-
1
-
-
0004006101
-
-
Chicago: Swallow Press, More precisely, John Dewey takes community to be characterized essentially by ‘conjoint activities whose consequences are appreciated as good by all persons who take part it, and where the realization of the good is such as to affect an energetic desire to sustain it.’ See
-
1984. The Public and Its Problems 149Chicago: Swallow Press. More precisely, John Dewey takes community to be characterized essentially by ‘conjoint activities whose consequences are appreciated as good by all persons who take part in it, and where the realization of the good is such as to affect an energetic desire to sustain it.’ See
-
(1984)
The Public and Its Problems
, pp. 149
-
-
-
2
-
-
85064029782
-
-
Alisdair MacIntyre has taken the family to be a paradigm of community, along with the city, the tribe, and the nation. MacIntyres concept of community is, however, clearly different from community the normative sense, since not all families, tribes, etc., show respect for one anothers needs and interests. For MacIntyre community is found a group when it is united by a common history, culture, and tradition— but these uniting bonds do not guarantee mutual concern. See Alisdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study Moral Theory (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
-
1981. 205 Alisdair MacIntyre has taken the family to be a paradigm of community, along with the city, the tribe, and the nation. MacIntyre's concept of community is, however, clearly different from community in the normative sense, since not all families, tribes, etc., show respect for one another's needs and interests. For MacIntyre community is found in a group when it is united by a common history, culture, and tradition— but these uniting bonds do not guarantee mutual concern. See Alisdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
-
(1981)
, pp. 205
-
-
-
3
-
-
84954731926
-
Liberalism and the Value of Community
-
Mason does a good job of distinguishing community its normative sense from community as it has been understood by such contemporary thinkers as Alisdair MacIntyre, Richard Rorty, and Michael Sandel, who, he thinks, have all neglected to some extent the normative sense of community. Julius Moravscik (‘Communal Ties,’ Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association621988) and Jane Roland Martin (Reclaiming Conversation (New Haven: Yale University Press 1985) also articulate conceptions of community what I take to be its normative sense, which interactive strategies and attitudes are given a central place
-
Mason, Andrew. 1993. ‘Liberalism and the Value of Community,’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23: 211–25. (Mason does a good job of distinguishing community in its normative sense from community as it has been understood by such contemporary thinkers as Alisdair MacIntyre, Richard Rorty, and Michael Sandel, who, he thinks, have all neglected to some extent the normative sense of community. Julius Moravscik (‘Communal Ties,’ Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association621988) and Jane Roland Martin (Reclaiming Conversation (New Haven: Yale University Press 1985) also articulate conceptions of community in what I take to be its normative sense, in which interactive strategies and attitudes are given a central place.
-
(1993)
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.23
, pp. 211-225
-
-
Mason, A.1
-
4
-
-
84992628005
-
The Ethics of Community: The Metaphysical and Ethical Presuppositions of AVP
-
Reitan, Eric. 1992. ‘The Ethics of Community: The Metaphysical and Ethical Presuppositions of AVP,’. The Acorn, 7: 21
-
(1992)
The Acorn
, vol.7
, pp. 21
-
-
Reitan, E.1
-
6
-
-
0003456188
-
-
Boston: Houghton Mifflin, These include strategies for separating people from problems, uncovering the interests that underlie expressed positions, and devising creative options for resolving problems. See Roger Fisher and William Ury
-
1981. Getting to Yes: Negotiating Agreement Without Giving In Boston: Houghton Mifflin. These include strategies for separating people from problems, uncovering the interests that underlie expressed positions, and devising creative options for resolving problems. See Roger Fisher and William Ury
-
(1981)
Getting to Yes: Negotiating Agreement Without Giving In
-
-
-
7
-
-
85064025235
-
The Needs of the Soul,’ in
-
New York: G.P. Putnams Sons,. In
-
Weil, Simone. 1952. “ ‘The Needs of the Soul,’ in ”. In The Need for Roots 21New York: G.P. Putnam's Sons.
-
(1952)
The Need for Roots
, pp. 21
-
-
Weil, S.1
-
8
-
-
78649610848
-
Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment,’ reprinted in
-
Boston: D. Reidel, It is interesting to note that Murphys scheme punishment, by exacting the debt owed by the criminal to society, enables the criminal to ‘re-enter the community of good citizens on an equal status’ (84). Thus Murphys understanding of the stigma associated with crime leads him towards a view of punishment that bears some similarities to my reintegrative account. There are, however, a few critical differences between Murphys theory and the one I develop here. First, the community of good citizens is defined by Murphy according to a contractual model which self-interest drives autonomous individuals to conform to law, whereas my scheme this community is defined by mutual care. Second, for Murphy reintegration is an effect of punishment but not the justification for it— the demands of fairness and rational consistency, rather than the goal of building community, provide the justification. Murphys account of retribution can, however, be incorporated within the reintegrative theory to explain the stigma of the crime. Thus the two theories are not strictly opposed. A deeper discussion of the relationship between the two theories is warranted, and will be the subject of a future paper.,. In
-
Murphy, Jeffrie. 1979. “ ‘Kant's Theory of Criminal Punishment,’ reprinted in ”. In Retribution, Justice, and Therapy 83Boston: D. Reidel. It is interesting to note that in Murphy's scheme punishment, by exacting the debt owed by the criminal to society, enables the criminal to ‘re-enter the community of good citizens on an equal status’ (84). Thus Murphy's understanding of the stigma associated with crime leads him towards a view of punishment that bears some similarities to my reintegrative account. There are, however, a few critical differences between Murphy's theory and the one I develop here. First, the community of good citizens is defined by Murphy according to a contractual model in which self-interest drives autonomous individuals to conform to law, whereas in my scheme this community is defined by mutual care. Second, for Murphy reintegration is an effect of punishment but not the justification for it— the demands of fairness and rational consistency, rather than the goal of building community, provide the justification. Murphy's account of retribution can, however, be incorporated within the reintegrative theory to explain the stigma of the crime. Thus the two theories are not strictly opposed. A deeper discussion of the relationship between the two theories is warranted, and will be the subject of a future paper.
-
(1979)
Retribution, Justice, and Therapy
, pp. 83
-
-
Murphy, J.1
-
9
-
-
0004246155
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Jean Hampton and Jeffrie
-
Murphy, G., 1988. Forgiveness and Mercy 122–43. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Jean Hampton and Jeffrie
-
(1988)
Forgiveness and Mercy
, pp. 122-143
-
-
Murphy, G.1
-
10
-
-
0003405378
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, For a good discussion of Weils views on justice, see Peter Winch, esp. ch. 14
-
1989. Simone Weil: ‘The Just Balance’ Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. For a good discussion of Weil's views on justice, see Peter Winch, esp. ch. 14.
-
(1989)
Simone Weil: ‘The Just Balance’
-
-
-
11
-
-
0042218931
-
A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment
-
263; Jean Hampton, ‘The Moral Education Theory of Punishment,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs13 208–38. For a critical discussion of this kind of theory, see Russ Shafer-Landau, ‘Can Punishment Morally Educate?’ Law and Philosophy10 (1991, 189–219
-
Morris, Herbert. 1984. ‘A Paternalistic Theory of Punishment,’. American Philosophical Quarterly, 18: 1981–71. 263; Jean Hampton, ‘The Moral Education Theory of Punishment,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs13 208–38. For a critical discussion of this kind of theory, see Russ Shafer-Landau, ‘Can Punishment Morally Educate?’ Law and Philosophy10 (1991, 189–219
-
(1984)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.18
, pp. 1981-1971
-
-
Morris, H.1
-
12
-
-
85064025185
-
-
London: Macmillan Press 1979), esp. see also R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 57–8, ch. 9
-
Dilman, Ilham. 1986. Morality and the Inner Life 203–4. (London: Macmillan Press 1979), esp. see also R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 57–8, ch. 9.
-
(1986)
Morality and the Inner Life
, pp. 203-204
-
-
Dilman, I.1
-
13
-
-
85064027283
-
-
See 265–6. See also Hampshire, ‘Moral Education,’ 227, for a slightly different account of how the hard treatment of punishment educates the criminal. According to Hampshire, the hard treatment is intended to ‘represent’ the pain suffered by the criminals victims, thus enabling the criminal to identify with the victim and recognize the wrongness of what was done. It is plausible to suppose that punishment educates both the way I suggest and the way Hampshire emphasizes
-
Morris. See 265–6. See also Hampshire, ‘Moral Education,’ 227, for a slightly different account of how the hard treatment of punishment educates the criminal. According to Hampshire, the hard treatment is intended to ‘represent’ the pain suffered by the criminal's victims, thus enabling the criminal to identify with the victim and recognize the wrongness of what was done. It is plausible to suppose that punishment educates in both the way I suggest and in the way Hampshire emphasizes.
-
-
-
Morris1
-
14
-
-
85064026829
-
Pacifism and the Use of Force,’ reprinted in
-
Robertson D.B., (ed), Cleveland: World Publishing, see also Morris, 270.,. Edited by
-
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1967. “ ‘Pacifism and the Use of Force,’ reprinted in ”. In Love and Justice: Selections form the Shorter Writings of Reinhold Niebuhr Edited by: Robertson, D. B., 250–1. Cleveland: World Publishing. see also Morris, 270.
-
(1967)
Love and Justice: Selections form the Shorter Writings of Reinhold Niebuhr
, pp. 250-251
-
-
Niebuhr, R.1
-
15
-
-
85085821175
-
God's Justice and Mercy,’ reprinted in
-
New Haven: Yale University Press, !Robert McAfee Brown, E.M. Forster makes a similar point at the end of A Passage to India.,. In
-
Niebuhr. 1986. “ ‘God's Justice and Mercy,’ reprinted in ”. In The Essential Reinhold Niebuhr 29New Haven: Yale University Press. !Robert McAfee Brown, E.M. Forster makes a similar point at the end of A Passage to India.
-
(1986)
The Essential Reinhold Niebuhr
, pp. 29
-
-
Niebuhr1
-
16
-
-
84972258753
-
-
Murphy makes the point powerfully ‘Marxism and Retribution,’ 2 (1973,–43
-
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 217 Murphy makes the point powerfully in ‘Marxism and Retribution,’ 2 (1973,–43
-
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, pp. 217
-
-
-
17
-
-
85064023341
-
-
See 268
-
Morris. See 268.
-
-
-
Morris1
-
18
-
-
0004108379
-
-
this respect, the reintegrative theory of punishment is more harmony with recent work feminist ethics than with the Kantian tradition. The feminist emphasis on care and responsibility to relationships rather than on rights and justice can serve as a powerful foundation for the reintegrative theory. See especially Carol Gilligan, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1982) and Nel Noddings, Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education (Berkeley: University of California Press
-
1984. In a Different Voice In this respect, the reintegrative theory of punishment is more in harmony with recent work in feminist ethics than with the Kantian tradition. The feminist emphasis on care and responsibility to relationships rather than on rights and justice can serve as a powerful foundation for the reintegrative theory. See especially Carol Gilligan, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1982) and Nel Noddings, Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education (Berkeley: University of California Press
-
(1984)
In a Different Voice
-
-
-
19
-
-
85064025170
-
-
‘Marxism,’ 243
-
Murphy. ‘Marxism,’ 243
-
-
-
Murphy1
-
20
-
-
85064021863
-
Punitive Violence and its Alternatives,’ in
-
Philadelphia: Temple University Press, Hugo Adam Bedau !James Brady and Newton Garver, (203–4,. In
-
1991. “ ‘Punitive Violence and its Alternatives,’ in ”. In Justice, Law, and Violence Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Hugo Adam Bedau !James Brady and Newton Garver, (203–4
-
(1991)
Justice, Law, and Violence
-
-
-
21
-
-
85064025605
-
-
See Duff, 66–7
-
See Duff, 66–7.
-
-
-
|