theory would still be a fairness theory, because it would still require fairness information in step (1). That is, the fairness optimum under F would remain the presumptive social optimum, which could be trumped only by a Pareto improvement and not by any other alternative favored by a welfarist theory.
  • 51
    • 84923714568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Chang, supra note 1, at 230-32. I argue that given the constraints imposed by scarce resources, the constrained optimum under F* or F** is likely to be the fairness optimum under F. In their reply, Kaplow and Shavell question this proposed focus on the fairness optimum under F, basing their critique on the incorrect assumption that this optimum must be "identified in a literally perfect, precise manner." Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 247 n.26. A fairness criterion F like liberal consequentialism would take the costs of policy analysis into account in selecting the social optimum. Thus, one would maximize F only as best one could given the scarcity of resources. In support of their claim, Kaplow and Shavell cite the fact that F* and F** violate continuity and independence. Id. at 247. These features of F* and F** would not be relevant to the identification of the fairness optimum under F. If F is liberal consequentialism, then it could satisfy Kaplow and Shavell's continuity and independence assumptions.
  • 52
    • 84923721818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Kaplow and Shavell note, "in reality, it will rarely be the case that one legal rule will literally make everyone better off than will another legal rule." supra note 2
    • As Kaplow and Shavell note, "in reality, it will rarely be the case that one legal rule will literally make everyone better off than will another legal rule." Kaplow & Shavell, Conflict, supra note 2, at 72.
    • Conflict , pp. 72
    • Kaplow1    Shavell2
  • 53
    • 0041161556 scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court, 1975 Term - Foreword: In Defense of the Antidiscrimination Principle
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 248. Kaplow and Shavell ask, for example, about "external preferences that have socially desirable effects," such as "disapprobation" that "deters individuals from improper behavior." Id. These effects, however, merely suggest that we may wish to encourage these external preferences for their instrumental value in promoting the satisfaction of personal preferences. It does not follow that we should count the satisfaction of these external preferences as instrinsically valuable components of social welfare. Kaplow and Shavell also criticize my use of the term "instrinsically immoral" as conclusory. Id. at 248 n.28 (quoting Chang, supra note 1, at 189 n.67)
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 248. Kaplow and Shavell ask, for example, about "external preferences that have socially desirable effects," such as "disapprobation" that "deters individuals from improper behavior." Id. These effects, however, merely suggest that we may wish to encourage these external preferences for their instrumental value in promoting the satisfaction of personal preferences. It does not follow that we should count the satisfaction of these external preferences as instrinsically valuable components of social welfare. Kaplow and Shavell also criticize my use of the term "instrinsically immoral" as conclusory. Id. at 248 n.28 (quoting Chang, supra note 1, at 189 n.67). The footnote that they quote, however, uses that term as a conclusion only after first explaining the distinctiwon between "purely self-regarding preferences" and "inherently discriminatory preferences" such as "'those reflecting overt racial hostility'" or "'racially selective sympathy.'" Chang, supra note 1, at 189 n.67 (quoting Paul Brest, The Supreme Court, 1975 Term - Foreword: In Defense of the Antidiscrimination Principle, 90 HARV. L. REV. 1, 8 (1976)).
    • (1976) HARV. L. REV. , vol.90 , pp. 1
    • Brest, P.1
  • 54
    • 84923714567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For example, is the sadist's pleasure of "seeing . . . victims suffer" a personal preference that ought to count? Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 248 n.28. To the extent that this sadist's preferences require that the victims actually suffer, however, this pleasure derives from an external preference. The component that is purely personal could be satisfied by actors pretending to suffer. Thus, the pleasure of seeing a snuff film would be objectionable, but the pleasure of seeing violence depicted using actors and special effects would not. In any event, I am open to arguments that there may exist some personal preferences that ought not to count. I have only criticized the suggestion that we must "exclude all personal preferences that derive from moral or political views." Chang, supra note 1, at 194 (emphasis added).
  • 55
    • 84923714566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 248
    • Kaplow & Shavell, supra note 5, at 248.
  • 56
    • 84923714565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Kaplow and Shavell endorse welfarism, they do not defend any particular functional form for the social welfare function.
  • 57
    • 84923714564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Perhaps Kaplow and Shavell mean to ask what legal and political institutions we should erect in order to make social choices. These issues, such as what constitution, what rights for individuals against the government, what democratic procedures, and what rules for judicial review we should adopt, are questions that each individual must answer according to that individual's moral and political beliefs. How to make social choices in the absence of any consensus on moral and political philosophies is itself a problem that we each must consider according to our own moral and political principles. Each of us may endorse the same electoral processes or doctrines of judicial restraint using entirely different moral and political theories.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.