메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 69, Issue 2, 2002, Pages 171-190

Kant, Kuhn, and the rationality of science

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041736490     PISSN: 00318248     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/341048     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (70)

References (23)
  • 1
    • 0004287547 scopus 로고
    • The "general problem of pure reason," along with its two more specific sub-problems, is formulated in § VI of the Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason at B19-24. Sections V and VI, which culminate in the three questions "How is pure mathematics possible?", "How is pure natural science possible?", and "How is metaphysics as a science possible?", are added to the second (1787) edition of the Critique and clearly follow the structure of the 1783 Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, which was intended to clarify the first (1781) edition. This way of framing the general problem of pure reason also clearly reflects the increasing emphasis on the question of pure natural science found in the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (1786). For an extended discussion of Kant's theory of pure natural science and its relation to Newtonian physics Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, especially chapters 3 and 4
    • The "general problem of pure reason," along with its two more specific sub-problems, is formulated in § VI of the Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason at B19-24. Sections V and VI, which culminate in the three questions "How is pure mathematics possible?", "How is pure natural science possible?", and "How is metaphysics as a science possible?", are added to the second (1787) edition of the Critique and clearly follow the structure of the 1783 Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, which was intended to clarify the first (1781) edition. This way of framing the general problem of pure reason also clearly reflects the increasing emphasis on the question of pure natural science found in the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (1786). For an extended discussion of Kant's theory of pure natural science and its relation to Newtonian physics see Friedman, Kant and the Exact Sciences (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), especially chapters 3 and 4.
    • (1992) Kant and the Exact Sciences
    • Friedman1
  • 2
    • 0002795153 scopus 로고
    • Two dogmas of empiricism
    • From the first two paragraphs of § 6, entitled "Empiricism without the Dogmas,"
    • From the first two paragraphs of § 6, entitled "Empiricism without the Dogmas," of "Two Dogmas of Empiricism," Philosophical Review 60 (1951): 20-43; reprinted in From a Logical Point of View (New York: Harper, 1953), pp. 42-43.
    • (1951) Philosophical Review , vol.60 , pp. 20-43
  • 3
    • 0004218079 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper
    • From the first two paragraphs of § 6, entitled "Empiricism without the Dogmas," of "Two Dogmas of Empiricism," Philosophical Review 60 (1951): 20-43; reprinted in From a Logical Point of View (New York: Harper, 1953), pp. 42-43.
    • (1953) From a Logical Point of View , pp. 42-43
  • 4
    • 0042826530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Helmholtz's zeichentheorie and Schlick's allgemeine erkenntnislehre
    • For extended discussion of Helmholtz and Poincaré see my "Helmholtz's Zeichentheorie and Schlick's Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre," Philosophical Topics 25 (1997): 19-50; "Geometry, Construction, and Intuition in Kant and His Successors," in Gila Scher and Richard Tieszen (eds.), Between Logic and Intuition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) ; and Reconsidering Logical Positivism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), chapter 4.
    • (1997) Philosophical Topics , vol.25 , pp. 19-50
    • Helmholtz1    Poincaré2
  • 5
    • 0013467646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Geometry, construction, and intuition in Kant and his successors
    • Gila Scher and Richard Tieszen (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For extended discussion of Helmholtz and Poincaré see my "Helmholtz's Zeichentheorie and Schlick's Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre," Philosophical Topics 25 (1997): 19-50; "Geometry, Construction, and Intuition in Kant and His Successors," in Gila Scher and Richard Tieszen (eds.), Between Logic and Intuition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) ; and Reconsidering Logical Positivism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), chapter 4.
    • (2000) Between Logic and Intuition
  • 6
    • 0038021434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chapter 4
    • For extended discussion of Helmholtz and Poincaré see my "Helmholtz's Zeichentheorie and Schlick's Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre," Philosophical Topics 25 (1997): 19-50; "Geometry, Construction, and Intuition in Kant and His Successors," in Gila Scher and Richard Tieszen (eds.), Between Logic and Intuition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) ; and Reconsidering Logical Positivism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), chapter 4.
    • (1999) Reconsidering Logical Positivism
  • 7
    • 0009092743 scopus 로고
    • Berlin: Springer
    • Reichenbach, Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis Apriori (Berlin: Springer, 1920); translated as The Theory of Relativity and a Priori Knowledge (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1965). The distinction between the two meanings of the Kantian a priori described in the next sentence occurs in chapter 5.
    • (1920) Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis Apriori
    • Reichenbach1
  • 8
    • 0040749923 scopus 로고
    • translated as Los Angeles: University of California Press, The distinction between the two meanings of the Kantian a priori described in the next sentence occurs in chapter 5
    • Reichenbach, Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis Apriori (Berlin: Springer, 1920); translated as The Theory of Relativity and a Priori Knowledge (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1965). The distinction between the two meanings of the Kantian a priori described in the next sentence occurs in chapter 5.
    • (1965) The Theory of Relativity and a Priori Knowledge
  • 9
    • 0039560285 scopus 로고
    • Wien: Springer
    • Carnap, Logische Syntax der Sprache (Wien: Springer, 1934); translated as The Logical Syntax of Language (London: Kegan Paul, 1937).
    • (1934) Logische Syntax der Sprache
    • Carnap1
  • 10
    • 0003465610 scopus 로고
    • translated as London: Kegan Paul
    • Carnap, Logische Syntax der Sprache (Wien: Springer, 1934); translated as The Logical Syntax of Language (London: Kegan Paul, 1937).
    • (1937) The Logical Syntax of Language
  • 11
    • 0037684656 scopus 로고
    • Empiricism, semantics, and ontology
    • This distinction is first made explicitly in Carnap, "Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology," Revue Internationale de Philosophie 11 (1950): 20-40; reprinted in Meaning and Necessity, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956).
    • (1950) Revue Internationale de Philosophie , vol.11 , pp. 20-40
    • Carnap1
  • 12
    • 0003989950 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • This distinction is first made explicitly in Carnap, "Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology," Revue Internationale de Philosophie 11 (1950): 20-40; reprinted in Meaning and Necessity, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956).
    • (1956) Meaning and Necessity, 2nd Ed.
  • 13
    • 0042325435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carnap explicitly embraces this much of epistemological holism (based on the ideas of Poincaré and Pierre Duhem) in § 82 of Logical Syntax. Quine is therefore extremely misleading when he (in the above-cited passage from § 6 of "Two Dogmas") simply equates analyticity with unrevisability. He is similarly misleading in § 5 (p. 41) when he asserts that the "dogma of reductionism" (i.e., the denial of Duhemian holism) is "at root identical" with the dogma of analyticity
    • Carnap explicitly embraces this much of epistemological holism (based on the ideas of Poincaré and Pierre Duhem) in § 82 of Logical Syntax. Quine is therefore extremely misleading when he (in the above-cited passage from § 6 of "Two Dogmas") simply equates analyticity with unrevisability. He is similarly misleading in § 5 (p. 41) when he asserts that the "dogma of reductionism" (i.e., the denial of Duhemian holism) is "at root identical" with the dogma of analyticity.
  • 14
    • 0041824500 scopus 로고
    • Spacetime theory as physical geometry
    • For an analysis of the principle of equivalence along these lines, including illuminating comparisons with Reichenbach's conception of the need for "coordinating definitions" in physical geometry, see Robert DiSalle, "Spacetime Theory as Physical Geometry," Erkenntnis 42 (1995): 317-337.
    • (1995) Erkenntnis , vol.42 , pp. 317-337
    • DiSalle, R.1
  • 15
    • 0042826526 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press, chapter 9. There is some irony in the circumstance that Kuhn introduces this example as part of a criticism of what he calls "early logical positivism"
    • Kuhn develops this example in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), chapter 9. There is some irony in the circumstance that Kuhn introduces this example as part of a criticism of what he calls "early logical positivism" (p. 98).
    • (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd Ed. , pp. 98
    • Kuhn1
  • 16
    • 0002891695 scopus 로고
    • Afterwords
    • Paul Horwich (ed.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • Kuhn, "Afterwords," in Paul Horwich (ed.), World Changes (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993), pp. 331-332.
    • (1993) World Changes , pp. 331-332
    • Kuhn1
  • 17
    • 85016045643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 10 above
    • Kuhn, "Afterwords" (note 10 above), pp. 338-339.
    • Afterwords , pp. 338-339
    • Kuhn1
  • 18
    • 0003893389 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, chapter 1
    • See Habermas, Theorie des Kommunikativen Handelns (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1981), vol. 1, chapter 1; translated as The Theory of Communicative Action (Boston: Beacon, 1984).
    • (1981) Theorie des Kommunikativen Handelns , vol.1
    • Habermas1
  • 19
    • 0003651494 scopus 로고
    • translated as Boston: Beacon
    • See Habermas, Theorie des Kommunikativen Handelns (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1981), vol. 1, chapter 1; translated as The Theory of Communicative Action (Boston: Beacon, 1984).
    • (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action
  • 20
    • 0042826527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Kuhn's own discussion of the theory of relativity (see note 9), he explicitly denies that classical mechanics can be logically derived from relativistic mechanics in the limit of small velocities. His main ground for this denial is that "the physical referents" of the terms of the two theories are different (op. cit., pp. 101-2). Here, however, I am merely pointing to a purely mathematical fact about the corresponding mathematical structures
    • In Kuhn's own discussion of the theory of relativity (see note 9), he explicitly denies that classical mechanics can be logically derived from relativistic mechanics in the limit of small velocities. His main ground for this denial is that "the physical referents" of the terms of the two theories are different (op. cit., pp. 101-2). Here, however, I am merely pointing to a purely mathematical fact about the corresponding mathematical structures.
  • 21
    • 0042325434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That the convergence in question yields only a purely retrospective reinterpretation of the original theory is a second (and related) point Kuhn makes in the discussion cited in note 13 above, where he points out (p. 101) that the laws derived as special cases in the limit within relativity theory "are not [Newton's] unless those laws are reinterpreted in a way that would have been impossible until after Einstein's work." I believe that Kuhn is correct in this and, in fact, that it captures a centrally important aspect of what he has called the non-intertranslatability or "incommensurability" of pre-revolutionary and post-revolutionary theories
    • That the convergence in question yields only a purely retrospective reinterpretation of the original theory is a second (and related) point Kuhn makes in the discussion cited in note 13 above, where he points out (p. 101) that the laws derived as special cases in the limit within relativity theory "are not [Newton's] unless those laws are reinterpreted in a way that would have been impossible until after Einstein's work." I believe that Kuhn is correct in this and, in fact, that it captures a centrally important aspect of what he has called the non-intertranslatability or "incommensurability" of pre-revolutionary and post-revolutionary theories.
  • 22
    • 70349637009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Geometry as a branch of physics
    • D. Malament (ed.), Chicago: Open Court
    • For a detailed discussion of this case see my "Geometry as a Branch of Physics," in D. Malament (ed.), Reading Natural Philosophy (Chicago: Open Court, 2002).
    • (2002) Reading Natural Philosophy
  • 23
    • 0041323903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See again the reference cited in note 15 above.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.