메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 109, Issue 4, 2000, Pages 483-523

Nonconceptual content and the space of reasons

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041982127     PISSN: 00318108     EISSN: 15581470     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1215/00318108-109-4-483     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (296)

References (47)
  • 1
    • 0004045957 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, See, in particular, sections 5.1, 5.2, and 7.4. Further references are in the text, marked by ' VR and a page number
    • Gareth Evans, The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982). See, in particular, sections 5.1, 5.2, and 7.4. Further references are in the text, marked by ' VR and a page number.
    • (1982) The Varieties of Reference
    • Evans, G.1
  • 2
    • 0004109730 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press, chap. 3 and part 2 of the afterword. Further references are in the text, marked by 'MW' and a page number
    • John McDowell, Mind and World (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994), chap. 3 and part 2 of the afterword. Further references are in the text, marked by 'MW' and a page number.
    • (1994) Mind and World
    • McDowell, J.1
  • 3
    • 85196886317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unless, of course, one held that all content is nonconceptual-though, then, the claim so stated would not register any difference between belief and perception
    • Unless, of course, one held that all content is nonconceptual-though, then, the claim so stated would not register any difference between belief and perception.
  • 4
    • 85196904910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jim Pryor suggested to me that it might be better to speak of "conceptually-constituted content" and "nonconceptually- constituted content." This seems reasonable. But, as the terminology used in the paper is well established, I am afraid we are stuck with it
    • Jim Pryor suggested to me that it might be better to speak of "conceptually-constituted content" and "nonconceptually- constituted content." This seems reasonable. But, as the terminology used in the paper is well established, I am afraid we are stuck with it.
  • 5
    • 85196877432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I suspect that the state view is indefensible-even incoherent, if coupled with the claim that the contents of beliefs are conceptual-but I shall not argue this point here
    • I suspect that the state view is indefensible-even incoherent, if coupled with the claim that the contents of beliefs are conceptual-but I shall not argue this point here.
  • 6
    • 33748873616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Concepts, ed. Enrique Villanueva Atascadero, Calif: Ridgeview, in which he argues, pace McDowell, that the contents of beliefs and perceptions are both nonconceptual. Stalnaker understands very well that, once the nature of conceptual content has been properly understood, the claim that beliefs have conceptual content can be seen to be controversial; the claim that perceptions do, even more so
    • See Robert Stalnaker, "What Might Nonconceptual Content Be?" in Concepts, ed. Enrique Villanueva (Atascadero, Calif: Ridgeview, 1998), 339-52, in which he argues, pace McDowell, that the contents of beliefs and perceptions are both nonconceptual. Stalnaker understands very well that, once the nature of conceptual content has been properly understood, the claim that beliefs have conceptual content can be seen to be controversial; the claim that perceptions do, even more so.
    • (1998) What Might Nonconceptual Content Be , pp. 339-352
    • Stalnaker, R.1
  • 7
    • 85196886507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, it is an open question whether McDowell understands this thesis as Evans does: But McDowell certainly does not use the term 'conceptual content' in such a way that the claim that beliefs have conceptual content is trivial. Failure to grasp this point will make certain aspects of Mind and World hard to understand
    • Of course, it is an open question whether McDowell understands this thesis as Evans does: But McDowell certainly does not use the term 'conceptual content' in such a way that the claim that beliefs have conceptual content is trivial. Failure to grasp this point will make certain aspects of Mind and World hard to understand.
  • 8
    • 85196878235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I think Evans actually meant more by the claim that beliefs have conceptual content. In particular, someone who took the contents of beliefs to be sets of possible worlds could agree with what has been said so far- could profess to accept the Generality Constraint-so long as she conceived of grasp of a concept as an abstraction from an ability to entertain certain sorts of Thoughts (and of concepts themselves as abstractions from a class of Thoughts). For Evans, though, possession of the cognitive capacities that constitutes grasp of concepts is supposed in some sense to be prior to, or independent of, one's capacity to entertain such Thoughts as these: Possession of such capacities-grasp of certain concepts-is supposed to figure in an explanation of one's ability to entertain the Thoughts one can. One might say, then, that, for Evans, Thoughts are conceptual in so far as they are intrinsically conceptually articulated.
  • 9
    • 0003363321 scopus 로고
    • Semantic Theory and Tacit Knowledge
    • This sort of issue was discussed, some time ago, in connection with the question of what justifies the attribution of knowledge of a structured, axiomatic theory of meaning to a competent speaker. See in his Collected Papers Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press
    • This sort of issue was discussed, some time ago, in connection with the question of what justifies the attribution of knowledge of a structured, axiomatic theory of meaning to a competent speaker. See Gareth Evans, "Semantic Theory and Tacit Knowledge," in his Collected Papers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press, 1985), 322-42;
    • (1985) Collected Papers , pp. 322-342
    • Evans, G.1
  • 10
    • 0001873815 scopus 로고
    • Tacit knowledge and semantic theory: Can a five per cent difference matter
    • Martin Davies, "Tacit Knowledge and Semantic Theory: Can a Five per cent Difference Matter?" Mind96 (1987): 441-62;
    • (1987) Mind96 , pp. 441-462
    • Davies, M.1
  • 11
    • 0002292326 scopus 로고
    • Theories of meaning and speakers' knowledge
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • Crispin Wright, "Theories of Meaning and Speakers' Knowledge," in his Realism, Meaning, and Truth (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986), 204-38.
    • (1986) Realism, Meaning, and Truth , pp. 204-238
    • Wright, C.1
  • 12
    • 33748861247 scopus 로고
    • Perception, concepts, and memory
    • at 758-59
    • For remarks in a similar spirit, see M. G. F. Martin, "Perception, Concepts, and Memory," Philosophical Review 101 (1992): 745-63, at 758-59.
    • (1992) Philosophical Review , vol.101 , pp. 745-763
    • Martin, M.G.F.1
  • 13
    • 85196874810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McDowell is concerned to emphasize that my demonstrative concept need not die with my experience: This is the reason for the parentheticals. But, having inserted them here, I shall omit them below, as it will be enough for us to focus on the situation that gives rise to the concept in the first place
    • McDowell is concerned to emphasize that my demonstrative concept need not die with my experience: This is the reason for the parentheticals. But, having inserted them here, I shall omit them below, as it will be enough for us to focus on the situation that gives rise to the concept in the first place.
  • 14
    • 85196880867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If to say that it appears as if that part of my desk is that color is to give a completely faithful report of (part of) the content of my experience, and if perceptual content is conceptual, I could not have such an experience unless I had the demonstrative concept that color
    • If to say that it appears as if that part of my desk is that color is to give a completely faithful report of (part of) the content of my experience, and if perceptual content is conceptual, I could not have such an experience unless I had the demonstrative concept that color.
  • 15
    • 85196900864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One could have such information without having such a concept, if the state view were correct. (This is one sort of reason it might seem appealing.) But I mean to be setting that view aside here
    • One could have such information without having such a concept, if the state view were correct. (This is one sort of reason it might seem appealing.) But I mean to be setting that view aside here.
  • 16
    • 85196892749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Independently, maybe, even of your understanding what I have said, since, on Evans's view, you do not understand what I have said if you are not, yourself, in a position to perceive the relevant part of my desk (or have some other informational link to it), though you do know what kind of thing I have said
    • Independently, maybe, even of your understanding what I have said, since, on Evans's view, you do not understand what I have said if you are not, yourself, in a position to perceive the relevant part of my desk (or have some other informational link to it), though you do know what kind of thing I have said.
  • 17
    • 85196901099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There are cases in which the demonstrative need not refer to the color of the desk. If there is a transparent film of color covering the desk, the demonstrative 'that color' could refer to the color of the film, in which case my utterance of 'That part of the desk is that color' need not be true. But I am interested here in what we might call "pure" cases of misperception, cases in which I simply misperceive the color of the desk, not because of some external interference, such as films of color, funny lighting, etc. I find, for example, that it is frequently the case that, if I shut one eye, colors take on a slightly greenish tint, whereas, if I shut the other, they take on a comparatively reddish tint. That is the kind of thing I have in mind. (Such "pure" misperception can occur in film cases, too, of course: If I misperceive the color of the film, no "external" color need be available to determine the content of my experience.)
  • 18
    • 85196899590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Just as Evans would insist that I cannot have a demonstrative concept of the little green man who appears to be sitting on top of my monitor, if there is no such man there, perhaps he would also insist I can have no demonstrative concept of the color the relevant part of my desk appears to me to be, if I am misperceiving its color. But the intuition is very strong that if my experience presents my desk as being a certain shade of brown, I can form a concept of that particular shade. It will not do simply to deny it.
  • 19
    • 85196887961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Perhaps the beliefs I form on the basis of my experience are, by and large, true. But I see no reason to think my total perceptual state is usually veridical. My total perceptual state almost always represents the world as containing something that is ringing at a particular frequency, which there rarely is, and my visual experience misrepresents depth with an astonishing regularity. And because I wear glasses, the periphery of my vision almost always represents the world in a most peculiar fashion. (It is also worth remembering that illusions, like the Müller-Lyer illusion, highlight quite ordinary features of perceptual experience. That is why they are interesting.)
  • 20
    • 85196903502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the question what to do about the richness of nonveridical perception would remain open: But perhaps that would not trouble McDowell
    • Of course, the question what to do about the richness of nonveridical perception would remain open: But perhaps that would not trouble McDowell.
  • 21
    • 85196892946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that this is different from saying that my belief has the following content: That, if it is true, then snow is white, and, if it is false, then snow is pink. We certainly can, and I certainly do, have beliefs with that sort of content
    • Note that this is different from saying that my belief has the following content: That, if it is true, then snow is white, and, if it is false, then snow is pink. We certainly can, and I certainly do, have beliefs with that sort of content.
  • 22
    • 0004114760 scopus 로고
    • Some theorists of perception have denied this claim, namely, those who think that perceptual knowledge is to be justified by an inference to the best explanation: The existence of an external world causing them is supposed to be the best explanation of our having the sense-data we do see New York: Cambridge University Press, I take it that McDowell's objection to such views would be one to be mentioned in note 21 below, namely, that they leave it obscure how we could so much as have concepts of external objects and properties. But I do not intend to evaluate this claim here
    • Some theorists of perception have denied this claim, namely, those who think that perceptual knowledge is to be justified by an inference to the best explanation: The existence of an external world causing them is supposed to be the best explanation of our having the sense-data we do (see Frank Jackson, Perception: A Representative Theory (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1977)). I take it that McDowell's objection to such views would be one to be mentioned in note 21 below, namely, that they leave it obscure how we could so much as have concepts of external objects and properties. But I do not intend to evaluate this claim here.
    • (1977) Perception: A Representative Theory
    • Jackson, F.1
  • 23
    • 0000105177 scopus 로고
    • A coherence theory of truth and knowledge
    • McDowell presents Davidson's view as an alternative to the sense-datum theory, which is certainly how Davidson himself conceives it. See ed. E. LePore Oxford: Blackwell, But it seems to me that if the objection McDowell brings against Davidson works at all, it works against this view, too: see MW, 13-8
    • McDowell presents Davidson's view as an alternative to the sense-datum theory, which is certainly how Davidson himself conceives it. See Donald Davidson, "A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge," in Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, ed. E. LePore (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986), 307-19. But it seems to me that if the objection McDowell brings against Davidson works at all, it works against this view, too: see MW, 13-8.
    • (1986) Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson , pp. 307-319
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 24
    • 85196894923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • One thing that is distinctive of McDowell's treatment of these issues is his connecting them with questions about how, if the sense-datum theory were correct, we could so much as have beliefs, not just about our sense- data, but about the world itself-let alone how these beliefs might be justified: How, McDowell wants to ask, could we so much as have a concept of a square object if that concept never made contact with square objects? indeed, with anything outside our minds? But I shall not discuss this aspect of his presentation in any detail, since I do not think it bears directly upon the concerns of this paper.
  • 25
    • 85196888952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McDowell himself describes Evans's view as being, for just this reason, "deceptively innocent" (MW, 53) and admits that his charge that it is a version of the Myth of the Given "can seem difficult to sustain" (MW, 162)
    • McDowell himself describes Evans's view as being, for just this reason, "deceptively innocent" (MW, 53) and admits that his charge that it is a version of the Myth of the Given "can seem difficult to sustain" (MW, 162).
  • 26
    • 85196885983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I have heard it objected that an organism will only be able to make use of the information experience provides insofar as it can conceptualize it, where the conclusion is supposed to be that the content of the experience-the content it has for the organism-is limited by the concepts the organism possesses. But the inference from premise to conclusion is questionable (it ignores the distinction between concepts one has independent of the experience and experience-dependent concepts that it might make available) and the premise is independently doubtful (see note 27 and the text to which it is attached).
  • 27
    • 0004167578 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: MIT Press
    • See A Study of Concepts (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1992).
    • (1992) A Study of Concepts
  • 28
    • 85196871203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 31 and the text to which it is attached for some further remarks on this issue
    • See note 31 and the text to which it is attached for some further remarks on this issue.
  • 29
    • 85196906058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although the comparison with testimony can be misleading if not treated with care-it tends to suggest the representational theory considered in the last section-we might say that perception is more like a little voice saying, "There is a desk in front of you." (See VR, 122-23.)
    • Although the comparison with testimony can be misleading if not treated with care-it tends to suggest the representational theory considered in the last section-we might say that perception is more like a little voice saying, "There is a desk in front of you." (See VR, 122-23.)
  • 30
    • 85196871630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This suggests that perceptual experience can influence action otherwise than by giving rise to beliefs. (Evans might have had something like this in mind when he wrote of connections between the informational system and action that are "more primitive" than its connections to belief.)
    • This suggests that perceptual experience can influence action otherwise than by giving rise to beliefs. (Evans might have had something like this in mind when he wrote of connections between the informational system and action that are "more primitive" than its connections to belief.)
  • 31
    • 85196902133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I use this term, rather than 'representational', because the term 'representational content' is in such common use. (The term has also been used by John Searle: See his Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).) Indeed, when people speak of perception as having representational content, this seems to me to run together the two aspects of perceptual experience I am trying to distinguish. One does not easily speak of intentions as having representational content.
  • 32
    • 85196874511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, it would be nice to know more about what it means to say that perceptual states are "assertive." Unfortunately, I do not know how to explain this. Nor, however, do I know how to explain what is involved in a belief's being assertive: What exactly does it mean to say that beliefs purport to represent how the world is? I think an answer to this question could be converted into an answer for the case of perception, too: At least, that is the point of my relying upon this analogy here.
  • 33
    • 85196889597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The occurrence of this word should set off no alarms: When people deny that perceptual knowledge is inferentially justified, what they mean, typically, is that it is not inferred from any prior beliefs about my experiential states. The view I am developing can acknowledge this point: If it is right to say that perceptual beliefs are inferred, they are inferred from prior presentational attitudes about the world.
  • 34
    • 85196885756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although I have no special interest in retaining the word 'inferred', it seems to me to be useful. In making an inference, although there is a sense in which I must recognize that the premise entails the conclusion, if the inference is to yield knowledge, my recognizing this need not, and in general cannot (on pain of Lewis Carroll problems), involve my having the belief that it does so. So room has to be made, even here, for my recognizing the existence of such a semantic relation, without my forming a belief that it obtains.
  • 35
    • 85196893887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I would certainly understand a request to be told more about the nature of this transition-and I wish I had something positive to say about it, that is, something to say about conceptualization, which is what the translation between types of representational content involves. But I do not see any reason for skepticism that there is something to be said here: The problem is not one that should be underestimated, but Peacocke has done much to explain in what a grasp of certain basic, observational concepts might consist and how possession of them is related to the capacity to form beliefs on the basis of perceptual experience. (See A Study of Concepts, especially §1.2, and 79-80; compare VR, 229.) McDowell discusses and criticizes certain of Peacocke's proposals, but his objections mostly concern Peacocke's right to speak of a subject's reasons (see MW, 162-63). It is that right, of course, that I am defending.
  • 36
    • 85196906329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evans's claim that their content will systematically depend upon that of my perceptual states is too weak: I take this just to be a slip
    • Evans's claim that their content will systematically depend upon that of my perceptual states is too weak: I take this just to be a slip.
  • 37
    • 85196905352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • So, on Evans's view, there is something right in the idea that statements of the form 'It appears to X as if p' mean that X has prima facie justification for believing that p. I do not think we should take that as an analysis of judgments of appearance, though, since I think this analysis would miss the fact that such judgments do make reference to the underlying perceptual states themselves. See note 38, and the text to which it is attached, for more on this issue.
  • 38
    • 85196904624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is no reason Evans needs to insist that judgments about how things appear are incorrigible, especially certain, or what have you: So his view need not inherit any of the problems often thought to attach to views that allow real judgments to have such properties
    • There is no reason Evans needs to insist that judgments about how things appear are incorrigible, especially certain, or what have you: So his view need not inherit any of the problems often thought to attach to views that allow real judgments to have such properties.
  • 39
    • 85196899046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, one might also exercise other conceptual capacities in evaluating these reasons-one might as well bring one's full cognitive capabilities to bear-and one typically will. But this point is of no help to McDowell either
    • Of course, one might also exercise other conceptual capacities in evaluating these reasons-one might as well bring one's full cognitive capabilities to bear-and one typically will. But this point is of no help to McDowell either.
  • 40
    • 77950044851 scopus 로고
    • Spin Control: Comment on John McDowell's Mind and World
    • A diagnosis of McDowell's reflections not unlike mine is given by at 267-68. In his "Reply to Gibson, Byrne, and Brandom," 283-300, at 299ff., McDowell responds in a way that suggests he takes Byrne's diagnosis to rest upon the assumption I am here disowning
    • A diagnosis of McDowell's reflections not unlike mine is given by Alex Byrne: See his "Spin Control: Comment on John McDowell's Mind and World," Philosophical Issues 7 (1995): 261-73, at 267-68. In his "Reply to Gibson, Byrne, and Brandom," 283-300, at 299ff., McDowell responds in a way that suggests he takes Byrne's diagnosis to rest upon the assumption I am here disowning.
    • (1995) Philosophical Issues , vol.7 , pp. 261-273
    • Byrne, A.1
  • 41
    • 64949157019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It seems to me that one can truly say that it appears to me as if p, even if I lack the concepts required if I am to form that judgment, so long as I would so judge, if I did have those concepts But it does not seem to me that it matters for our purposes what view one takes here
    • It seems to me that one can truly say that it appears to me as if p, even if I lack the concepts required if I am to form that judgment, so long as I would so judge, if I did have those concepts (cf. Wright, "Human Nature?" 244-45.) But it does not seem to me that it matters for our purposes what view one takes here.
    • Human Nature , pp. 244-245
    • Wright1
  • 42
    • 85196883144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I hesitate to say that it is for me to judge that I am in a state that gives me reason to hold the belief that p, because it is not clear to me that Evans's account of judgments of appearance should be taken as an analysis of them. It is not, in particular, clear to me that, in order to be able to make judgments of appearance, a creature has to have such concepts as that of a reason, has to be able to think about how she would judge under certain circumstances, and so on and so forth. Compare note 33.
  • 43
    • 85196909779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This difficulty may be caused by a linguistic tangle: We speak of beliefs as being reasons for holding other beliefs; but, if I infer q from p, my reason is not that I believe that p, but just that p, where that is something I believe. So it is okay to say that my belief is my reason, so long as it is clear that my reason is what I believe, not the fact that I believe (though, of course, what I believe can only be a reason for me so long as I do believe). And similarly, if we say that my perceptual state is my reason, it is not that I am in that state (that is, the fact that it appears to me that p) that is my reason, but how things appear.
  • 44
    • 0002207423 scopus 로고
    • Language and communication
    • The idea that there is such a connection is so deeply embedded in that tradition that-in the form of a thesis that an account of thought can only be given via an account of language-it was once enshrined by as "the fundamental principle of analytic philosophy." New York: Oxford University Press
    • The idea that there is such a connection is so deeply embedded in that tradition that-in the form of a thesis that an account of thought can only be given via an account of language-it was once enshrined by Michael Dummett as "the fundamental principle of analytic philosophy." See his "Language and Communication," in his Seas of Language (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 166-87, at 171.
    • (1993) Seas of Language , pp. 166-187
    • Dummett, M.1
  • 45
    • 61149268111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Has dummett over-salted his frege? Remarks on the conveyability of thought
    • For some interesting, and related, reflections, see ed. R. Heck Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For some interesting, and related, reflections, see Alexander George, "Has Dummett Over-salted His Frege? Remarks on the Conveyability of Thought," in Language, Thought, and Logic: Essays in Honour of Michael Dummett, ed. R. Heck (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 35-69.
    • (1997) Language, Thought, and Logic: Essays in Honour of Michael Dummett , pp. 35-69
    • George, A.1
  • 46
    • 85196883677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare wright
    • One that includes "experiences" among the things that must cohere
    • One that includes "experiences" among the things that must cohere. Compare Wright, "Human Nature?" 241-42.
    • Human Nature , pp. 241-242
  • 47
    • 85196899982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whose tongue lashes out at any moving black thing, and not just at flies
    • Whose tongue lashes out at any moving black thing, and not just at flies.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.