메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 19, Issue 3, 1998, Pages 406-438

Rehabilitating Hobbes: Obligation, anti-Fascism and the myth of a 'Taylor thesis'

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0042279724     PISSN: 0143781X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (4)

References (197)
  • 1
    • 0042441455 scopus 로고
    • London
    • G.P. Gooch, Hobbes (London, 1939, 1970), p. 3.
    • (1939) Hobbes , pp. 3
    • Gooch, G.P.1
  • 2
    • 77954703174 scopus 로고
    • The ethical doctrine of Hobbes
    • October
    • A.E. Taylor, 'The Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', Philosophy, XIII, 52 (October 1938), pp. 406-24. The other 1938 essay, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes', appeared in Seventeenth Century Studies, ed. J. Dover Wilson (Oxford, 1938), pp. 129-47. Although this second essay appeared rather prominently, no one took any notice.
    • (1938) Philosophy , vol.13-52 , pp. 406-424
    • Taylor, A.E.1
  • 3
    • 77954703174 scopus 로고
    • An apology for Mr. Hobbes
    • Oxford
    • A.E. Taylor, 'The Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', Philosophy, XIII, 52 (October 1938), pp. 406-24. The other 1938 essay, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes', appeared in Seventeenth Century Studies, ed. J. Dover Wilson (Oxford, 1938), pp. 129-47. Although this second essay appeared rather prominently, no one took any notice.
    • (1938) Seventeenth Century Studies , pp. 129-147
    • Wilson, J.D.1
  • 4
    • 0010666062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • H. Warrender, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes: His Theory of Obligation (Oxford, 1957). I am currently working on a study of the various phases in the reception of Warrender's interpretation, from the earliest reviews by Oakeshott, Macpherson and others to the last bitter arguments stirred up by Skinner's demand that the interpretive purchase shift from text to intentional-conventional circumstances. At a certain point discussion of Warrender's assertions just peters out.
    • (1957) The Political Philosophy of Hobbes: His Theory of Obligation
    • Warrender, H.1
  • 5
    • 0042942222 scopus 로고
    • ed. Richard Tuck Cambridge
    • Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Richard Tuck (Cambridge, 1991), p. 144.
    • (1991) Leviathan , pp. 144
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 7
    • 0003737417 scopus 로고
    • London
    • It is perhaps worth noting that rhetorical analysis has all but entirely replaced these older ethical concerns. See, to name only a few, Raia Prokhovnik, Rhetoric and Philosophy in Hobbes's Leviathan (London, 1991); Victoria Kahn, 'Hobbes: A Rhetoric of Logic', in Rhetoric, Prudence, and Skepticism in the Renaissance (Ithaca, NY, 1985); and, of course, Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, 1996).
    • (1991) Rhetoric and Philosophy in Hobbes's Leviathan
    • Prokhovnik, R.1
  • 8
    • 0041439144 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes: A rhetoric of logic
    • Ithaca, NY
    • It is perhaps worth noting that rhetorical analysis has all but entirely replaced these older ethical concerns. See, to name only a few, Raia Prokhovnik, Rhetoric and Philosophy in Hobbes's Leviathan (London, 1991); Victoria Kahn, 'Hobbes: A Rhetoric of Logic', in Rhetoric, Prudence, and Skepticism in the Renaissance (Ithaca, NY, 1985); and, of course, Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, 1996).
    • (1985) Rhetoric, Prudence, and Skepticism in the Renaissance
    • Kahn, V.1
  • 9
    • 0003650067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • It is perhaps worth noting that rhetorical analysis has all but entirely replaced these older ethical concerns. See, to name only a few, Raia Prokhovnik, Rhetoric and Philosophy in Hobbes's Leviathan (London, 1991); Victoria Kahn, 'Hobbes: A Rhetoric of Logic', in Rhetoric, Prudence, and Skepticism in the Renaissance (Ithaca, NY, 1985); and, of course, Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, 1996).
    • (1996) Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 11
    • 0010666062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Just how this work was connected to Taylor before the publication of Warrender's The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, can be glimpsed in assessments made of Taylor's career at the time of his death in 1945. W.D. Ross, writing the major memorial in Proceeding of the British Academy (Oxford, 1945), does not mention Taylor's work on Hobbes at all. The lesser 1938 essay, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes' is even left out of the appended bibliography of Taylor's work. It is also interesting to note that the discussion of Taylor in the Dictionary of National Biography (London, 1941-50), which was written by D.M. MacKinnon, also leaves out mention of Taylor on Hobbes. MacKinnon was later mentioned by Warrender in his preface to The Political Philosophy of Hobbes as among those 'tutors and friends' who had helped shape his views of Hobbes.
    • The Political Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Warrender1
  • 12
    • 0041439141 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • Just how this work was connected to Taylor before the publication of Warrender's The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, can be glimpsed in assessments made of Taylor's career at the time of his death in 1945. W.D. Ross, writing the major memorial in Proceeding of the British Academy (Oxford, 1945), does not mention Taylor's work on Hobbes at all. The lesser 1938 essay, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes' is even left out of the appended bibliography of Taylor's work. It is also interesting to note that the discussion of Taylor in the Dictionary of National Biography (London, 1941-50), which was written by D.M. MacKinnon, also leaves out mention of Taylor on Hobbes. MacKinnon was later mentioned by Warrender in his preface to The Political Philosophy of Hobbes as among those 'tutors and friends' who had helped shape his views of Hobbes.
    • (1945) Proceeding of the British Academy
    • Ross, W.D.1
  • 13
    • 0004230658 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Just how this work was connected to Taylor before the publication of Warrender's The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, can be glimpsed in assessments made of Taylor's career at the time of his death in 1945. W.D. Ross, writing the major memorial in Proceeding of the British Academy (Oxford, 1945), does not mention Taylor's work on Hobbes at all. The lesser 1938 essay, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes' is even left out of the appended bibliography of Taylor's work. It is also interesting to note that the discussion of Taylor in the Dictionary of National Biography (London, 1941-50), which was written by D.M. MacKinnon, also leaves out mention of Taylor on Hobbes. MacKinnon was later mentioned by Warrender in his preface to The Political Philosophy of Hobbes as among those 'tutors and friends' who had helped shape his views of Hobbes.
    • (1941) Dictionary of National Biography
  • 14
    • 0010666062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Just how this work was connected to Taylor before the publication of Warrender's The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, can be glimpsed in assessments made of Taylor's career at the time of his death in 1945. W.D. Ross, writing the major memorial in Proceeding of the British Academy (Oxford, 1945), does not mention Taylor's work on Hobbes at all. The lesser 1938 essay, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes' is even left out of the appended bibliography of Taylor's work. It is also interesting to note that the discussion of Taylor in the Dictionary of National Biography (London, 1941-50), which was written by D.M. MacKinnon, also leaves out mention of Taylor on Hobbes. MacKinnon was later mentioned by Warrender in his preface to The Political Philosophy of Hobbes as among those 'tutors and friends' who had helped shape his views of Hobbes.
    • The Political Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Warrender1
  • 22
    • 0041940540 scopus 로고
    • Some other Taylor thesis
    • New Series June
    • His bibliography and its accompanying essay were published by the Philosophical Documentation Center and formed part of the Hobbes Tercentenary Congress which had been held in 1979. Just more than a decade later Sacksteder returned to the topic of the Taylor thesis. In a general and very appreciative article he again repeated many of his exaggerated claims about Taylor's significance and influence, again directing special attention to Taylor's innovations in method and style. 'Thus exposition of Hobbes', he concluded in regard to Taylor, 'is part only of the project in which he engages himself. The modality of his piece is exploration of fruitful analogies, mostly between Hobbes and Kant . . . The result combines valuable reopenings for reflections on Hobbes with a sketch of a doctrine of duty.' Excessive estimations of the 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes' are still there. 'I think this among the preeminent contributions to Hobbes scholarship', he wrote, 'though it remains controversial . . . For my own part, and limiting myself to Hobbesian interpretation only, I find Taylor's explorations plausible, if not definitive.' William Sacksteder, 'Some Other Taylor Thesis', International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, No. 11 (June 1990).
    • (1990) International Hobbes Association Newsletter , vol.11
    • Sacksteder, W.1
  • 23
    • 39049156552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Uncannily, Howard Warrender's devastating critical review of Sacksteder's contentions about Taylor and Hobbes Studies appears on a page in Political Studies facing his own obituary.
    • Political Studies
    • Warrender, H.1
  • 24
    • 84982719963 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes studies: Documentation versus history
    • Howard Warrender, 'Hobbes Studies: Documentation versus History', Political Studies, XXXIII (1985), pp. 304-7, p. 304.
    • (1985) Political Studies , vol.33 , pp. 304-307
    • Warrender, H.1
  • 30
    • 0041439098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The first part of Stuart Brown's essay was published separately because 'it offers the newcomer a useful introduction to the whole debate on the so-called 'Taylor-Warrender Thesis'. K.C. Brown had, in fact, printed this 'introduction' ahead of Taylor's own article. A self-fulfilling interpretation?
  • 32
    • 0042441399 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes: The Taylor thesis
    • Stuart Brown, 'Hobbes: The Taylor Thesis', Philosophical Review, 68 (1959), p. 303. The frankest judgment, however, would be that Taylor had 'adduced' virtually no evidence whatsoever.
    • (1959) Philosophical Review , vol.68 , pp. 303
    • Brown, S.1
  • 33
    • 0042441399 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes: The Taylor thesis
    • Ibid., p. 304. As if, somehow, Oakeshott had used but failed to cite Taylor. What can one possibly say in the face of arguments conducted in such a manner?
    • (1959) Philosophical Review , vol.68 , pp. 304
    • Brown, S.1
  • 35
    • 84977716339 scopus 로고
    • A note on Professor Oakeshott's introduction to the Leviathan'
    • J.M. Brown, 'A Note on Professor Oakeshott's Introduction to the Leviathan', Political Studies. 1 (1953), pp. 53-64; Dorothea Krook, 'Mr. Brown's Note Annotated', Political Studies, 1 (1953), pp. 216-27; and J.M. Brown, 'Hobbes: A Rejoinder', Political Studies, 2 (1954), pp. 168-72.
    • (1953) Political Studies , vol.1 , pp. 53-64
    • Brown, J.M.1
  • 36
    • 84977728904 scopus 로고
    • Mr. Brown's note annotated
    • J.M. Brown, 'A Note on Professor Oakeshott's Introduction to the Leviathan', Political Studies. 1 (1953), pp. 53-64; Dorothea Krook, 'Mr. Brown's Note Annotated', Political Studies, 1 (1953), pp. 216-27; and J.M. Brown, 'Hobbes: A Rejoinder', Political Studies, 2 (1954), pp. 168-72.
    • (1953) Political Studies , vol.1 , pp. 216-227
    • Krook, D.1
  • 37
    • 84977729944 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes: A rejoinder
    • J.M. Brown, 'A Note on Professor Oakeshott's Introduction to the Leviathan', Political Studies. 1 (1953), pp. 53-64; Dorothea Krook, 'Mr. Brown's Note Annotated', Political Studies, 1 (1953), pp. 216-27; and J.M. Brown, 'Hobbes: A Rejoinder', Political Studies, 2 (1954), pp. 168-72.
    • (1954) Political Studies , vol.2 , pp. 168-172
    • Brown, J.M.1
  • 38
    • 0041940536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbes: The problem of interpretation
    • ed. R. Koselleck and R. Schnur Berlin
    • The myth has been persistent. Even W.H. Greenleaf paid unquestioning lip service to it in 1969 (see W.H. Greenleaf, 'Hobbes: The Problem of Interpretation', in Hobbes-Forschungen, ed. R. Koselleck and R. Schnur (Berlin, 1969), pp. 9-32, especially pp. 13, 15-16. The myth was still apparently alive and well in 1994 for David Booin-Vail. 'Taylor's article', he wrote, 'provoked an enormous amount of discussion, but it still found few supporters'. D. Booin-Vail, Thomas Hobbes and the Science of Moral Virtue (Cambridge, 1994), pp. 92-3.
    • (1969) Hobbes-Forschungen , pp. 9-32
    • Greenleaf, W.H.1
  • 39
    • 0041940535 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • The myth has been persistent. Even W.H. Greenleaf paid unquestioning lip service to it in 1969 (see W.H. Greenleaf, 'Hobbes: The Problem of Interpretation', in Hobbes-Forschungen, ed. R. Koselleck and R. Schnur (Berlin, 1969), pp. 9-32, especially pp. 13, 15-16. The myth was still apparently alive and well in 1994 for David Booin-Vail. 'Taylor's article', he wrote, 'provoked an enormous amount of discussion, but it still found few supporters'. D. Booin-Vail, Thomas Hobbes and the Science of Moral Virtue (Cambridge, 1994), pp. 92-3.
    • (1994) Thomas Hobbes and the Science of Moral Virtue , pp. 92-93
    • Booin-Vail, D.1
  • 40
    • 0042942208 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes today
    • C.B. Macpherson, 'Hobbes Today', Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science, 11 (1945), pp. 524-34; J.W.N. Watkins, 'Philosophy and Politics in Hobbes', Philosophical Quarterly, 5 (1955), pp. 125-46; and J.W.N. Watkins, 'The Posthumous Career of Thomas Hobbes', Review of Politics, 19(3) (1957), pp. 351-60.
    • (1945) Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science , vol.11 , pp. 524-534
    • Macpherson, C.B.1
  • 41
    • 84963008345 scopus 로고
    • Philosophy and politics in Hobbes
    • C.B. Macpherson, 'Hobbes Today', Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science, 11 (1945), pp. 524-34; J.W.N. Watkins, 'Philosophy and Politics in Hobbes', Philosophical Quarterly, 5 (1955), pp. 125-46; and J.W.N. Watkins, 'The Posthumous Career of Thomas Hobbes', Review of Politics, 19(3) (1957), pp. 351-60.
    • (1955) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.5 , pp. 125-146
    • Watkins, J.W.N.1
  • 42
    • 0042441438 scopus 로고
    • The posthumous career of Thomas Hobbes
    • C.B. Macpherson, 'Hobbes Today', Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science, 11 (1945), pp. 524-34; J.W.N. Watkins, 'Philosophy and Politics in Hobbes', Philosophical Quarterly, 5 (1955), pp. 125-46; and J.W.N. Watkins, 'The Posthumous Career of Thomas Hobbes', Review of Politics, 19(3) (1957), pp. 351-60.
    • (1957) Review of Politics , vol.19 , Issue.3 , pp. 351-360
    • Watkins, J.W.N.1
  • 43
    • 0037739155 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes's concept of obligation
    • Thomas Nagel, 'Hobbes's Concept of Obligation', Philosophical Review, 68 (1959), pp. 68-83.
    • (1959) Philosophical Review , vol.68 , pp. 68-83
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 44
    • 84971120758 scopus 로고
    • Obligations and rights in Hobbes
    • D.D. Raphael, 'Obligations and Rights in Hobbes', Philosophy, 37 (1962), pp. 345-52.
    • (1962) Philosophy , vol.37 , pp. 345-352
    • Raphael, D.D.1
  • 45
    • 0004216228 scopus 로고
    • London
    • J.W.N. Watkins, Hobbes's System of Ideas (London, 1965). Moreover, in a review of Wartender's book, Watkins never mentions Taylor at all (Philosophy, XXVIX, 137 (1957-8), pp. 238-41).
    • (1965) Hobbes's System of Ideas
    • Watkins, J.W.N.1
  • 46
    • 0042942216 scopus 로고
    • XXVIX
    • J.W.N. Watkins, Hobbes's System of Ideas (London, 1965). Moreover, in a review of Wartender's book, Watkins never mentions Taylor at all (Philosophy, XXVIX, 137 (1957-8), pp. 238-41).
    • (1957) Philosophy , Issue.137 , pp. 238-241
    • Wartender1
  • 47
    • 84971139096 scopus 로고
    • Warrender and his critics
    • Brian Barry, 'Warrender and His Critics', Philosophy, 43 (1968), pp. 117-37.
    • (1968) Philosophy , vol.43 , pp. 117-137
    • Barry, B.1
  • 50
    • 0004077791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the essays in K.C. Brown, Hobbes Studies, especially the one by John Plamenatz. Throughout the time I have spent working on this essay, and during an even longer time spent researching the interesting and complicated story of Warrender's treatment by Hobbes scholars, I have not been able completely to dispel the suspicion that much of the significance granted to Taylor was part of the widespread attack on Warrender. But this is, as I said, merely suspicion.
    • Hobbes Studies
    • Brown, K.C.1
  • 53
    • 0042441447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes , pp. 406
  • 54
    • 0042441441 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • (1989) Essays in Political Philosophy
    • Collingwood, R.G.1
  • 55
    • 84942985153 scopus 로고
    • Fascism and nazism
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • (1940) Philosophy
  • 56
    • 0039607136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • The New Leviathan
  • 57
    • 84980139758 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • (1964) Political Quarterly , vol.35 , pp. 444
  • 58
    • 0040936041 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • (1957) Sovereignty , pp. 239
    • De Jouvenal, B.1
  • 59
    • 0041940530 scopus 로고
    • On the spirit of hobbes' political philosophy
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • (1950) Revue Internationale de Philosophie , vol.4 , pp. 405-431
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 60
    • 0042942207 scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • (1946) Leviathan
    • Oakeshott1
  • 61
    • 0041439136 scopus 로고
    • ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw London
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • (1925) The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries , pp. 169-172
    • Woodward, E.E.1
  • 62
    • 0007312765 scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hobbes
    • December
    • Ibid., p. 406. It should be pointed out that Taylor was not as alone in his sentiments as he was in his strategy. R.G. Collingwood felt at the same time that Hobbes represented just the civilized political attitudes which might prove effective antidotes to Fascism and Nazism. See R.G. Collingwood, Essays in Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1989), especially 'Fascism and Nazism', reprinted from Philosophy in 1940, and the draft preface to The New Leviathan. See also the interesting and opposite anxiety, that perhaps Hobbes might reasonably be considered as contributing to world tyranny, later expressed by Isaiah Berlin ('Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson', Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), p. 444) and Bertrand de Jouvenal (Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1957), p. 239), who thought he had detected the same anxiety expressed between the lines in Leo Strauss, 'On the Spirit of Hobbes' Political Philosophy', Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4 (1950), pp. 405-31 and in Oakeshott's 'Introduction' to Leviathan (1946). More faintly still, worry about whether Hobbes was somehow accountable for modern totalitarianism was there to be read in E.E. Woodward's article on Hobbes in The Social and Political Ideas of Some Great Thinkers of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, ed. F.J.C. Hearnshaw (London, 1925, 1936, 1949), pp. 169-72. See also the relief expressed by Michael Oakeshott in 1935 that Hobbes's political theory had been exonerated of the charge, levelled by Figgis and Vaughan, of being 'one of adulterated despotism or nothing'. Michael Oakeshott, 'Thomas Hobbes', Scrutiny, IV, 3 (December 1935), p. 272.
    • (1935) Scrutiny , vol.4 , Issue.3 , pp. 272
    • Oakeshott, M.1
  • 63
    • 84943197373 scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hobbes, ein authoritärer Engländer
    • Walter Wulfstich, 'Thomas Hobbes, ein authoritärer Engländer', Zeitschrift für neusprachlichen Unterricht, 40 (1941), pp. 219-25. See also Helmut Schelsky, 'Die Totalität des Staates bei Hobbes', Archiv für Rechts- und Sozial-philosophie, 31 (1938), pp. 176-93;
    • (1941) Zeitschrift für Neusprachlichen Unterricht , vol.40 , pp. 219-225
    • Wulfstich, W.1
  • 64
    • 0041940529 scopus 로고
    • Die totalität des staates bei Hobbes
    • Walter Wulfstich, 'Thomas Hobbes, ein authoritärer Engländer', Zeitschrift für neusprachlichen Unterricht, 40 (1941), pp. 219-25. See also Helmut Schelsky, 'Die Totalität des Staates bei Hobbes', Archiv für Rechts- und Sozial-philosophie, 31 (1938), pp. 176-93;
    • (1938) Archiv für Rechts- und Sozial-philosophie , vol.31 , pp. 176-193
    • Schelsky, H.1
  • 65
    • 0042942202 scopus 로고
    • Paris, Lyon
    • J. Vialatoux, La Cité De Hobbes, Théorie De L'état Totalitaire (Paris, Lyon, 1935), especially pp. 194-210; René Capitant, 'Hobbes et l'État totalitaire', Archives de Philosophie du Droit et de Sociologie Juridique, 6(1&2) (1936), pp. 46-75; René Capitant, 'Thomas Hobbes et le troisième reich', Allemagne Contemporaine, 20 (1936), pp. 55-7; Maurice de Gandillac, 'Du Leviathan à l'état Totalitaire', La Semaine Planétaire: La Vie Intellectuelle, 44 (1936), pp. 73-97; and Otto Koellreutter, 'Leviathan und totaler Staat', Reichsvenvaltungsblatt, 59(38) (1938), pp. 803-7. Norberte Bobbio, writing in 1974, reflected: 'Hobbes has been vituperated for centuries as a counselor to tyrants, and, in the 1930s, as the harbinger of the totalitarian state.' Norberto Bobbio, Thomas Hobbes and the Natural Law Tradition (Chicago and London, 1993), p. 221.
    • (1935) La Cité De Hobbes, Théorie De L'état Totalitaire , pp. 194-210
    • Vialatoux, J.1
  • 66
    • 84907679312 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes et l'état totalitaire
    • J. Vialatoux, La Cité De Hobbes, Théorie De L'état Totalitaire (Paris, Lyon, 1935), especially pp. 194-210; René Capitant, 'Hobbes et l'État totalitaire', Archives de Philosophie du Droit et de Sociologie Juridique, 6(1&2) (1936), pp. 46-75; René Capitant, 'Thomas Hobbes et le troisième reich', Allemagne Contemporaine, 20 (1936), pp. 55-7; Maurice de Gandillac, 'Du Leviathan à l'état Totalitaire', La Semaine Planétaire: La Vie Intellectuelle, 44 (1936), pp. 73-97; and Otto Koellreutter, 'Leviathan und totaler Staat', Reichsvenvaltungsblatt, 59(38) (1938), pp. 803-7. Norberte Bobbio, writing in 1974, reflected: 'Hobbes has been vituperated for centuries as a counselor to tyrants, and, in the 1930s, as the harbinger of the totalitarian state.' Norberto Bobbio, Thomas Hobbes and the Natural Law Tradition (Chicago and London, 1993), p. 221.
    • (1936) Archives de Philosophie du Droit et de Sociologie Juridique , vol.6 , Issue.1-2 , pp. 46-75
    • Capitant, R.1
  • 67
    • 0042942199 scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hobbes et le troisième reich
    • J. Vialatoux, La Cité De Hobbes, Théorie De L'état Totalitaire (Paris, Lyon, 1935), especially pp. 194-210; René Capitant, 'Hobbes et l'État totalitaire', Archives de Philosophie du Droit et de Sociologie Juridique, 6(1&2) (1936), pp. 46-75; René Capitant, 'Thomas Hobbes et le troisième reich', Allemagne Contemporaine, 20 (1936), pp. 55-7; Maurice de Gandillac, 'Du Leviathan à l'état Totalitaire', La Semaine Planétaire: La Vie Intellectuelle, 44 (1936), pp. 73-97; and Otto Koellreutter, 'Leviathan und totaler Staat', Reichsvenvaltungsblatt, 59(38) (1938), pp. 803-7. Norberte Bobbio, writing in 1974, reflected: 'Hobbes has been vituperated for centuries as a counselor to tyrants, and, in the 1930s, as the harbinger of the totalitarian state.' Norberto Bobbio, Thomas Hobbes and the Natural Law Tradition (Chicago and London, 1993), p. 221.
    • (1936) Allemagne Contemporaine , vol.20 , pp. 55-57
    • Capitant, R.1
  • 68
    • 0042942201 scopus 로고
    • Du leviathan à l'état totalitaire
    • J. Vialatoux, La Cité De Hobbes, Théorie De L'état Totalitaire (Paris, Lyon, 1935), especially pp. 194-210; René Capitant, 'Hobbes et l'État totalitaire', Archives de Philosophie du Droit et de Sociologie Juridique, 6(1&2) (1936), pp. 46-75; René Capitant, 'Thomas Hobbes et le troisième reich', Allemagne Contemporaine, 20 (1936), pp. 55-7; Maurice de Gandillac, 'Du Leviathan à l'état Totalitaire', La Semaine Planétaire: La Vie Intellectuelle, 44 (1936), pp. 73-97; and Otto Koellreutter, 'Leviathan und totaler Staat', Reichsvenvaltungsblatt, 59(38) (1938), pp. 803-7. Norberte Bobbio, writing in 1974, reflected: 'Hobbes has been vituperated for centuries as a counselor to tyrants, and, in the 1930s, as the harbinger of the totalitarian state.' Norberto Bobbio, Thomas Hobbes and the Natural Law Tradition (Chicago and London, 1993), p. 221.
    • (1936) La Semaine Planétaire: La Vie Intellectuelle , vol.44 , pp. 73-97
    • De Gandillac, M.1
  • 69
    • 0041439135 scopus 로고
    • Leviathan und totaler staat
    • J. Vialatoux, La Cité De Hobbes, Théorie De L'état Totalitaire (Paris, Lyon, 1935), especially pp. 194-210; René Capitant, 'Hobbes et l'État totalitaire', Archives de Philosophie du Droit et de Sociologie Juridique, 6(1&2) (1936), pp. 46-75; René Capitant, 'Thomas Hobbes et le troisième reich', Allemagne Contemporaine, 20 (1936), pp. 55-7; Maurice de Gandillac, 'Du Leviathan à l'état Totalitaire', La Semaine Planétaire: La Vie Intellectuelle, 44 (1936), pp. 73-97; and Otto Koellreutter, 'Leviathan und totaler Staat', Reichsvenvaltungsblatt, 59(38) (1938), pp. 803-7. Norberte Bobbio, writing in 1974, reflected: 'Hobbes has been vituperated for centuries as a counselor to tyrants, and, in the 1930s, as the harbinger of the totalitarian state.' Norberto Bobbio, Thomas Hobbes and the Natural Law Tradition (Chicago and London, 1993), p. 221.
    • (1938) Reichsvenvaltungsblatt , vol.59 , Issue.38 , pp. 803-807
    • Koellreutter, O.1
  • 70
    • 0040258148 scopus 로고
    • Chicago and London
    • J. Vialatoux, La Cité De Hobbes, Théorie De L'état Totalitaire (Paris, Lyon, 1935), especially pp. 194-210; René Capitant, 'Hobbes et l'État totalitaire', Archives de Philosophie du Droit et de Sociologie Juridique, 6(1&2) (1936), pp. 46-75; René Capitant, 'Thomas Hobbes et le troisième reich', Allemagne Contemporaine, 20 (1936), pp. 55-7; Maurice de Gandillac, 'Du Leviathan à l'état Totalitaire', La Semaine Planétaire: La Vie Intellectuelle, 44 (1936), pp. 73-97; and Otto Koellreutter, 'Leviathan und totaler Staat', Reichsvenvaltungsblatt, 59(38) (1938), pp. 803-7. Norberte Bobbio, writing in 1974, reflected: 'Hobbes has been vituperated for centuries as a counselor to tyrants, and, in the 1930s, as the harbinger of the totalitarian state.' Norberto Bobbio, Thomas Hobbes and the Natural Law Tradition (Chicago and London, 1993), p. 221.
    • (1993) Thomas Hobbes and the Natural Law Tradition , pp. 221
    • Bobbio, N.1
  • 71
    • 84943199708 scopus 로고
    • 'Hobbes' philosophy and its historical background'
    • Z. Lubienski, 'Hobbes' Philosophy and its Historical Background', Journal of Philosophical Studies, V, 18 (1930), pp. 175-90.
    • (1930) Journal of Philosophical Studies , vol.5 , Issue.18 , pp. 175-190
    • Lubienski, Z.1
  • 75
    • 0039751416 scopus 로고
    • London
    • John Laird, Hobbes (London, 1934), p. 205.
    • (1934) Hobbes , pp. 205
    • Laird, J.1
  • 76
    • 0041940531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 312, n. i.
    • Hobbes , vol.1 , pp. 312
  • 79
    • 0007187488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • passim
    • Ibid., and see pp. 155-75, passim. The roots of Strauss's argument in earlier discussions relevant to the modern state and Weimar are discussed with care, balance and acuity by John McCormick in his 'Fear, Technology, and the State: Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss, and the Revival of Hobbes in Weimar and National Socialist Germany', Political Theory, 22(4) (1994), pp. 612-52. In general, however, the large literature on Hobbes in German goes more or less without notice in Anglo-American Hobbes Studies. Schmitt's writings, of course, constitute an exception. Schmitt had been busy in 1938 in crediting Hobbes with the role of 'father of the totalitarian state'. See the very interesting essay by Gershon Weiler, 'Carl Schmitt on Hobbes', International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 12 (November 1990), pp. 3-8. See also Gershon Weiler, From Absolutism to Totalitarianism: Carl Schmitt on Thomas Hobbes (Durango, 1994), arguing that Schmitt, in so doing, had perhaps got Hobbes wrong. Horst Mewes, reviewing the book, is not so sure (International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 18 (June, 1994), pp. 8-12). Mewes points out that later on in 1965, returning to the study of Hobbes, Schmitt had come to the opinion that Hobbes was best understood by Howard Warrender and Francis Hood - no mention of Taylor, however.
    • The Political Philosophy of Hobbes , pp. 155-175
  • 80
    • 84970759054 scopus 로고
    • Fear, technology, and the state: Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss, and the revival of hobbes in Weimar and National Socialist Germany
    • Ibid., and see pp. 155-75, passim. The roots of Strauss's argument in earlier discussions relevant to the modern state and Weimar are discussed with care, balance and acuity by John McCormick in his 'Fear, Technology, and the State: Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss, and the Revival of Hobbes in Weimar and National Socialist Germany', Political Theory, 22(4) (1994), pp. 612-52. In general, however, the large literature on Hobbes in German goes more or less without notice in Anglo-American Hobbes Studies. Schmitt's writings, of course, constitute an exception. Schmitt had been busy in 1938 in crediting Hobbes with the role of 'father of the totalitarian state'. See the very interesting essay by Gershon Weiler, 'Carl Schmitt on Hobbes', International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 12 (November 1990), pp. 3-8. See also Gershon Weiler, From Absolutism to Totalitarianism: Carl Schmitt on Thomas Hobbes (Durango, 1994), arguing that Schmitt, in so doing, had perhaps got Hobbes wrong. Horst Mewes, reviewing the book, is not so sure (International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 18 (June, 1994), pp. 8-12). Mewes points out that later on in 1965, returning to the study of Hobbes, Schmitt had come to the opinion that Hobbes was best understood by Howard Warrender and Francis Hood - no mention of Taylor, however.
    • (1994) Political Theory , vol.22 , Issue.4 , pp. 612-652
    • McCormick, J.1
  • 81
    • 0042441434 scopus 로고
    • Carl Schmitt on Hobbes
    • New Series November
    • Ibid., and see pp. 155-75, passim. The roots of Strauss's argument in earlier discussions relevant to the modern state and Weimar are discussed with care, balance and acuity by John McCormick in his 'Fear, Technology, and the State: Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss, and the Revival of Hobbes in Weimar and National Socialist Germany', Political Theory, 22(4) (1994), pp. 612-52. In general, however, the large literature on Hobbes in German goes more or less without notice in Anglo-American Hobbes Studies. Schmitt's writings, of course, constitute an exception. Schmitt had been busy in 1938 in crediting Hobbes with the role of 'father of the totalitarian state'. See the very interesting essay by Gershon Weiler, 'Carl Schmitt on Hobbes', International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 12 (November 1990), pp. 3-8. See also Gershon Weiler, From Absolutism to Totalitarianism: Carl Schmitt on Thomas Hobbes (Durango, 1994), arguing that Schmitt, in so doing, had perhaps got Hobbes wrong. Horst Mewes, reviewing the book, is not so sure (International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 18 (June, 1994), pp. 8-12). Mewes points out that later on in 1965, returning to the study of Hobbes, Schmitt had come to the opinion that Hobbes was best understood by Howard Warrender and Francis Hood - no mention of Taylor, however.
    • (1990) International Hobbes Association Newsletter , vol.12 , pp. 3-8
    • Weiler, G.1
  • 82
    • 0005476957 scopus 로고
    • Durango
    • Ibid., and see pp. 155-75, passim. The roots of Strauss's argument in earlier discussions relevant to the modern state and Weimar are discussed with care, balance and acuity by John McCormick in his 'Fear, Technology, and the State: Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss, and the Revival of Hobbes in Weimar and National Socialist Germany', Political Theory, 22(4) (1994), pp. 612-52. In general, however, the large literature on Hobbes in German goes more or less without notice in Anglo-American Hobbes Studies. Schmitt's writings, of course, constitute an exception. Schmitt had been busy in 1938 in crediting Hobbes with the role of 'father of the totalitarian state'. See the very interesting essay by Gershon Weiler, 'Carl Schmitt on Hobbes', International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 12 (November 1990), pp. 3-8. See also Gershon Weiler, From Absolutism to Totalitarianism: Carl Schmitt on Thomas Hobbes (Durango, 1994), arguing that Schmitt, in so doing, had perhaps got Hobbes wrong. Horst Mewes, reviewing the book, is not so sure (International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 18 (June, 1994), pp. 8-12). Mewes points out that later on in 1965, returning to the study of Hobbes, Schmitt had come to the opinion that Hobbes was best understood by Howard Warrender and Francis Hood - no mention of Taylor, however.
    • (1994) From Absolutism to Totalitarianism: Carl Schmitt on Thomas Hobbes
    • Weiler, G.1
  • 83
    • 0042942200 scopus 로고
    • New Series June
    • Ibid., and see pp. 155-75, passim. The roots of Strauss's argument in earlier discussions relevant to the modern state and Weimar are discussed with care, balance and acuity by John McCormick in his 'Fear, Technology, and the State: Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss, and the Revival of Hobbes in Weimar and National Socialist Germany', Political Theory, 22(4) (1994), pp. 612-52. In general, however, the large literature on Hobbes in German goes more or less without notice in Anglo-American Hobbes Studies. Schmitt's writings, of course, constitute an exception. Schmitt had been busy in 1938 in crediting Hobbes with the role of 'father of the totalitarian state'. See the very interesting essay by Gershon Weiler, 'Carl Schmitt on Hobbes', International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 12 (November 1990), pp. 3-8. See also Gershon Weiler, From Absolutism to Totalitarianism: Carl Schmitt on Thomas Hobbes (Durango, 1994), arguing that Schmitt, in so doing, had perhaps got Hobbes wrong. Horst Mewes, reviewing the book, is not so sure (International Hobbes Association Newsletter, New Series, no. 18 (June, 1994), pp. 8-12). Mewes points out that later on in 1965, returning to the study of Hobbes, Schmitt had come to the opinion that Hobbes was best understood by Howard Warrender and Francis Hood - no mention of Taylor, however.
    • (1994) International Hobbes Association Newsletter , vol.18 , pp. 8-12
    • Mewes, H.1
  • 85
    • 0041439131 scopus 로고
    • Plato as fascist
    • June [review of Crossman]
    • R.C.K. Ensor, 'Plato as Fascist', London Mercury, XXXVI, 212 (June 1937), p. 203 [review of Crossman]; C.G. Field, 'Plato's Political Thought and Its Value Today', Philosophy, XVI, 63 (1941), H.B. Acton, 'The Alleged Fascism of Plato', Philosophy, XIII, 51 (1938); R.F. Alfred Hoernlè, 'Would Plato Have Approved of the National-Socialist State?', Philosophy, XIII, 50 (1938).
    • (1937) London Mercury , vol.36 , Issue.212 , pp. 203
    • Ensor, R.C.K.1
  • 86
    • 0041439132 scopus 로고
    • Plato's political thought and its value today
    • R.C.K. Ensor, 'Plato as Fascist', London Mercury, XXXVI, 212 (June 1937), p. 203 [review of Crossman]; C.G. Field, 'Plato's Political Thought and Its Value Today', Philosophy, XVI, 63 (1941), H.B. Acton, 'The Alleged Fascism of Plato', Philosophy, XIII, 51 (1938); R.F. Alfred Hoernlè, 'Would Plato Have Approved of the National-Socialist State?', Philosophy, XIII, 50 (1938).
    • (1941) Philosophy , vol.16 , Issue.63
    • Field, C.G.1
  • 87
    • 0042942198 scopus 로고
    • The alleged fascism of Plato
    • R.C.K. Ensor, 'Plato as Fascist', London Mercury, XXXVI, 212 (June 1937), p. 203 [review of Crossman]; C.G. Field, 'Plato's Political Thought and Its Value Today', Philosophy, XVI, 63 (1941), H.B. Acton, 'The Alleged Fascism of Plato', Philosophy, XIII, 51 (1938); R.F. Alfred Hoernlè, 'Would Plato Have Approved of the National-Socialist State?', Philosophy, XIII, 50 (1938).
    • (1938) Philosophy , vol.13 , Issue.51
    • Acton, H.B.1
  • 88
    • 84878447175 scopus 로고
    • Would plato have approved of the national-socialist state?
    • R.C.K. Ensor, 'Plato as Fascist', London Mercury, XXXVI, 212 (June 1937), p. 203 [review of Crossman]; C.G. Field, 'Plato's Political Thought and Its Value Today', Philosophy, XVI, 63 (1941), H.B. Acton, 'The Alleged Fascism of Plato', Philosophy, XIII, 51 (1938); R.F. Alfred Hoernlè, 'Would Plato Have Approved of the National-Socialist State?', Philosophy, XIII, 50 (1938).
    • (1938) Philosophy , vol.13 , Issue.50
    • Hoernlè, R.F.A.1
  • 89
    • 0003822522 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Karl Popper, The Open Society and its Enemies (New York, 1952), p. vii; 'The Autobiography of Karl Popper', in The Philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. Paul A. Schilpp (La Salle, 1974), p. 91.
    • (1952) The Open Society and Its Enemies
    • Popper, K.1
  • 90
    • 0007262567 scopus 로고
    • The autobiography of Karl Popper
    • La Salle
    • Karl Popper, The Open Society and its Enemies (New York, 1952), p. vii; 'The Autobiography of Karl Popper', in The Philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. Paul A. Schilpp (La Salle, 1974), p. 91.
    • (1974) The Philosophy of Karl Popper , pp. 91
    • Schilpp, P.A.1
  • 91
    • 0042942195 scopus 로고
    • Carl S. Friedrich, Journal of Social Philosophy, III, 3 (1938), p. 251. Stalin, it has recently been said, read Leviathan 'assiduously'. See Barry Cooper, The End of History (Toronto, 1984), p. 354, n. 30.
    • (1938) Journal of Social Philosophy , vol.3 , Issue.3 , pp. 251
    • Friedrich, C.S.1
  • 92
    • 0042441435 scopus 로고
    • Toronto
    • Carl S. Friedrich, Journal of Social Philosophy, III, 3 (1938), p. 251. Stalin, it has recently been said, read Leviathan 'assiduously'. See Barry Cooper, The End of History (Toronto, 1984), p. 354, n. 30.
    • (1984) The End of History , vol.30 , pp. 354
    • Cooper, B.1
  • 95
    • 0041439129 scopus 로고
    • The deification of the state
    • Carl S. Friedrich, 'The Deification of the State', The Review of Politics, I, 1 (1939), p. 29.
    • (1939) The Review of Politics , vol.1 , Issue.1 , pp. 29
    • Friedrich, C.S.1
  • 100
    • 0042441406 scopus 로고
    • The moral philosophy of Hobbes
    • J. A. Passmore, 'The Moral Philosophy of Hobbes', Australian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy, 19 (1941), p. 43; and see Alfred Cobban who includes Hobbes as a major precursor to the modern theory of dictatorship (Alfred Cobban, Dictatorship: Its History and Theory (New York, 1941), pp. 42-50). Cobban also devotes a chapter to Carl Schmitt's 'theory of dictatorship' (ibid., pp. 335-44).
    • (1941) Australian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy , vol.19 , pp. 43
    • Passmore, J.A.1
  • 101
    • 0041940500 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • J. A. Passmore, 'The Moral Philosophy of Hobbes', Australian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy, 19 (1941), p. 43; and see Alfred Cobban who includes Hobbes as a major precursor to the modern theory of dictatorship (Alfred Cobban, Dictatorship: Its History and Theory (New York, 1941), pp. 42-50). Cobban also devotes a chapter to Carl Schmitt's 'theory of dictatorship' (ibid., pp. 335-44).
    • (1941) Dictatorship: Its History and Theory , pp. 42-50
    • Cobban, A.1
  • 102
    • 0042942193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • J. A. Passmore, 'The Moral Philosophy of Hobbes', Australian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy, 19 (1941), p. 43; and see Alfred Cobban who includes Hobbes as a major precursor to the modern theory of dictatorship (Alfred Cobban, Dictatorship: Its History and Theory (New York, 1941), pp. 42-50). Cobban also devotes a chapter to Carl Schmitt's 'theory of dictatorship' (ibid., pp. 335-44).
    • Dictatorship: Its History and Theory , pp. 335-344
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 104
    • 0042942165 scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hobbes on absolutism
    • Joseph H. Fichter, 'Thomas Hobbes on Absolutism', The Modern Schoolman, XVI, 3 (1939), p. 64.
    • (1939) The Modern Schoolman , vol.16 , Issue.3 , pp. 64
    • Fichter, J.H.1
  • 106
    • 0041439127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gooch, Hobbes, p. 41. The Mussolini article is reprinted in full in The Social and Political Doctrines of Contemporary Europe, ed. Michael Oakeshott (Cambridge, 1939), pp. 164-79.
    • Hobbes , pp. 41
    • Gooch1
  • 111
    • 0004287799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 91. A Hobbes Society had been founded by Baron Cay von Brockdorff, and there was an international conference on Hobbes at Kiel in 1938. Perhaps both the Germans and Taylor had been drawn to notice Hobbes on his three hundred and fiftieth birthday. Taylor says nothing about it.
    • Leviathan , pp. 91
    • Hobbes1
  • 112
  • 115
  • 122
    • 0042942213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The choice of De Cive over Leviathan is central to the strategy adopted by Taylor in his second and strongest essay. He decided to move away from the latter to the former as 'a corrective to misunderstandings based on exclusive attention to the Leviathan'. Taylor, 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', p. 407. Sterling Lamprecht had also limited himself to De Cive because Leviathan was 'intellectually and philosophically . . . not as fine as the De Cive . . . it lacks reasoned integrity and scholarly poise . . . The De Cive, if less eloquent in its rhetoric, is very much more methodological and clear in its philosophical import' (Sterling Lamprecht, 'Hobbes and Hobbism', American Political Science Review, 34 (1940), p. 33). Warrender, too, while insisting that his thesis could be supported solely by Leviathan, went on to use De Cive extensively, because it did in fact more often support that thesis than did Leviathan. See Warrender's brief remarks in Warrender, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, pp. vii-viii. Later on, in a note on the publication of a new collected works of Hobbes, Warrender took a slightly different position. 'Superficially', he wrote, 'the various accounts of Hobbes's political philosophy look very similar. The guide to parallel passages shows that this similarity conceals a great deal of divergence.' Howard Warrender, 'Thomas Hobbes: The Collected Works, and a Note on a New Critical Edition', Revista Critica di Storia della Filosophia, 33 (1978), p. 244. Richard Tuck, more recently, argued that Leviathan and De Cive differ significantly on the question of the sovereign's interpretation of scripture. See Richard Tuck, 'Warrender's De Cive', Political Studies, XXXIII (1985), p. 312. The differences between De Cive and Leviathan have been most recently argued in Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Skinner virtually begins with this severe distinction, to wit: 'Hobbes's De Cive is arguably the most important work of political theory in the early 1640s, but it is as violently anti-rhetorical a text as Hobbes was capable of making it.' (Ibid., p. 6.) All in all, Taylor's choice of De Cive as base for his defence of Hobbes was actually to defend a Hobbes so unfamiliar as not to be the one who, even from Taylor's point of view, needed defending or rehabilitation.
    • Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes , pp. 407
    • Taylor1
  • 123
    • 0042441400 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes and hobbism
    • The choice of De Cive over Leviathan is central to the strategy adopted by Taylor in his second and strongest essay. He decided to move away from the latter to the former as 'a corrective to misunderstandings based on exclusive attention to the Leviathan'. Taylor, 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', p. 407. Sterling Lamprecht had also limited himself to De Cive because Leviathan was 'intellectually and philosophically . . . not as fine as the De Cive . . . it lacks reasoned integrity and scholarly poise . . . The De Cive, if less eloquent in its rhetoric, is very much more methodological and clear in its philosophical import' (Sterling Lamprecht, 'Hobbes and Hobbism', American Political Science Review, 34 (1940), p. 33). Warrender, too, while insisting that his thesis could be supported solely by Leviathan, went on to use De Cive extensively, because it did in fact more often support that thesis than did Leviathan. See Warrender's brief remarks in Warrender, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, pp. vii-viii. Later on, in a note on the publication of a new collected works of Hobbes, Warrender took a slightly different position. 'Superficially', he wrote, 'the various accounts of Hobbes's political philosophy look very similar. The guide to parallel passages shows that this similarity conceals a great deal of divergence.' Howard Warrender, 'Thomas Hobbes: The Collected Works, and a Note on a New Critical Edition', Revista Critica di Storia della Filosophia, 33 (1978), p. 244. Richard Tuck, more recently, argued that Leviathan and De Cive differ significantly on the question of the sovereign's interpretation of scripture. See Richard Tuck, 'Warrender's De Cive', Political Studies, XXXIII (1985), p. 312. The differences between De Cive and Leviathan have been most recently argued in Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Skinner virtually begins with this severe distinction, to wit: 'Hobbes's De Cive is arguably the most important work of political theory in the early 1640s, but it is as violently anti-rhetorical a text as Hobbes was capable of making it.' (Ibid., p. 6.) All in all, Taylor's choice of De Cive as base for his defence of Hobbes was actually to defend a Hobbes so unfamiliar as not to be the one who, even from Taylor's point of view, needed defending or rehabilitation.
    • (1940) American Political Science Review , vol.34 , pp. 33
    • Lamprecht, S.1
  • 124
    • 0010666062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The choice of De Cive over Leviathan is central to the strategy adopted by Taylor in his second and strongest essay. He decided to move away from the latter to the former as 'a corrective to misunderstandings based on exclusive attention to the Leviathan'. Taylor, 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', p. 407. Sterling Lamprecht had also limited himself to De Cive because Leviathan was 'intellectually and philosophically . . . not as fine as the De Cive . . . it lacks reasoned integrity and scholarly poise . . . The De Cive, if less eloquent in its rhetoric, is very much more methodological and clear in its philosophical import' (Sterling Lamprecht, 'Hobbes and Hobbism', American Political Science Review, 34 (1940), p. 33). Warrender, too, while insisting that his thesis could be supported solely by Leviathan, went on to use De Cive extensively, because it did in fact more often support that thesis than did Leviathan. See Warrender's brief remarks in Warrender, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, pp. vii-viii. Later on, in a note on the publication of a new collected works of Hobbes, Warrender took a slightly different position. 'Superficially', he wrote, 'the various accounts of Hobbes's political philosophy look very similar. The guide to parallel passages shows that this similarity conceals a great deal of divergence.' Howard Warrender, 'Thomas Hobbes: The Collected Works, and a Note on a New Critical Edition', Revista Critica di Storia della Filosophia, 33 (1978), p. 244. Richard Tuck, more recently, argued that Leviathan and De Cive differ significantly on the question of the sovereign's interpretation of scripture. See Richard Tuck, 'Warrender's De Cive', Political Studies, XXXIII (1985), p. 312. The differences between De Cive and Leviathan have been most recently argued in Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Skinner virtually begins with this severe distinction, to wit: 'Hobbes's De Cive is arguably the most important work of political theory in the early 1640s, but it is as violently anti-rhetorical a text as Hobbes was capable of making it.' (Ibid., p. 6.) All in all, Taylor's choice of De Cive as base for his defence of Hobbes was actually to defend a Hobbes so unfamiliar as not to be the one who, even from Taylor's point of view, needed defending or rehabilitation.
    • The Political Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Warrender1
  • 125
    • 0041439097 scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hobbes: The collected works, and a note on a new critical edition
    • The choice of De Cive over Leviathan is central to the strategy adopted by Taylor in his second and strongest essay. He decided to move away from the latter to the former as 'a corrective to misunderstandings based on exclusive attention to the Leviathan'. Taylor, 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', p. 407. Sterling Lamprecht had also limited himself to De Cive because Leviathan was 'intellectually and philosophically . . . not as fine as the De Cive . . . it lacks reasoned integrity and scholarly poise . . . The De Cive, if less eloquent in its rhetoric, is very much more methodological and clear in its philosophical import' (Sterling Lamprecht, 'Hobbes and Hobbism', American Political Science Review, 34 (1940), p. 33). Warrender, too, while insisting that his thesis could be supported solely by Leviathan, went on to use De Cive extensively, because it did in fact more often support that thesis than did Leviathan. See Warrender's
    • (1978) Revista Critica di Storia della Filosophia , vol.33 , pp. 244
    • Warrender, H.1
  • 126
    • 84982732910 scopus 로고
    • Warrender's de cive
    • The choice of De Cive over Leviathan is central to the strategy adopted by Taylor in his second and strongest essay. He decided to move away from the latter to the former as 'a corrective to misunderstandings based on exclusive attention to the Leviathan'. Taylor, 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', p. 407. Sterling Lamprecht had also limited himself to De Cive because Leviathan was 'intellectually and philosophically . . . not as fine as the De Cive . . . it lacks reasoned integrity and scholarly poise . . . The De Cive, if less eloquent in its rhetoric, is very much more methodological and clear in its philosophical import' (Sterling Lamprecht, 'Hobbes and Hobbism', American Political Science Review, 34 (1940), p. 33). Warrender, too, while insisting that his thesis could be supported solely by Leviathan, went on to use De Cive extensively, because it did in fact more often support that thesis than did Leviathan. See Warrender's brief remarks in Warrender, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, pp. vii-viii. Later on, in a note on the publication of a new collected works of Hobbes, Warrender took a slightly different position. 'Superficially', he wrote, 'the various accounts of Hobbes's political philosophy look very similar. The guide to parallel passages shows that this similarity conceals a great deal of divergence.' Howard Warrender, 'Thomas Hobbes: The Collected Works, and a Note on a New Critical Edition', Revista Critica di Storia della Filosophia, 33 (1978), p. 244. Richard Tuck, more recently, argued that Leviathan and De Cive differ significantly on the question of the sovereign's interpretation of scripture. See Richard Tuck, 'Warrender's De Cive', Political Studies, XXXIII (1985), p. 312. The differences between De Cive and Leviathan have been most recently argued in Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Skinner virtually begins with this severe distinction, to wit: 'Hobbes's De Cive is arguably the most important work of political theory in the early 1640s, but it is as violently anti-rhetorical a text as Hobbes was capable of making it.' (Ibid., p. 6.) All in all, Taylor's choice of De Cive as base for his defence of Hobbes was actually to defend a Hobbes so unfamiliar as not to be the one who, even from Taylor's point of view, needed defending or rehabilitation.
    • (1985) Political Studies , vol.33 , pp. 312
    • Tuck, R.1
  • 127
    • 0003650067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The choice of De Cive over Leviathan is central to the strategy adopted by Taylor in his second and strongest essay. He decided to move away from the latter to the former as 'a corrective to misunderstandings based on exclusive attention to the Leviathan'. Taylor, 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', p. 407. Sterling Lamprecht had also limited himself to De Cive because Leviathan was 'intellectually and philosophically . . . not as fine as the De Cive . . . it lacks reasoned integrity and scholarly poise . . . The De Cive, if less eloquent in its rhetoric, is very much more methodological and clear in its philosophical import' (Sterling Lamprecht, 'Hobbes and Hobbism', American Political Science Review, 34 (1940), p. 33). Warrender, too, while insisting that his thesis could be supported solely by Leviathan, went on to use De Cive extensively, because it did in fact more often support that thesis than did Leviathan. See Warrender's brief remarks in Warrender, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, pp. vii-viii. Later on, in a note on the publication of a new collected works of Hobbes, Warrender took a slightly different position. 'Superficially', he wrote, 'the various accounts of Hobbes's political philosophy look very similar. The guide to parallel passages shows that this similarity conceals a great deal of divergence.' Howard Warrender, 'Thomas Hobbes: The Collected Works, and a Note on a New Critical Edition', Revista Critica di Storia della Filosophia, 33 (1978), p. 244. Richard Tuck, more recently, argued that Leviathan and De Cive differ significantly on the question of the sovereign's interpretation of scripture. See Richard Tuck, 'Warrender's De Cive', Political Studies, XXXIII (1985), p. 312. The differences between De Cive and Leviathan have been most recently argued in Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Skinner virtually begins with this severe distinction, to wit: 'Hobbes's De Cive is arguably the most important work of political theory in the early 1640s, but it is as violently anti-rhetorical a text as Hobbes was capable of making it.' (Ibid., p. 6.) All in all, Taylor's choice of De Cive as base for his defence of Hobbes was actually to defend a Hobbes so unfamiliar as not to be the one who, even from Taylor's point of view, needed defending or rehabilitation.
    • Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Skinner1
  • 128
    • 0003650067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The choice of De Cive over Leviathan is central to the strategy adopted by Taylor in his second and strongest essay. He decided to move away from the latter to the former as 'a corrective to misunderstandings based on exclusive attention to the Leviathan'. Taylor, 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', p. 407. Sterling Lamprecht had also limited himself to De Cive because Leviathan was 'intellectually and philosophically . . . not as fine as the De Cive . . . it lacks reasoned integrity and scholarly poise . . . The De Cive, if less eloquent in its rhetoric, is very much more methodological and clear in its philosophical import' (Sterling Lamprecht, 'Hobbes and Hobbism', American Political Science Review, 34 (1940), p. 33). Warrender, too, while insisting that his thesis could be supported solely by Leviathan, went on to use De Cive extensively, because it did in fact more often support that thesis than did Leviathan. See Warrender's brief remarks in Warrender, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, pp. vii-viii. Later on, in a note on the publication of a new collected works of Hobbes, Warrender took a slightly different position. 'Superficially', he wrote, 'the various accounts of Hobbes's political philosophy look very similar. The guide to parallel passages shows that this similarity conceals a great deal of divergence.' Howard Warrender, 'Thomas Hobbes: The Collected Works, and a Note on a New Critical Edition', Revista Critica di Storia della Filosophia, 33 (1978), p. 244. Richard Tuck, more recently, argued that Leviathan and De Cive differ significantly on the question of the sovereign's interpretation of scripture. See Richard Tuck, 'Warrender's De Cive', Political Studies, XXXIII (1985), p. 312. The differences between De Cive and Leviathan have been most recently argued in Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Skinner virtually begins with this severe distinction, to wit: 'Hobbes's De Cive is arguably the most important work of political theory in the early 1640s, but it is as violently anti-rhetorical a text as Hobbes was capable of making it.' (Ibid., p. 6.) All in all, Taylor's choice of De Cive as base for his defence of Hobbes was actually to defend a Hobbes so unfamiliar as not to be the one who, even from Taylor's point of view, needed defending or rehabilitation.
    • Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes , pp. 6
  • 129
    • 0041940498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 2, above
    • See note 2, above.
  • 130
    • 0041439099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Oddly, neither paper cites or refers to the other or to Taylor's own book in any way.
  • 132
    • 0041439104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taylor cites Laird twice (once in each essay) without referencing a source. The quotes are prejudicial and used as authority for points simply not otherwise capable of being made about Hobbes. In the first, in characterizing Hobbes's moral theory at large, Taylor writes that it 'is, as Professor Laird has said, "wicked", in a way which Hobbes is not' (Taylor, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes', p. 137 n.). In the second is this: 'that Hobbes was a fundamentally honest man, and a man, as Professor Laird has said, with an almost overwhelming sense of duty' (Taylor, 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', p. 422).
    • An Apology for Mr. Hobbes , pp. 137
    • Taylor1
  • 133
    • 0042942213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taylor cites Laird twice (once in each essay) without referencing a source. The quotes are prejudicial and used as authority for points simply not otherwise capable of being made about Hobbes. In the first, in characterizing Hobbes's moral theory at large, Taylor writes that it 'is, as Professor Laird has said, "wicked", in a way which Hobbes is not' (Taylor, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes', p. 137 n.). In the second is this: 'that Hobbes was a fundamentally honest man, and a man, as Professor Laird has said, with an almost overwhelming sense of duty' (Taylor, 'Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes', p. 422).
    • Ethical Doctrine of Hobbes , pp. 422
    • Taylor1
  • 134
    • 0041439104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taylor, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes', p. 147. In 1925, however, in one of J.H. Muirhead's two volumes of 'personal statements' by contemporary philosophers, Taylor had written of Hobbes that when he 'actually defined "the will" as the "last appetite in deliberation", he virtually denied that there is any such act as choice. Hence, against him, it had to be shown, first that choice is a genuine specific experience, and next that there is a real moral difference between choosing to do a thing because you judge the doing of it to be good and doing it because you are terrified by the menaces of a human or superhuman despot.' A.E. Taylor, 'The Freedom of Man', in J.H. Muirhead, Contemporary British Philosophy (London, 1925), p. 276 (emphasis added).
    • An Apology for Mr. Hobbes , pp. 147
    • Taylor1
  • 135
    • 0041439101 scopus 로고
    • The freedom of man
    • J.H. Muirhead, London, (emphasis added)
    • Taylor, 'An Apology for Mr. Hobbes', p. 147. In 1925, however, in one of J.H. Muirhead's two volumes of 'personal statements' by contemporary philosophers, Taylor had written of Hobbes that when he 'actually defined "the will" as the "last appetite in deliberation", he virtually denied that there is any such act as choice. Hence, against him, it had to be shown, first that choice is a genuine specific experience, and next that there is a real moral difference between choosing to do a thing because you judge the doing of it to be good and doing it because you are terrified by the menaces of a human or superhuman despot.' A.E. Taylor, 'The Freedom of Man', in J.H. Muirhead, Contemporary British Philosophy (London, 1925), p. 276 (emphasis added).
    • (1925) Contemporary British Philosophy , pp. 276
    • Taylor, A.E.1
  • 138
    • 0041439104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 142. In his Gifford Lectures, delivered in 1926-8 and published in 1931, Taylor still held a more caustic opinion of Hobbes's views on God. Acknowledging that on Hobbes's view there might well be as many religions as there were individuals, 'this does not very much matter' to Hobbes, because 'he really cares nothing about religion and wholly disbelieves in its worth as a knowledge and worship of God. Knowledge of God, according to his philosophy, is impossible, because God is 'ingenerable'. Obedience to established worship is no more than an obedience to law compounded with an unwillingness 'to disturb the King's peace for any metaphysical puillets of our own' (A.E. Taylor, Faith of a Moralist (London, 1931), Vol. II, pp. 203-4.
    • An Apology for Mr Hobbes , pp. 142
  • 139
    • 0041940496 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Ibid., p. 142. In his Gifford Lectures, delivered in 1926-8 and published in 1931, Taylor still held a more caustic opinion of Hobbes's views on God. Acknowledging that on Hobbes's view there might well be as many religions as there were individuals, 'this does not very much matter' to Hobbes, because 'he really cares nothing about religion and wholly disbelieves in its worth as a knowledge and worship of God. Knowledge of God, according to his philosophy, is impossible, because God is 'ingenerable'. Obedience to established worship is no more than an obedience to law compounded with an unwillingness 'to disturb the King's peace for any metaphysical puillets of our own' (A.E. Taylor, Faith of a Moralist (London, 1931), Vol. II, pp. 203-4.
    • (1931) Faith of a Moralist , vol.2 , pp. 203-204
    • Taylor, A.E.1
  • 146
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고
    • In a 1939 essay, 'The Right and the Good', in which he discussed the 'new deontology' of Ross and Prichard, Taylor distinguished his own views with respect to the obligations created by law and its sanctions. They were only further inducements to an obligation already rooted in promises and other social acts. 'I, do not, of course', Taylor wrote, 'mean by saying this to agree with the utilitarian thesis that "a penal sanction" is part of the very meaning of obligation. My view is rather that of Hobbes that the law and its penalties "tie a man being bound".' A.E. Taylor, 'The Right and the Good', Mind, XLVIII (1939), p. 273.
    • (1939) The Right and the Good
  • 147
    • 0042942157 scopus 로고
    • The right and the good
    • In a 1939 essay, 'The Right and the Good', in which he discussed the 'new deontology' of Ross and Prichard, Taylor distinguished his own views with respect to the obligations created by law and its sanctions. They were only further inducements to an obligation already rooted in promises and other social acts. 'I, do not, of course', Taylor wrote, 'mean by saying this to agree with the utilitarian thesis that "a penal sanction" is part of the very meaning of obligation. My view is rather that of Hobbes that the law and its penalties "tie a man being bound".' A.E. Taylor, 'The Right and the Good', Mind, XLVIII (1939), p. 273.
    • (1939) Mind , vol.48 , pp. 273
    • Taylor, A.E.1
  • 178
    • 0041940494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is not meant, by the way, to be anything like a complete or systematic criticism of Taylor's article. The misreadings and sleights of hand are too extensive to be pursued here and, as illustrated by Stuart Brown's earlier critique, the temptation is often just to substitute the contours of one's own reading for Taylor's and that is not my purpose. Moreover, I cannot conceive of a systematic criticism of Taylor that did not find itself drawn irresistibly into discussion of Warrender's longer, sharper, more honest and more carefully argued presentation. That, too, is beyond the scope of the present writing.
  • 184
    • 0041940493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 412, citing Hobbes, De Cive, III, 29.
    • De Cive , vol.3 , pp. 29
    • Hobbes1
  • 185
    • 0042441391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 414.
    • De Cive , pp. 414
  • 186
    • 0042441393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 415.
    • De Cive , pp. 415
  • 197
    • 0042942153 scopus 로고
    • London
    • It is, after all, a very different thing to say, as von Leyden has said (and as Taylor also believed), that 'neither can there be any doubt that [Hobbes] himself was not an atheist', and saying, as we have repeatedly seen Taylor do, that God plays a significant theoretical role in Hobbes's political thought. See, W. von Leyden, Hobbes and Locke (London, 1982), p. 70.
    • (1982) Hobbes and Locke , pp. 70
    • Von Leyden, W.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.