메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 60, Issue 3, 1999, Pages 399-416

Weeds: Cultivating the imagination in medieval arabic political philosophy

(1)  Kochin, Michael S a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0042208735     PISSN: 00225037     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3654010     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (15)

References (116)
  • 1
    • 0041768017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 21ff
    • Apology 21ff, cf. Symposium 220d.
    • Apology
  • 2
    • 85076585694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Apology 21ff, cf. Symposium 220d.
    • Symposium
  • 3
    • 4244071194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • tr. David Ames Curtis Atlantic Highlands, N.J.
    • On the religio-political significance of the twelve-month cycle see Pierre Lévêque and Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Cleisthenes the Athenian, tr. David Ames Curtis (Atlantic Highlands, N.J., 1996), 67, 96-97.
    • (1996) Cleisthenes the Athenian , vol.67 , pp. 96-97
    • Lévêque, P.1    Vidal-Naquet, P.2
  • 4
    • 0043271072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Such a resolution though periodization flies in the face of numerous passages in both the "early" and the "later" dialogues. In the Gorgias Socrates claims to be the only true politician in Athens - the city as a whole is disordered, filled up with the toxins of excess, but Socrates the political physician claims to be able to diagnose the disease and propose, if not impose, the remedy (518b ff., 521d). In the Laws, on the other hand, the Athenian Stranger recognizes that the best human beings do not necessarily grow up in the best-governed city (951bc), thereby admitting that the standard for political order does not simply transcend and realize the standard for order within the individual but can contradict and subvert it.
  • 5
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republic 520a-c; all translations from the Greek are my own.
    • Republic
  • 6
    • 25744436910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Charmides 153d.
    • Charmides
  • 7
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republic 488.
    • Republic , pp. 488
  • 8
    • 0042769814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alfarabi, Political Regime, N104-107; selections tr. Fauzi M. Najjar, in Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, ed. Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi (Ithaca, N.Y., 1972), 53-56. Whereas Plato uses the image of the sun to describe the relation of the idea of the good to the other intelligibles, Alfarabi uses this image and Plato's language to describe the relation of the Active Intellect to the other intelligibles (Republic 508a ff., Political Regime N35-36). All translations from The Political Regime are drawn from Fauzi Najjar's published and Miriam Galston's unpublished partial translations (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy); but I have also consulted Shukhri Abed's complete Hebrew translation (Tel Aviv, 1992). References to the Political Regime are to Najjar's Arabic edition, Al-Siyāsāt al-madaniyyah (Beirut: Matba'ah al-kāthūlīkiyyah, 1964), as used by Galston and Abed (preceded by N), and to Medieval Political Philosophy, when the passage is translated by Najjar.
    • Political Regime
    • Alfarabi1
  • 9
    • 0004020506 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.
    • Alfarabi, Political Regime, N104-107; selections tr. Fauzi M. Najjar, in Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, ed. Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi (Ithaca, N.Y., 1972), 53-56. Whereas Plato uses the image of the sun to describe the relation of the idea of the good to the other intelligibles, Alfarabi uses this image and Plato's language to describe the relation of the Active Intellect to the other intelligibles (Republic 508a ff., Political Regime N35-36). All translations from The Political Regime are drawn from Fauzi Najjar's published and Miriam Galston's unpublished partial translations (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy); but I have also consulted Shukhri Abed's complete Hebrew translation (Tel Aviv, 1992). References to the Political Regime are to Najjar's Arabic edition, Al-Siyāsāt al-madaniyyah (Beirut: Matba'ah al-kāthūlīkiyyah, 1964), as used by Galston and Abed (preceded by N), and to Medieval Political Philosophy, when the passage is translated by Najjar.
    • (1972) Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook , pp. 53-56
    • Najjar, F.M.1    Lerner, R.2    Mahdi, M.3
  • 10
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 508a ff
    • Alfarabi, Political Regime, N104-107; selections tr. Fauzi M. Najjar, in Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, ed. Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi (Ithaca, N.Y., 1972), 53-56. Whereas Plato uses the image of the sun to describe the relation of the idea of the good to the other intelligibles, Alfarabi uses this image and Plato's language to describe the relation of the Active Intellect to the other intelligibles (Republic 508a ff., Political Regime N35-36). All translations from The Political Regime are drawn from Fauzi Najjar's published and Miriam Galston's unpublished partial translations (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy); but I have also consulted Shukhri Abed's complete Hebrew translation (Tel Aviv, 1992). References to the Political Regime are to Najjar's Arabic edition, Al-Siyāsāt al-madaniyyah (Beirut: Matba'ah al-kāthūlīkiyyah, 1964), as used by Galston and Abed (preceded by N), and to Medieval Political Philosophy, when the passage is translated by Najjar.
    • Republic
  • 11
    • 0042769814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alfarabi, Political Regime, N104-107; selections tr. Fauzi M. Najjar, in Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, ed. Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi (Ithaca, N.Y., 1972), 53-56. Whereas Plato uses the image of the sun to describe the relation of the idea of the good to the other intelligibles, Alfarabi uses this image and Plato's language to describe the relation of the Active Intellect to the other intelligibles (Republic 508a ff., Political Regime N35-36). All translations from The Political Regime are drawn from Fauzi Najjar's published and Miriam Galston's unpublished partial translations (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy); but I have also consulted Shukhri Abed's complete Hebrew translation (Tel Aviv, 1992). References to the Political Regime are to Najjar's Arabic edition, Al-Siyāsāt al-madaniyyah (Beirut: Matba'ah al-kāthūlīkiyyah, 1964), as used by Galston and Abed (preceded by N), and to Medieval Political Philosophy, when the passage is translated by Najjar.
    • Political Regime
  • 12
    • 0043271070 scopus 로고
    • Al-siyāsāt al-madaniyyah
    • Najjar's Arabic edition, Beirut: Matba'ah al-kāthūlīkiyyah
    • Alfarabi, Political Regime, N104-107; selections tr. Fauzi M. Najjar, in Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, ed. Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi (Ithaca, N.Y., 1972), 53-56. Whereas Plato uses the image of the sun to describe the relation of the idea of the good to the other intelligibles, Alfarabi uses this image and Plato's language to describe the relation of the Active Intellect to the other intelligibles (Republic 508a ff., Political Regime N35-36). All translations from The Political Regime are drawn from Fauzi Najjar's published and Miriam Galston's unpublished partial translations (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy); but I have also consulted Shukhri Abed's complete Hebrew translation (Tel Aviv, 1992). References to the Political Regime are to Najjar's Arabic edition, Al-Siyāsāt al-madaniyyah (Beirut: Matba'ah al-kāthūlīkiyyah, 1964), as used by Galston and Abed (preceded by N), and to Medieval Political Philosophy, when the passage is translated by Najjar.
    • (1964) Political Regime
  • 13
    • 0042769810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (preceded by N), translated by Najjar
    • Alfarabi, Political Regime, N104-107; selections tr. Fauzi M. Najjar, in Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, ed. Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi (Ithaca, N.Y., 1972), 53-56. Whereas Plato uses the image of the sun to describe the relation of the idea of the good to the other intelligibles, Alfarabi uses this image and Plato's language to describe the relation of the Active Intellect to the other intelligibles (Republic 508a ff., Political Regime N35-36). All translations from The Political Regime are drawn from Fauzi Najjar's published and Miriam Galston's unpublished partial translations (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy); but I have also consulted Shukhri Abed's complete Hebrew translation (Tel Aviv, 1992). References to the Political Regime are to Najjar's Arabic edition, Al-Siyāsāt al-madaniyyah (Beirut: Matba'ah al-kāthūlīkiyyah, 1964), as used by Galston and Abed (preceded by N), and to Medieval Political Philosophy, when the passage is translated by Najjar.
    • Medieval Political Philosophy
    • Galston1    Abed2
  • 14
    • 0041768005 scopus 로고
    • Fārābī's funny flora: Al-nawābit as 'opposition,'
    • On the historical background of the term "weeds" (in Arabic, al-nawābit), see Ilai Alon, "Fārābī's Funny Flora: Al-nawābit as 'Opposition,' "Arabica, 37 (1990), 56-90. Alon notes that while the term emerges in ninth-century disputes over the Caliphate, Alfarabi gives it the novel general meaning of "oppositionists," those who oppose the rulers and their doctrines, without regard for the specific doctrine opposed.
    • (1990) Arabica , vol.37 , pp. 56-90
    • Alon, I.1
  • 15
    • 0043271067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Governance of the solitary
    • Governance of the Solitary, tr. Lawrence Berman, in Medieval Political Philosophy, 127. References to The Governance of the Solitary given by page number.
    • Medieval Political Philosophy , pp. 127
    • Berman, L.1
  • 16
    • 0041768015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • given by page number
    • Governance of the Solitary, tr. Lawrence Berman, in Medieval Political Philosophy, 127. References to The Governance of the Solitary given by page number.
    • The Governance of the Solitary
  • 19
    • 84894908575 scopus 로고
    • Attainment of happiness
    • rev. ed., Ithaca, N.Y., sec. 45
    • Attainment of Happiness, in The Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, tr. Muhsin Mahdi (rev. ed., Ithaca, N.Y., 1969), sec. 45.
    • (1969) The Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle
    • Mahdi, M.1
  • 20
    • 0042769814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This statement of the relation between political science and philosophy is based on Alfarabi's accounts of political science in the Political Regime, the Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, and the Opinions of the Citizens of the Virtuous City, ed. and tr. Richard Walzer as Alfarabi's Perfect State (Oxford, 1985). As Miriam Galston has shown in Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi (Princeton, 1990), the relation of political science to philosophy (and thus of political practice to philosophic inquiry) appears in a very different light in Alfarabi's Selected Aphorisms; see Aphorisms of the Statesman, ed. and tr. D. M. Dunlop (Cambridge, 1962), aphorism 4; Politics and Excellence, 123-24, 188.
    • Political Regime
    • Alfarabi1
  • 21
    • 0009983223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This statement of the relation between political science and philosophy is based on Alfarabi's accounts of political science in the Political Regime, the Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, and the Opinions of the Citizens of the Virtuous City, ed. and tr. Richard Walzer as Alfarabi's Perfect State (Oxford, 1985). As Miriam Galston has shown in Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi (Princeton, 1990), the relation of political science to philosophy (and thus of political practice to philosophic inquiry) appears in a very different light in Alfarabi's Selected Aphorisms; see Aphorisms of the Statesman, ed. and tr. D. M. Dunlop (Cambridge, 1962), aphorism 4; Politics and Excellence, 123-24, 188.
    • Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle
  • 22
    • 0042769765 scopus 로고
    • Opinions of the citizens of the virtuous city
    • Oxford
    • This statement of the relation between political science and philosophy is based on Alfarabi's accounts of political science in the Political Regime, the Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, and the Opinions of the Citizens of the Virtuous City, ed. and tr. Richard Walzer as Alfarabi's Perfect State (Oxford, 1985). As Miriam Galston has shown in Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi (Princeton, 1990), the relation of political science to philosophy (and thus of political practice to philosophic inquiry) appears in a very different light in Alfarabi's Selected Aphorisms; see Aphorisms of the Statesman, ed. and tr. D. M. Dunlop (Cambridge, 1962), aphorism 4; Politics and Excellence, 123-24, 188.
    • (1985) Richard Walzer As Alfarabi's Perfect State
  • 23
    • 0007254977 scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • This statement of the relation between political science and philosophy is based on Alfarabi's accounts of political science in the Political Regime, the Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, and the Opinions of the Citizens of the Virtuous City, ed. and tr. Richard Walzer as Alfarabi's Perfect State (Oxford, 1985). As Miriam Galston has shown in Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi (Princeton, 1990), the relation of political science to philosophy (and thus of political practice to philosophic inquiry) appears in a very different light in Alfarabi's Selected Aphorisms; see Aphorisms of the Statesman, ed. and tr. D. M. Dunlop (Cambridge, 1962), aphorism 4; Politics and Excellence, 123-24, 188.
    • (1990) Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi
    • Galston, M.1
  • 24
    • 0042268541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This statement of the relation between political science and philosophy is based on Alfarabi's accounts of political science in the Political Regime, the Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, and the Opinions of the Citizens of the Virtuous City, ed. and tr. Richard Walzer as Alfarabi's Perfect State (Oxford, 1985). As Miriam Galston has shown in Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi (Princeton, 1990), the relation of political science to philosophy (and thus of political practice to philosophic inquiry) appears in a very different light in Alfarabi's Selected Aphorisms; see Aphorisms of the Statesman, ed. and tr. D. M. Dunlop (Cambridge, 1962), aphorism 4; Politics and Excellence, 123-24, 188.
    • Selected Aphorisms
    • Alfarabi1
  • 25
    • 25444439451 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, aphorism 4
    • This statement of the relation between political science and philosophy is based on Alfarabi's accounts of political science in the Political Regime, the Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, and the Opinions of the Citizens of the Virtuous City, ed. and tr. Richard Walzer as Alfarabi's Perfect State (Oxford, 1985). As Miriam Galston has shown in Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi (Princeton, 1990), the relation of political science to philosophy (and thus of political practice to philosophic inquiry) appears in a very different light in Alfarabi's Selected Aphorisms; see Aphorisms of the Statesman, ed. and tr. D. M. Dunlop (Cambridge, 1962), aphorism 4; Politics and Excellence, 123-24, 188.
    • (1962) Aphorisms of the Statesman
    • Dunlop, D.M.1
  • 26
    • 84978971236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This statement of the relation between political science and philosophy is based on Alfarabi's accounts of political science in the Political Regime, the Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, and the Opinions of the Citizens of the Virtuous City, ed. and tr. Richard Walzer as Alfarabi's Perfect State (Oxford, 1985). As Miriam Galston has shown in Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi (Princeton, 1990), the relation of political science to philosophy (and thus of political practice to philosophic inquiry) appears in a very different light in Alfarabi's Selected Aphorisms; see Aphorisms of the Statesman, ed. and tr. D. M. Dunlop (Cambridge, 1962), aphorism 4; Politics and Excellence, 123-24, 188.
    • Politics and Excellence , pp. 123-124
  • 27
  • 28
    • 0043271018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec. 34
    • Attainment, sec. 34; cf. Book of Religion, tr. Charles Butterworth (Department of Government and Politics, University of Maryland, photocopy), sec. 5; Book of Letters, tr. Muhsin Mahdi (Department of Near Eastern Languages and Civilizations, Harvard University, photocopy), sees. 144, 147.
    • Attainment
  • 29
    • 0043271020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Department of Government and Politics, University of Maryland, photocopy), sec. 5
    • Attainment, sec. 34; cf. Book of Religion, tr. Charles Butterworth (Department of Government and Politics, University of Maryland, photocopy), sec. 5; Book of Letters, tr. Muhsin Mahdi (Department of Near Eastern Languages and Civilizations, Harvard University, photocopy), sees. 144, 147.
    • Book of Religion
    • Butterworth, C.1
  • 30
    • 0043271069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Department of Near Eastern Languages and Civilizations, Harvard University, photocopy), sees. 144, 147
    • Attainment, sec. 34; cf. Book of Religion, tr. Charles Butterworth (Department of Government and Politics, University of Maryland, photocopy), sec. 5; Book of Letters, tr. Muhsin Mahdi (Department of Near Eastern Languages and Civilizations, Harvard University, photocopy), sees. 144, 147.
    • Book of Letters
    • Mahdi, M.1
  • 31
  • 32
  • 33
    • 0042268494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political regime N85
    • Political Regime N85; Medieval Political Philosophy, 40; cf. Virtuous City chap. 14 sec. 4.
    • Medieval Political Philosophy , pp. 40
  • 34
    • 84972336139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 14 sec. 4
    • Political Regime N85; Medieval Political Philosophy, 40; cf. Virtuous City chap. 14 sec. 4.
    • Virtuous City
  • 35
    • 0042268495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec. 59
    • Attainment, sec. 59, cf. Book of Religion sec. 2, Book of Letters sees. 108-10.
    • Attainment
  • 36
    • 0043271020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec. 2
    • Attainment, sec. 59, cf. Book of Religion sec. 2, Book of Letters sees. 108-10.
    • Book of Religion
  • 37
    • 0043271069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sees. 108-10
    • Attainment, sec. 59, cf. Book of Religion sec. 2, Book of Letters sees. 108-10.
    • Book of Letters
  • 38
  • 40
    • 84972336139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 17, sec. 2
    • Virtuous City ch. 17, sec. 2.
    • Virtuous City
  • 41
    • 0043271025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • tr. Charles Butterworth (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy), sec. 61
    • See Alfarabi, The Harmonization of the Opinions of the Two Sages: Plato and Aristotle, tr. Charles Butterworth (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy), sec. 61, where one who believes that "the first creator" is corporeal will only become perplexed if "compelled to conceive" that the Creator is incorporeal or acts without motion. In consequence, Alfarabi hints, the multitude is taught that a corporeal Creator created a corporeal universe out of preexisting matter (sec. 62). The truer doctrine of God's incorporeality is reserved for those who will recognize its greater accuracy. Maimonides famously contradicts this particular segregation of images, in principle in the Guide, and in practice in the Code (Guide of the Perplexed, I, 35; "Laws of the Foundations of the Torah," ch. i-ii). Cf. also Averroes, Decisive Treatise in Averroes on the Harmony of Religion and Philosophy, ed. and tr. George Hourani (London, 1967), 13ff; Shem Tob ad Guide I:35; Shlomo Pines, "Translator's Introduction," in Moses Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed (Chicago, 1963), cxix.
    • The Harmonization of the Opinions of the Two Sages: Plato and Aristotle
    • Alfarabi1
  • 42
    • 0041768007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Laws of the foundations of the Torah
    • ch. i-ii
    • See Alfarabi, The Harmonization of the Opinions of the Two Sages: Plato and Aristotle, tr. Charles Butterworth (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy), sec. 61, where one who believes that "the first creator" is corporeal will only become perplexed if "compelled to conceive" that the Creator is incorporeal or acts without motion. In consequence, Alfarabi hints, the multitude is taught that a corporeal Creator created a corporeal universe out of preexisting matter (sec. 62). The truer doctrine of God's incorporeality is reserved for those who will recognize its greater accuracy. Maimonides famously contradicts this particular segregation of images, in principle in the Guide, and in practice in the Code (Guide of the Perplexed, I, 35; "Laws of the Foundations of the Torah," ch. i-ii). Cf. also Averroes, Decisive Treatise in Averroes on the Harmony of Religion and Philosophy, ed. and tr. George Hourani (London, 1967), 13ff; Shem Tob ad Guide I:35; Shlomo Pines, "Translator's Introduction," in Moses Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed (Chicago, 1963), cxix.
    • Guide of the Perplexed , vol.1 , pp. 35
  • 43
    • 0042268497 scopus 로고
    • ed. and tr. George Hourani London, 13ff
    • See Alfarabi, The Harmonization of the Opinions of the Two Sages: Plato and Aristotle, tr. Charles Butterworth (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy), sec. 61, where one who believes that "the first creator" is corporeal will only become perplexed if "compelled to conceive" that the Creator is incorporeal or acts without motion. In consequence, Alfarabi hints, the multitude is taught that a corporeal Creator created a corporeal universe out of preexisting matter (sec. 62). The truer doctrine of God's incorporeality is reserved for those who will recognize its greater accuracy. Maimonides famously contradicts this particular segregation of images, in principle in the Guide, and in practice in the Code (Guide of the Perplexed, I, 35; "Laws of the Foundations of the Torah," ch. i-ii). Cf. also Averroes, Decisive Treatise in Averroes on the Harmony of Religion and Philosophy, ed. and tr. George Hourani (London, 1967), 13ff; Shem Tob ad Guide I:35; Shlomo Pines, "Translator's Introduction," in Moses Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed (Chicago, 1963), cxix.
    • (1967) Decisive Treatise in Averroes on the Harmony of Religion and Philosophy
    • Averroes1
  • 44
    • 0043271065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alfarabi, The Harmonization of the Opinions of the Two Sages: Plato and Aristotle, tr. Charles Butterworth (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy), sec. 61, where one who believes that "the first creator" is corporeal will only become perplexed if "compelled to conceive" that the Creator is incorporeal or acts without motion. In consequence, Alfarabi hints, the multitude is taught that a corporeal Creator created a corporeal universe out of preexisting matter (sec. 62). The truer doctrine of God's incorporeality is reserved for those who will recognize its greater accuracy. Maimonides famously contradicts this particular segregation of images, in principle in the Guide, and in practice in the Code (Guide of the Perplexed, I, 35; "Laws of the Foundations of the Torah," ch. i-ii). Cf. also Averroes, Decisive Treatise in Averroes on the Harmony of Religion and Philosophy, ed. and tr. George Hourani (London, 1967), 13ff; Shem Tob ad Guide I:35; Shlomo Pines, "Translator's Introduction," in Moses Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed (Chicago, 1963), cxix.
    • Guide , vol.1 , pp. 35
    • Tob Ad, S.1
  • 45
    • 70349490636 scopus 로고
    • Translator's introduction
    • Moses Maimonides, Chicago
    • See Alfarabi, The Harmonization of the Opinions of the Two Sages: Plato and Aristotle, tr. Charles Butterworth (University of Maryland, Department of Government and Politics, photocopy), sec. 61, where one who believes that "the first creator" is corporeal will only become perplexed if "compelled to conceive" that the Creator is incorporeal or acts without motion. In consequence, Alfarabi hints, the multitude is taught that a corporeal Creator created a corporeal universe out of preexisting matter (sec. 62). The truer doctrine of God's incorporeality is reserved for those who will recognize its greater accuracy. Maimonides famously contradicts this particular segregation of images, in principle in the Guide, and in practice in the Code (Guide of the Perplexed, I, 35; "Laws of the Foundations of the Torah," ch. i-ii). Cf. also Averroes, Decisive Treatise in Averroes on the Harmony of Religion and Philosophy, ed. and tr. George Hourani (London, 1967), 13ff; Shem Tob ad Guide I:35; Shlomo Pines, "Translator's Introduction," in Moses Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed (Chicago, 1963), cxix.
    • (1963) The Guide of the Perplexed
    • Pines, S.1
  • 46
  • 47
    • 84974288927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political regime N85-86
    • Political Regime N85-86; Medieval Political Philosophy, 41; and see Joshua Parens, "Multiculturalism and the Problem of Particularism," American Political Science Review, 88 (1994), 163-81.
    • Medieval Political Philosophy , pp. 41
  • 48
    • 84974288927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Multiculturalism and the problem of particularism
    • Political Regime N85-86; Medieval Political Philosophy, 41; and see Joshua Parens, "Multiculturalism and the Problem of Particularism," American Political Science Review, 88 (1994), 163-81.
    • (1994) American Political Science Review , vol.88 , pp. 163-181
    • Parens, J.1
  • 54
    • 84972336139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 17, sec. 4
    • Virtuous City, ch. 17, sec. 4.
    • Virtuous City
  • 55
    • 0043271019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In The Opinion of the Citizens of the Virtuous City Alfarabi does not use the term weeds (al-nawdbit). Instead, as we have already cited, he speaks of those who reject the images of the city as false. Like the weeds of the Political Regime, these "rejecters" are a group among the citizens of the virtuous or excellent city.
    • The Opinion of the Citizens of the Virtuous City
    • Alfarabi1
  • 57
    • 0042769814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Political Regime N80, N101; Medieval Political Philosophy, 37, 51.
    • Political Regime
  • 59
    • 0042769814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Regime N106; Medieval Political Philosophy, 55.
    • Political Regime
  • 61
    • 0042769774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sees. 59, 61
    • Attainment, sees. 59, 61; cf. Political Regime N77.
    • Attainment
  • 62
    • 0042769814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • N77
    • Attainment, sees. 59, 61; cf. Political Regime N77.
    • Political Regime
  • 63
    • 0043271069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec. 149
    • Compare Book of Letters sec. 149, where Alfarabi states that if neither the adherents of philosophy nor those of a religion recognize that religion depends on philosophy, "the adherents of philosophy will also oppose this religion so long as they do not know that this religion consists of paradigms of what is in philosophy." Alfarabi goes on to state that the adherents of philosophy must defend themselves before the adherents of religion "by seeking to make them discern that the contents of their religion are paradigms of the contents of philosophy." The philosopher must therefore interpret the law philosophically both to the weed and to the "cultivated" multitude.
    • Book of Letters
  • 68
    • 0043271063 scopus 로고
    • Avempace botánico
    • Weeds or spontaneous growths are mentioned in Ibn Bajjah's botanical treatise; see "Avempace Botánico," ed. and Spanish tr. Miguel Aśn Palacios, Al Andalus, 5 (1940), 255-99. The brief discussion (p. 288) does not appear relevant to his political philosophy.
    • (1940) Al Andalus , vol.5 , pp. 255-299
    • Aśn Palacios, M.1
  • 73
    • 0043271063 scopus 로고
    • Avempace botánico
    • Ibid.
    • (1940) Al Andalus , vol.5 , pp. 255-299
  • 77
    • 84972336139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 19, secs. 2-4, 7
    • Virtuous City, ch. 19, secs. 2-4, 7.
    • Virtuous City
  • 78
    • 0041768002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hayy ibn yaqzan
    • tr. George N. Atiyeh
    • Ibn Tufayl, Hayy ibn Yaqzan, tr. George N. Atiyeh, in Medieval Political Philosophy, 10. Translations of Hayy are taken from Atiyeh's partial translation in Medieval Political Philosophy or Lenn Goodman's translation (New York, 1972) for portions untranslated by Atiyeh. References to Hayy are given using the standard page numbers of Léon Gauthier's Arabic text (Beirut, 1936).
    • Medieval Political Philosophy , pp. 10
    • Tufayl, I.1
  • 79
    • 0004020506 scopus 로고
    • translation New York, for portions untranslated by Atiyeh
    • Ibn Tufayl, Hayy ibn Yaqzan, tr. George N. Atiyeh, in Medieval Political Philosophy, 10. Translations of Hayy are taken from Atiyeh's partial translation in Medieval Political Philosophy or Lenn Goodman's translation (New York, 1972) for portions untranslated by Atiyeh. References to Hayy are given using the standard page numbers of Léon Gauthier's Arabic text (Beirut, 1936).
    • (1972) Medieval Political Philosophy
    • Goodman, L.1
  • 80
    • 0043271013 scopus 로고
    • Arabic text Beirut
    • Ibn Tufayl, Hayy ibn Yaqzan, tr. George N. Atiyeh, in Medieval Political Philosophy, 10. Translations of Hayy are taken from Atiyeh's partial translation in Medieval Political Philosophy or Lenn Goodman's translation (New York, 1972) for portions untranslated by Atiyeh. References to Hayy are given using the standard page numbers of Léon Gauthier's Arabic text (Beirut, 1936).
    • (1936) Hayy
    • Gauthier, L.1
  • 81
    • 0043271066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 12.
    • Hayy , pp. 12
  • 82
    • 0043271051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or Absāl, in some manuscripts, and in the recital of Avicenna from which Ibn Tufayl claims to take his characters' names (Hayy 20); cf. Henry Corbin, Avicenna and the Visionary Recital, tr. Willard R. Trask (New York, 1960).
    • Hayy , pp. 20
  • 83
    • 0041511055 scopus 로고
    • tr. Willard R. Trask New York
    • Or Absāl, in some manuscripts, and in the recital of Avicenna from which Ibn Tufayl claims to take his characters' names (Hayy 20); cf. Henry Corbin, Avicenna and the Visionary Recital, tr. Willard R. Trask (New York, 1960).
    • (1960) Avicenna and the Visionary Recital
    • Corbin, H.1
  • 84
    • 0042268526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hayy, 3-4.
    • Hayy , pp. 3-4
  • 86
    • 0042268537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hayy, 26-30.
    • Hayy , pp. 26-30
  • 88
    • 0043271053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though Ibn Tufayl does in the end contradict the story of Hayy's spontaneous generation (Hayy, 34); see Fradkin, "Political Thought of Ibn Tufayl."
    • Hayy , pp. 34
  • 89
    • 0041767968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though Ibn Tufayl does in the end contradict the story of Hayy's spontaneous generation (Hayy, 34); see Fradkin, "Political Thought of Ibn Tufayl."
    • Political Thought of Ibn Tufayl
    • Fradkin1
  • 90
    • 0042769798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hayy, 50.
    • Hayy , pp. 50
  • 91
    • 0042769800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hayy, 106-7.
    • Hayy , pp. 106-107
  • 92
    • 0042268529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Since Hayy cannot fit himself in to the order of the beings, he knows of nothing that is fit for him to eat (110-12).
  • 93
    • 0043271054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 109
    • Ibid., 109.
  • 94
    • 0041768000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 127-31
    • Ibid., 127-31.
  • 95
    • 0043271055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 132
    • Ibid., 132.
  • 96
    • 0042268538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 136-37
    • Ibid., 136-37.
  • 97
    • 0042769804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 137-38
    • Ibid., 137-38.
  • 98
    • 0042769805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 140, 142
    • Ibid., 140, 142.
  • 99
    • 0041768004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Ibid., 35-36
    • Cf. Ibid., 35-36.
  • 100
    • 0043271059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 143-44
    • Ibid., 143-44. The translation of these passages has been slightly modified from that of Atiyeh with the help of Michael Marmura; on the importance of distinguishing this "conjunction" or ittisal from the "union" with the divine see Hayy 4, 123-24.
    • Hayy , vol.4 , pp. 123-124
  • 101
    • 0043271061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 10.
    • Hayy , pp. 10
  • 102
    • 0042268533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 144.
    • Hayy , pp. 144
  • 103
    • 0041768003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 147.
    • Hayy , pp. 147
  • 104
    • 0042268532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 146, 147.
    • Hayy , pp. 146
  • 105
    • 0043271056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 146.
    • Hayy , pp. 146
  • 106
    • 0043271057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 147.
    • Hayy , pp. 147
  • 107
    • 0042268534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 148-49.
    • Hayy , pp. 148-149
  • 108
    • 0042268535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 149-50.
    • Hayy , pp. 149-150
  • 109
    • 0042268539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 150.
    • Hayy , pp. 150
  • 110
    • 0042268536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 150-54.
    • Hayy , pp. 150-154
  • 111
    • 0043271058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 153-54.
    • Hayy , pp. 153-154
  • 112
    • 0043271060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 4.
    • Hayy , pp. 4
  • 113
    • 0043271062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 143.
    • Hayy , pp. 143
  • 116
    • 0042769773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Farabi as founder
    • This paper was delivered as part of a panel entitled "Farabi as Founder" at the 1997 Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. I would like to thank Charles Butterworth, Christopher Colmo, Joseph Macfarland, and members of the audience; also Muhsin Mahdi, Joshua Parens, Donald Forbes, Ralph Lerner, Michael Marmura, Donald Smith, Natalie Oeltjen, and Lenn E. Goodman. Research was supported by a Claude R. Lambe Fellowship from the Institute for Humane Studies, a National Science Foundation Graduate Fellowship, and a Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada Postdoctoral Fellowship.
    • 1997 Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.