-
1
-
-
0042923653
-
-
note
-
In re Quinlan, 70 N.J. 10, 355 A.2d 647 (1976). This case involved a brain-damaged patient in a coma. In the face of active opposition from the hospital, the physicians, state and local authorities, and a lower-court guardian ad litem, the New Jersey Supreme Court held that it is permissible for a person's guardian to direct a physician and hospital to discontinue all extraordinary measures in order to allow a person to die. After a lengthy legal battle, the parents of Karen Ann Quinlan obtained a court order allowing them to remove the respirator that was keeping their daughter alive. The court ruled that the Quinlans could disconnect the mechanical ventilator so that the patient could "die with dignity." Unable to communicate with anyone, she lay comatose in a fetal position for ten years, with increasing respiratory problems and bedsores; her weight dropped from 115 to 70 pounds. Several Catholic moral theologians advised the parents that they were not morally required to continue the medical nutrition and hydration used to keep their daughter alive or the antibiotics used to fight her infections. However, the Quinlans believed that the feeding tube did not cause pain and that the respirator did.
-
-
-
-
2
-
-
0042923655
-
-
note
-
Oregon, The Oregon Death with Dignity Act, Or. Rev. Stat. sees. 127.800-897 (1994). Measure 16 was first approved by Oregon voters in a November 8, 1994 referendum. Under its provisions, a terminally ill patient who wants to utilize physician-assisted suicide must wish to escape unbearable suffering and must request a physician's prescription for lethal drugs three times. The doctor then must wait fifteen days after the first request before writing a prescription for the requested lethal drugs. In late December 1994, a federal judge in Eugene, Oregon, issued a preliminary injunction that prevented the implementation of the new law indefinitely. Three years later, on November 4, 1997, voters rejected Measure 51, which would have repealed Measure 16, by a 60-40 margin. This reaffirmed the voters' previous support for legally allowing physicians to provide lethal medication. The 9th U.S. Circuit Court of Appeals had, one week previously, lifted an injunction that had kept Measure 16 from going into effect. A few weeks after its decisions in Vacco v. Quill, 117 S.Ct. 2293 (1997), and Washington v. Glucksberg, 117 S.Ct. 2258 (1977) (see below), the U.S. Supreme Court refused to hear an appeal involving the injunction in Quinlan, and Measure 16 was shortly thereafter reaffirmed by the voters of Oregon and became the law of their state. (Note: The 9th Circuit case mentioned above was from the state of Washington, not Oregon.)
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
0042422901
-
-
note
-
In Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 486 (1965), and various subsequent U.S. Supreme Court decisions, the right of privacy is held to arise from the "penumbra" of several amendments to the U.S. Constitution. The thesis is that a personal right to privacy exists because these amendments imply it.
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
0027021970
-
Cruzan and the Constitutionalization of American Life
-
These problems are examined in Carl E. Schneider, "Cruzan and the Constitutionalization of American Life," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 17, no. 6 (1992): 589-604.
-
(1992)
Journal of Medicine and Philosophy
, vol.17
, Issue.6
, pp. 589-604
-
-
Schneider, C.E.1
-
5
-
-
0041420499
-
-
In re Quinlan
-
In re Quinlan.
-
-
-
-
6
-
-
0042422896
-
-
Ibid., 70 N.J. at 38-42, 355 A.2d at 662-64
-
Ibid., 70 N.J. at 38-42, 355 A.2d at 662-64.
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
0041921792
-
-
Ibid., 70 N.J. at 41, 355 A.2d at 664
-
Ibid., 70 N.J. at 41, 355 A.2d at 664.
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
0041420493
-
-
Ibid., 70 N.J. at 22-29, 35-42, 355 A.2d 653-57, 661-64
-
Ibid., 70 N.J. at 22-29, 35-42, 355 A.2d 653-57, 661-64.
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
0041921804
-
-
note
-
See the string of cases from Superintendent of Belchertown State School v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 737-40, 370 N.E.2d 417, 424-25 (1977) through Bouvia v. Superior Court, 179 Cal. App. 3d 1127, 1144, 225 Cal. Rptr. 297, 306 (1986).
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
0025714235
-
-
Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Dept. of Health, 110 S.Ct. 2841 (1990)
-
Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Dept. of Health, 110 S.Ct. 2841 (1990).
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
0042923642
-
-
note
-
Ibid. Twenty-five-year-old Nancy Cruzan had been in a persistent vegetative state for over three years. Her parents petitioned for permission to remove her feeding tube, knowing that if this were done, their daughter would die. The Missouri Supreme Court ruled that no one may order an end to life-sustaining treatment for an incompetent person in the absence of clear and convincing evidence of the patient's wishes, and the U.S. Supreme Court upheld this decision. The Supreme Court decision was followed by a hearing before a county probate judge at which three friends of Nancy Cruzan provided sufficient additional evidence that she had expressed a clear and convincing preference not to live "like a vegetable" connected to machines. This new evidence led the judge to accept the parents' request to remove the feeding tube, and thirteen days after it was removed, Nancy Cruzan died. Yet, the U.S. Supreme Court had not granted the Cruzan family precisely the relief that it had sought; the Court had declined to find a constitutional right to die, only a right of competent persons to decline life-sustaining treatments. The Court also held that it is constitutionally permissible for states to impose procedural precautions when third parties make decisions for incompetent patients. See Cruzan, 110 S.Ct., esp. at 2852.
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
0041921805
-
-
note
-
Cruzan, 110 S.Ct. at 2851. The Court noted that a constitutionally protected liberty interest in such matters could be inferred from its previous decisions that reached back as far as 1905. "Freedom," "liberty," and "self-determination" are the terms used to ground the argument in Cruzan. The Court also noted that the Supreme Court of Missouri had recognized a right to refuse treatment that was embodied in the common law doctrine of informed consent, but had declined to read a right of privacy into the state constitution and had expressed doubt as to whether such a right existed under the U.S. Constitution. Cruzan v. Harmon, 760 S.W.2d 408, 416-18 (Mo. 1988) (en banc), cert. granted, 109 S.Ct. 3240 (1989). 13 See the Court's own explicit statement on the limits of privacy claims in the subsequent case of Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992).
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
0041921806
-
-
In re Storar, 52 N.Y.2d 363, 376-77, 420 N.E.2d 64, 70 (1981)
-
In re Storar, 52 N.Y.2d 363, 376-77, 420 N.E.2d 64, 70 (1981).
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
0042422898
-
-
note
-
Informed consent is not an ancient concept with a rich medical tradition. The term "informed consent" first appeared in a public case in Salgo v. Leland Stanford, Jr., University Board of Trustees, 317 P.2d 170 (1957). The Salgo court suggested that there is a duty to disclose the risks and alternatives of a proposed treatment, which is a logical extension of the well-established duty to disclose the treatment's nature and consequences. Serious discussion of the doctrine of informed consent began only around 1972 in Canterbury v. Spence, 464 F.2d 772 (D.C. Cir. 1972), and Cobbs v. Grant, 104 Cal. Rptr. 505, 502 P.2d 1 (1972). These courts moved in the direction of a more patient-oriented standard of disclosure in which the patient's right of self-decision requires that the patient be given sufficient information to make an intelligent choice. As the idea of informed consent evolved, discussion of appropriate guidelines moved increasingly from a narrow focus on the physician's or researcher's obligation to disclose information, to the quality of a patient's or subject's understanding of information and right to authorize or refuse a biomedical intervention. 16 In re Conroy, 98 N.J. 321, 486 A.2d 1209 (1985).
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
0041921794
-
-
note
-
Compassion in Dying v. State of Washington, 79 F.3d 790 (9th Cir. 1996); Vacco V. Quill, 80 F.3d 716 (2d Cir. 1996). In the latter, at 723-24, see the court's conclusion that a right to physician-assisted suicide could not be included within the scope of the right of privacy.
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
0042422897
-
-
Vacco, 117 S.Ct. at 2300-2301; Glucksberg, 117 S.Ct. at 2269-70
-
Vacco, 117 S.Ct. at 2300-2301; Glucksberg, 117 S.Ct. at 2269-70.
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
0041420494
-
-
note
-
Many believe that Dr. Jack Kevorkian has been the most significant figure in bringing these issues to public attention, though his influence is highly controversial. His acts of assisted suicide eventuated in several court decisions as well. In the same month as the Glucksberg ruling, a court in Michigan acquitted Kevorkian of charges that he violated the state's newly enacted law on physician-assisted suicide by administering carbon monoxide to a patient. A jury decision in this case found that Kevorkian did not have the relevant intention to be in violation of the Michigan law, which exempted physicians whose intent is to relieve pain or discomfort rather than to cause death. The jury found that Kevorkian had only intended to relieve the suffering of his patients. Only after he performed a direct mercy killing was Kevorkian found guilty of a crime (second-degree murder).
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
0027571479
-
-
New York: Fordham University Press
-
See Bonnie Steinbock and Alastair Norcross, eds., Killing and Letting Die, 2d ed. (New York: Fordham University Press, 1994); Tom L. Beauchamp, ed., Intending Death (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1996); H. M. Malm, "Killing, Letting Die, and Simple Conflicts," Philosophy and Public Affairs 18, no. 3 (Summer 1989): 238-58; Jeff McMahan, "Killing, Letting Die, and Withdrawing Aid," Ethics 103, no. 2 (January 1993): 250-79; and Lawrence O. Gostin, "Drawing a Line Between Killing and Letting Die: The Law, and Law Reform, on Medically Assisted Dying," Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics 21, no. 1 (Spring 1993): 94-101.
-
(1994)
Killing and Letting Die, 2d Ed.
-
-
Steinbock, B.1
Norcross, A.2
-
19
-
-
0027571479
-
-
Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall
-
See Bonnie Steinbock and Alastair Norcross, eds., Killing and Letting Die, 2d ed. (New York: Fordham University Press, 1994); Tom L. Beauchamp, ed., Intending Death (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1996); H. M. Malm, "Killing, Letting Die, and Simple Conflicts," Philosophy and Public Affairs 18, no. 3 (Summer 1989): 238-58; Jeff McMahan, "Killing, Letting Die, and Withdrawing Aid," Ethics 103, no. 2 (January 1993): 250-79; and Lawrence O. Gostin, "Drawing a Line Between Killing and Letting Die: The Law, and Law Reform, on Medically Assisted Dying," Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics 21, no. 1 (Spring 1993): 94-101.
-
(1996)
Intending Death
-
-
Beauchamp, T.L.1
-
20
-
-
0024676931
-
Killing, Letting Die, and Simple Conflicts
-
Summer
-
See Bonnie Steinbock and Alastair Norcross, eds., Killing and Letting Die, 2d ed. (New York: Fordham University Press, 1994); Tom L. Beauchamp, ed., Intending Death (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1996); H. M. Malm, "Killing, Letting Die, and Simple Conflicts," Philosophy and Public Affairs 18, no. 3 (Summer 1989): 238-58; Jeff McMahan, "Killing, Letting Die, and Withdrawing Aid," Ethics 103, no. 2 (January 1993): 250-79; and Lawrence O. Gostin, "Drawing a Line Between Killing and Letting Die: The Law, and Law Reform, on Medically Assisted Dying," Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics 21, no. 1 (Spring 1993): 94-101.
-
(1989)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.18
, Issue.3
, pp. 238-258
-
-
Malm, H.M.1
-
21
-
-
0027448495
-
Killing, Letting Die, and Withdrawing Aid
-
January
-
See Bonnie Steinbock and Alastair Norcross, eds., Killing and Letting Die, 2d ed. (New York: Fordham University Press, 1994); Tom L. Beauchamp, ed., Intending Death (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1996); H. M. Malm, "Killing, Letting Die, and Simple Conflicts," Philosophy and Public Affairs 18, no. 3 (Summer 1989): 238-58; Jeff McMahan, "Killing, Letting Die, and Withdrawing Aid," Ethics 103, no. 2 (January 1993): 250-79; and Lawrence O. Gostin, "Drawing a Line Between Killing and Letting Die: The Law, and Law Reform, on Medically Assisted Dying," Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics 21, no. 1 (Spring 1993): 94-101.
-
(1993)
Ethics
, vol.103
, Issue.2
, pp. 250-279
-
-
McMahan, J.1
-
22
-
-
0027571479
-
Drawing a Line between Killing and Letting Die: The Law, and Law Reform, on Medically Assisted Dying
-
Spring
-
See Bonnie Steinbock and Alastair Norcross, eds., Killing and Letting Die, 2d ed. (New York: Fordham University Press, 1994); Tom L. Beauchamp, ed., Intending Death (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1996); H. M. Malm, "Killing, Letting Die, and Simple Conflicts," Philosophy and Public Affairs 18, no. 3 (Summer 1989): 238-58; Jeff McMahan, "Killing, Letting Die, and Withdrawing Aid," Ethics 103, no. 2 (January 1993): 250-79; and Lawrence O. Gostin, "Drawing a Line Between Killing and Letting Die: The Law, and Law Reform, on Medically Assisted Dying," Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics 21, no. 1 (Spring 1993): 94-101.
-
(1993)
Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics
, vol.21
, Issue.1
, pp. 94-101
-
-
Gostin, L.O.1
-
23
-
-
0016431107
-
Active and Passive Euthanasia
-
January 9
-
Cf. James Rachels, "Active and Passive Euthanasia," New England Journal of Medicine 292, no. 2 (January 9, 1975): 78-80. See also his The End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986); and Dan W. Brock, "Voluntary Active Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 22, no. 2 (March/April 1992): 10-22.
-
(1975)
New England Journal of Medicine
, vol.292
, Issue.2
, pp. 78-80
-
-
Rachels, J.1
-
24
-
-
0016431107
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Cf. James Rachels, "Active and Passive Euthanasia," New England Journal of Medicine 292, no. 2 (January 9, 1975): 78-80. See also his The End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986); and Dan W. Brock, "Voluntary Active Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 22, no. 2 (March/April 1992): 10-22.
-
(1986)
The End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality
-
-
-
25
-
-
0026831186
-
Voluntary Active Euthanasia
-
March/April
-
Cf. James Rachels, "Active and Passive Euthanasia," New England Journal of Medicine 292, no. 2 (January 9, 1975): 78-80. See also his The End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986); and Dan W. Brock, "Voluntary Active Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 22, no. 2 (March/April 1992): 10-22.
-
(1992)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.22
, Issue.2
, pp. 10-22
-
-
Brock, D.W.1
-
26
-
-
0024288115
-
Vital Distinctions, Mortal Questions: Debating Euthanasia and Health Care Costs
-
July 15
-
See Daniel Callahan, "Vital Distinctions, Mortal Questions: Debating Euthanasia and Health Care Costs," Commonweal 115, no. 13 (July 15, 1988): 397-404; Daniel Callahan, The Troubled Dream of Life (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1993), chap. 2; and several articles in Joanne Lynn, ed., By No Extraordinary Means (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1986), 227-66.
-
(1988)
Commonweal
, vol.115
, Issue.13
, pp. 397-404
-
-
Callahan, D.1
-
27
-
-
0024288115
-
-
New York: Simon and Schuster, chap. 2
-
See Daniel Callahan, "Vital Distinctions, Mortal Questions: Debating Euthanasia and Health Care Costs," Commonweal 115, no. 13 (July 15, 1988): 397-404; Daniel Callahan, The Troubled Dream of Life (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1993), chap. 2; and several articles in Joanne Lynn, ed., By No Extraordinary Means (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1986), 227-66.
-
(1993)
The Troubled Dream of Life
-
-
Callahan, D.1
-
28
-
-
0024288115
-
-
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press
-
See Daniel Callahan, "Vital Distinctions, Mortal Questions: Debating Euthanasia and Health Care Costs," Commonweal 115, no. 13 (July 15, 1988): 397-404; Daniel Callahan, The Troubled Dream of Life (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1993), chap. 2; and several articles in Joanne Lynn, ed., By No Extraordinary Means (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1986), 227-66.
-
(1986)
By No Extraordinary Means
, pp. 227-266
-
-
Lynn, J.1
-
29
-
-
0041921785
-
-
note
-
It is not absurd to say that a physician's actions physically cause death even when he or she forbears from treatment as a result of a patient's refusal. The actions of physicians are commonly necessary parts of sufficient conditions of a death as it occurs. For example, to withhold nutrition and hydration so that a patient dies of malnutrition is a necessary part of a sufficient condition of death at the time and in the way the death occurs. The doctor is not a sufficient cause of death but is a necessary part of a sufficient set of conditions of death. If the patient is suffering from conditions such as severe brain damage or cancer, these conditions are neither necessary nor sufficient conditions of death in the way it comes about. In many cases, both a physician's intervention and a disease, system failure, or injury are joint causal conditions of death. In a few more uncommon cases, multiple causal conditions may be relevant, each forming an independent causal sequence that is sufficient to cause death. That is, any one of several distinct sequences of causally linked events may be sufficient to cause death.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
0027771106
-
Patient Refusal of Hydration and Nutrition
-
December 27
-
On the importance of the refusal/request distinction, see James L. Bernat, Bernard Gert, and R. Peter Mogielnicki, "Patient Refusal of Hydration and Nutrition," Archives of Internal Medicine 153, no. 24 (December 27, 1993): 2723-28; Gert, Bernat, and Mogielnicki, "Distinguishing between Patients' Refusals and Requests," Hastings Center Report 24, no. 4 (July/ August 1994): 13-15; and Gert et al., "The Distinction between Active and Passive Euthanasia," Archives of Internal Medicine 155, no. 12 (June 26, 1995): 1329.
-
(1993)
Archives of Internal Medicine
, vol.153
, Issue.24
, pp. 2723-2728
-
-
Bernat, J.L.1
Gert, B.2
Mogielnicki, R.P.3
-
31
-
-
0028470568
-
Distinguishing between Patients' Refusals and Requests
-
July/ August
-
On the importance of the refusal/request distinction, see James L. Bernat, Bernard Gert, and R. Peter Mogielnicki, "Patient Refusal of Hydration and Nutrition," Archives of Internal Medicine 153, no. 24 (December 27, 1993): 2723-28; Gert, Bernat, and Mogielnicki, "Distinguishing between Patients' Refusals and Requests," Hastings Center Report 24, no. 4 (July/ August 1994): 13-15; and Gert et al., "The Distinction between Active and Passive Euthanasia," Archives of Internal Medicine 155, no. 12 (June 26, 1995): 1329.
-
(1994)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.24
, Issue.4
, pp. 13-15
-
-
Gert1
Bernat2
Mogielnicki3
-
32
-
-
0029069184
-
The Distinction between Active and Passive Euthanasia
-
June 26
-
On the importance of the refusal/request distinction, see James L. Bernat, Bernard Gert, and R. Peter Mogielnicki, "Patient Refusal of Hydration and Nutrition," Archives of Internal Medicine 153, no. 24 (December 27, 1993): 2723-28; Gert, Bernat, and Mogielnicki, "Distinguishing between Patients' Refusals and Requests," Hastings Center Report 24, no. 4 (July/ August 1994): 13-15; and Gert et al., "The Distinction between Active and Passive Euthanasia," Archives of Internal Medicine 155, no. 12 (June 26, 1995): 1329.
-
(1995)
Archives of Internal Medicine
, vol.155
, Issue.12
, pp. 1329
-
-
Gert1
-
33
-
-
0042422890
-
-
note
-
A physician who in principle accepts the permissibility of active aid-in-dying may legitimately refuse to honor any particular request for aid-in-dying for various reasons. For example, a sympathetic physician willing to assist a patient at a crisis point may refuse a patient's request for lethal medication if that request is premature.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
0007544160
-
Intending Death: The Structure of the Problem and Proposed Solutions
-
Beauchamp, ed.
-
Cf. Allen Buchanan, "Intending Death: The Structure of the Problem and Proposed Solutions," in Beauchamp, ed., Intending Death, 34-38 ; Thomas Nagel, "Death," in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); and F. M. Kamm, Morality, Mortality, vol. 1 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), chap. 1.
-
Intending Death
, pp. 34-38
-
-
Buchanan, A.1
-
35
-
-
0011340930
-
Death
-
Nagel, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Cf. Allen Buchanan, "Intending Death: The Structure of the Problem and Proposed Solutions," in Beauchamp, ed., Intending Death, 34-38 ; Thomas Nagel, "Death," in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); and F. M. Kamm, Morality, Mortality, vol. 1 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), chap. 1.
-
(1979)
Mortal Questions
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
36
-
-
0009434199
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press, chap. 1
-
Cf. Allen Buchanan, "Intending Death: The Structure of the Problem and Proposed Solutions," in Beauchamp, ed., Intending Death, 34-38 ; Thomas Nagel, "Death," in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); and F. M. Kamm, Morality, Mortality, vol. 1 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), chap. 1.
-
(1993)
Morality, Mortality
, vol.1
-
-
Kamm, F.M.1
-
37
-
-
0041420486
-
-
note
-
Several years after Nancy Cruzan died, Joseph Cruzan killed himself. He had suffered a long period of depression.
-
-
-
-
38
-
-
21444450261
-
A Cognitive Access Definition of Privacy
-
November
-
Some definitions of privacy center on a narrow range of conditions under which intrusions constitute losses of privacy, whereas other definitions center on a broader range of conditions. Some definitions view privacy as a condition of the person, others as a condition of control by the person over access to information. Some definitions place a value on privacy, others do not. See Madison Powers's survey of several definitions of privacy in "A Cognitive Access Definition of Privacy," Law and Philosophy 15, no. 4 (November 1996): 369-86; and Anita L. Allen's examination of restricted-access definitions in Uneasy Access: Privacy for Women in a Free Society (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1988). See also Alan F. Westin, Privacy and Freedom (New York: Athenaeum, 1967); and the critique by Ferdinand David Schoeman, "Privacy: Philosophical Dimensions of the Literature," in Schoeman, ed., Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy: An Anthology (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 3-4.
-
(1996)
Law and Philosophy
, vol.15
, Issue.4
, pp. 369-386
-
-
Powers, M.1
-
39
-
-
0009301899
-
-
Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield
-
Some definitions of privacy center on a narrow range of conditions under which intrusions constitute losses of privacy, whereas other definitions center on a broader range of conditions. Some definitions view privacy as a condition of the person, others as a condition of control by the person over access to information. Some definitions place a value on privacy, others do not. See Madison Powers's survey of several definitions of privacy in "A Cognitive Access Definition of Privacy," Law and Philosophy 15, no. 4 (November 1996): 369-86; and Anita L. Allen's examination of restricted-access definitions in Uneasy Access: Privacy for Women in a Free Society (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1988). See also Alan F. Westin, Privacy and Freedom (New York: Athenaeum, 1967); and the critique by Ferdinand David Schoeman, "Privacy: Philosophical Dimensions of the Literature," in Schoeman, ed., Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy: An Anthology (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 3-4.
-
(1988)
Uneasy Access: Privacy for Women in a Free Society
-
-
Allen, A.L.1
-
40
-
-
0004073139
-
-
New York: Athenaeum
-
Some definitions of privacy center on a narrow range of conditions under which intrusions constitute losses of privacy, whereas other definitions center on a broader range of conditions. Some definitions view privacy as a condition of the person, others as a condition of control by the person over access to information. Some definitions place a value on privacy, others do not. See Madison Powers's survey of several definitions of privacy in "A Cognitive Access Definition of Privacy," Law and Philosophy 15, no. 4 (November 1996): 369-86; and Anita L. Allen's examination of restricted-access definitions in Uneasy Access: Privacy for Women in a Free Society (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1988). See also Alan F. Westin, Privacy and Freedom (New York: Athenaeum, 1967); and the critique by Ferdinand David Schoeman, "Privacy: Philosophical Dimensions of the Literature," in Schoeman, ed., Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy: An Anthology (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 3-4.
-
(1967)
Privacy and Freedom
-
-
Westin, A.F.1
-
41
-
-
0003297655
-
Privacy: Philosophical Dimensions of the Literature
-
Schoeman, ed., New York: Cambridge University Press
-
Some definitions of privacy center on a narrow range of conditions under which intrusions constitute losses of privacy, whereas other definitions center on a broader range of conditions. Some definitions view privacy as a condition of the person, others as a condition of control by the person over access to information. Some definitions place a value on privacy, others do not. See Madison Powers's survey of several definitions of privacy in "A Cognitive Access Definition of Privacy," Law and Philosophy 15, no. 4 (November 1996): 369-86; and Anita L. Allen's examination of restricted-access definitions in Uneasy Access: Privacy for Women in a Free Society (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1988). See also Alan F. Westin, Privacy and Freedom (New York: Athenaeum, 1967); and the critique by Ferdinand David Schoeman, "Privacy: Philosophical Dimensions of the Literature," in Schoeman, ed., Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy: An Anthology (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 3-4.
-
(1984)
Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy: An Anthology
, pp. 3-4
-
-
Schoeman, F.D.1
-
42
-
-
84923486508
-
Privacy and the Limits of Law
-
January
-
Cf. Ruth Gavison, "Privacy and the Limits of Law," Yale Law Journal 89, no. 3 (January 1980): 428. (Gavison's article is reprinted in Schoeman, ed., Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy, 346-402.)
-
(1980)
Yale Law Journal
, vol.89
, Issue.3
, pp. 428
-
-
Gavison, R.1
-
43
-
-
0003688001
-
-
Cf. Ruth Gavison, "Privacy and the Limits of Law," Yale Law Journal 89, no. 3 (January 1980): 428. (Gavison's article is reprinted in Schoeman, ed., Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy, 346-402.)
-
Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy
, pp. 346-402
-
-
Schoeman1
-
44
-
-
0003506796
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press, chap. 19
-
Suffice it to say, here, that personal autonomy carries over the ideas of a region of sovereignty for the self and a right to protect it by restricting access, ideas that are closely linked to the concepts of privacy and the right to privacy. Cf. Joel Feinberg, Harm to Self, vol. 3 of The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), chap. 19. The idea that certain forms of self-determination are immune from social control has made the legal right of privacy controversial throughout its history. The U.S. Supreme Court has sometimes hinted that the right to privacy is primarily a right of self-determination in decision-making, a right on which clear boundaries must be placed. See Whalen v. Roe, 429 U.S. 589, 599-600 (1977).
-
(1986)
Harm to Self, Vol. 3 of the Moral Limits of the Criminal Law
, vol.3
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
45
-
-
0042923648
-
-
Whalen v. Roe, 429 U.S. 589, 599-600 (1977)
-
Suffice it to say, here, that personal autonomy carries over the ideas of a region of sovereignty for the self and a right to protect it by restricting access, ideas that are closely linked to the concepts of privacy and the right to privacy. Cf. Joel Feinberg, Harm to Self, vol. 3 of The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), chap. 19. The idea that certain forms of self-determination are immune from social control has made the legal right of privacy controversial throughout its history. The U.S. Supreme Court has sometimes hinted that the right to privacy is primarily a right of self-determination in decision-making, a right on which clear boundaries must be placed. See Whalen v. Roe, 429 U.S. 589, 599-600 (1977).
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
0027343366
-
Is There a Right to Die?
-
January/ February
-
Leon Kass, "Is There a Right to Die?" Hastings Center Report 23, no. 1 (January/ February 1993), reprinted in Tom L. Beauchamp and LeRoy Walters, eds., Contemporary Issues in Bioethics, 5th ed. (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1999), 352 n. 10.
-
(1993)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.23
, Issue.1
-
-
Kass, L.1
-
47
-
-
0007087796
-
-
reprinted, Belmont, CA: Wadsworth
-
Leon Kass, "Is There a Right to Die?" Hastings Center Report 23, no. 1 (January/ February 1993), reprinted in Tom L. Beauchamp and LeRoy Walters, eds., Contemporary Issues in Bioethics, 5th ed. (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1999), 352 n. 10.
-
(1999)
Contemporary Issues in Bioethics, 5th Ed.
, vol.352
, Issue.10
-
-
Beauchamp, T.L.1
Walters, L.2
-
48
-
-
0004024635
-
-
chap. 10
-
Cf. James Rachels, The End of Life, chap. 10; John Arras, "The Right to Die on the Slippery Slope," Social Theory and Practice 8, no. 3 (Fall 1982): 285-328; Wibren van der Burg, "The Slippery Slope Argument," Ethics 102, no. 1 (October 1991): 42-65; Ruth Macklin, "Which Way Down the Slippery Slope? Nazi Medical Killing and Euthanasia Today," in Arthur L. Caplan, ed., When Medicine Went Mad: Bioethics and the Holocaust (Totowa, NJ: Humana Press, 1992), 173-200;
-
The End of Life
-
-
Rachels, J.1
-
49
-
-
0020174963
-
The Right to Die on the Slippery Slope
-
Fall
-
Cf. James Rachels, The End of Life, chap. 10; John Arras, "The Right to Die on the Slippery Slope," Social Theory and Practice 8, no. 3 (Fall 1982): 285-328; Wibren van der Burg, "The Slippery Slope Argument," Ethics 102, no. 1 (October 1991): 42-65; Ruth Macklin, "Which Way Down the Slippery Slope? Nazi Medical Killing and Euthanasia Today," in Arthur L. Caplan, ed., When Medicine Went Mad: Bioethics and the Holocaust (Totowa, NJ: Humana Press, 1992), 173-200;
-
(1982)
Social Theory and Practice
, vol.8
, Issue.3
, pp. 285-328
-
-
Arras, J.1
-
50
-
-
84928439521
-
The Slippery Slope Argument
-
October
-
Cf. James Rachels, The End of Life, chap. 10; John Arras, "The Right to Die on the Slippery Slope," Social Theory and Practice 8, no. 3 (Fall 1982): 285-328; Wibren van der Burg, "The Slippery Slope Argument," Ethics 102, no. 1 (October 1991): 42-65; Ruth Macklin, "Which Way Down the Slippery Slope? Nazi Medical Killing and Euthanasia Today," in Arthur L. Caplan, ed., When Medicine Went Mad: Bioethics and the Holocaust (Totowa, NJ: Humana Press, 1992), 173-200;
-
(1991)
Ethics
, vol.102
, Issue.1
, pp. 42-65
-
-
Van Der Burg, W.1
-
51
-
-
0041420487
-
Which Way Down the Slippery Slope? Nazi Medical Killing and Euthanasia Today
-
Arthur L. Caplan, ed., Totowa, NJ: Humana Press
-
Cf. James Rachels, The End of Life, chap. 10; John Arras, "The Right to Die on the Slippery Slope," Social Theory and Practice 8, no. 3 (Fall 1982): 285-328; Wibren van der Burg, "The Slippery Slope Argument," Ethics 102, no. 1 (October 1991): 42-65; Ruth Macklin, "Which Way Down the Slippery Slope? Nazi Medical Killing and Euthanasia Today," in Arthur L. Caplan, ed., When Medicine Went Mad: Bioethics and the Holocaust (Totowa, NJ: Humana Press, 1992), 173-200;
-
(1992)
When Medicine Went Mad: Bioethics and the Holocaust
, pp. 173-200
-
-
Macklin, R.1
-
52
-
-
0027518004
-
The Great Slippery-Slope Argument
-
September
-
J. A. Burgess, "The Great Slippery-Slope Argument," Journal of Medical Ethics 19, no. 3 (September 1993): 169-74; and Douglas Walton, Slippery Slope Arguments (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992).
-
(1993)
Journal of Medical Ethics
, vol.19
, Issue.3
, pp. 169-174
-
-
Burgess, J.A.1
-
53
-
-
0027518004
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
J. A. Burgess, "The Great Slippery-Slope Argument," Journal of Medical Ethics 19, no. 3 (September 1993): 169-74; and Douglas Walton, Slippery Slope Arguments (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992).
-
(1992)
Slippery Slope Arguments
-
-
Walton, D.1
-
54
-
-
0025298649
-
Euthanasia - A Critique
-
June 28
-
See Peter A. Singer and Mark Siegler, "Euthanasia - A Critique," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (June 28, 1990): 1881-83; Joanne Lynn, "The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought," Journal of Palliative Care 4, nos. 1 and 2 (May 1988): 100-102; Susan Wolf, "Holding the Line on Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 19, no. 1 (January/February 1989): S13-S15; Leon R. Kass, "Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Public Interest 94 (1989): 25-46; H. Hendin and Gerald Klerman, "Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization," American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 1 (January 1993): 143-45; Alan D. Ogilvie and S. G. Potts, "Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience," British Medical Journal 309, no. 6953 (August 20-21, 1994): 492-93; Raymond J. Devettere, "Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning," Journal of Clinical Ethics 3, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 298; David Orentlicher, "Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide," Journal of the American Medical Association 262, no. 13 (October 6, 1989): 1844-45; and C. Everett Koop and Edward R. Grant, "The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 2, no. 3 (Spring 1986): 585-634.
-
(1990)
New England Journal of Medicine
, vol.322
, pp. 1881-1883
-
-
Singer, P.A.1
Siegler, M.2
-
55
-
-
0024007106
-
The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought
-
May
-
See Peter A. Singer and Mark Siegler, "Euthanasia - A Critique," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (June 28, 1990): 1881-83; Joanne Lynn, "The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought," Journal of Palliative Care 4, nos. 1 and 2 (May 1988): 100-102; Susan Wolf, "Holding the Line on Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 19, no. 1 (January/February 1989): S13-S15; Leon R. Kass, "Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Public Interest 94 (1989): 25-46; H. Hendin and Gerald Klerman, "Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization," American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 1 (January 1993): 143-45; Alan D. Ogilvie and S. G. Potts, "Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience," British Medical Journal 309, no. 6953 (August 20-21, 1994): 492-93; Raymond J. Devettere, "Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning," Journal of Clinical Ethics 3, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 298; David Orentlicher, "Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide," Journal of the American Medical Association 262, no. 13 (October 6, 1989): 1844-45; and C. Everett Koop and Edward R. Grant, "The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 2, no. 3 (Spring 1986): 585-634.
-
(1988)
Journal of Palliative Care
, vol.4
, Issue.1-2
, pp. 100-102
-
-
Lynn, J.1
-
56
-
-
0024352621
-
Holding the Line on Euthanasia
-
January/February
-
See Peter A. Singer and Mark Siegler, "Euthanasia - A Critique," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (June 28, 1990): 1881-83; Joanne Lynn, "The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought," Journal of Palliative Care 4, nos. 1 and 2 (May 1988): 100-102; Susan Wolf, "Holding the Line on Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 19, no. 1 (January/February 1989): S13-S15; Leon R. Kass, "Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Public Interest 94 (1989): 25-46; H. Hendin and Gerald Klerman, "Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization," American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 1 (January 1993): 143-45; Alan D. Ogilvie and S. G. Potts, "Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience," British Medical Journal 309, no. 6953 (August 20-21, 1994): 492-93; Raymond J. Devettere, "Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning," Journal of Clinical Ethics 3, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 298; David Orentlicher, "Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide," Journal of the American Medical Association 262, no. 13 (October 6, 1989): 1844-45; and C. Everett Koop and Edward R. Grant, "The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 2, no. 3 (Spring 1986): 585-634.
-
(1989)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.19
, Issue.1
-
-
Wolf, S.1
-
57
-
-
0024872024
-
Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill
-
See Peter A. Singer and Mark Siegler, "Euthanasia - A Critique," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (June 28, 1990): 1881-83; Joanne Lynn, "The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought," Journal of Palliative Care 4, nos. 1 and 2 (May 1988): 100-102; Susan Wolf, "Holding the Line on Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 19, no. 1 (January/February 1989): S13-S15; Leon R. Kass, "Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Public Interest 94 (1989): 25-46; H. Hendin and Gerald Klerman, "Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization," American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 1 (January 1993): 143-45; Alan D. Ogilvie and S. G. Potts, "Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience," British Medical Journal 309, no. 6953 (August 20-21, 1994): 492-93; Raymond J. Devettere, "Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning," Journal of Clinical Ethics 3, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 298; David Orentlicher, "Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide," Journal of the American Medical Association 262, no. 13 (October 6, 1989): 1844-45; and C. Everett Koop and Edward R. Grant, "The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 2, no. 3 (Spring 1986): 585-634.
-
(1989)
Public Interest
, vol.94
, pp. 25-46
-
-
Kass, L.R.1
-
58
-
-
0027510620
-
Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization
-
January
-
See Peter A. Singer and Mark Siegler, "Euthanasia - A Critique," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (June 28, 1990): 1881-83; Joanne Lynn, "The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought," Journal of Palliative Care 4, nos. 1 and 2 (May 1988): 100-102; Susan Wolf, "Holding the Line on Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 19, no. 1 (January/February 1989): S13-S15; Leon R. Kass, "Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Public Interest 94 (1989): 25-46; H. Hendin and Gerald Klerman, "Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization," American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 1 (January 1993): 143-45; Alan D. Ogilvie and S. G. Potts, "Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience," British Medical Journal 309, no. 6953 (August 20-21, 1994): 492-93; Raymond J. Devettere, "Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning," Journal of Clinical Ethics 3, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 298; David Orentlicher, "Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide," Journal of the American Medical Association 262, no. 13 (October 6, 1989): 1844-45; and C. Everett Koop and Edward R. Grant, "The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 2, no. 3 (Spring 1986): 585-634.
-
(1993)
American Journal of Psychiatry
, vol.150
, Issue.1
, pp. 143-145
-
-
Hendin, H.1
Klerman, G.2
-
59
-
-
0028098803
-
Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience
-
August 20-21
-
See Peter A. Singer and Mark Siegler, "Euthanasia - A Critique," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (June 28, 1990): 1881-83; Joanne Lynn, "The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought," Journal of Palliative Care 4, nos. 1 and 2 (May 1988): 100-102; Susan Wolf, "Holding the Line on Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 19, no. 1 (January/February 1989): S13-S15; Leon R. Kass, "Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Public Interest 94 (1989): 25-46; H. Hendin and Gerald Klerman, "Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization," American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 1 (January 1993): 143-45; Alan D. Ogilvie and S. G. Potts, "Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience," British Medical Journal 309, no. 6953 (August 20-21, 1994): 492-93; Raymond J. Devettere, "Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning," Journal of Clinical Ethics 3, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 298; David Orentlicher, "Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide," Journal of the American Medical Association 262, no. 13 (October 6, 1989): 1844-45; and C. Everett Koop and Edward R. Grant, "The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 2, no. 3 (Spring 1986): 585-634.
-
(1994)
British Medical Journal
, vol.309
, Issue.6953
, pp. 492-493
-
-
Ogilvie, A.D.1
Potts, S.G.2
-
60
-
-
0027015463
-
Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning
-
Winter
-
See Peter A. Singer and Mark Siegler, "Euthanasia - A Critique," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (June 28, 1990): 1881-83; Joanne Lynn, "The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought," Journal of Palliative Care 4, nos. 1 and 2 (May 1988): 100-102; Susan Wolf, "Holding the Line on Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 19, no. 1 (January/February 1989): S13-S15; Leon R. Kass, "Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Public Interest 94 (1989): 25-46; H. Hendin and Gerald Klerman, "Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization," American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 1 (January 1993): 143-45; Alan D. Ogilvie and S. G. Potts, "Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience," British Medical Journal 309, no. 6953 (August 20-21, 1994): 492-93; Raymond J. Devettere, "Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning," Journal of Clinical Ethics 3, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 298; David Orentlicher, "Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide," Journal of the American Medical Association 262, no. 13 (October 6, 1989): 1844-45; and C. Everett Koop and Edward R. Grant, "The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 2, no. 3 (Spring 1986): 585-634.
-
(1992)
Journal of Clinical Ethics
, vol.3
, Issue.4
, pp. 298
-
-
Devettere, R.J.1
-
61
-
-
0024415151
-
Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide
-
October 6
-
See Peter A. Singer and Mark Siegler, "Euthanasia - A Critique," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (June 28, 1990): 1881-83; Joanne Lynn, "The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought," Journal of Palliative Care 4, nos. 1 and 2 (May 1988): 100-102; Susan Wolf, "Holding the Line on Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 19, no. 1 (January/February 1989): S13-S15; Leon R. Kass, "Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Public Interest 94 (1989): 25-46; H. Hendin and Gerald Klerman, "Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization," American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 1 (January 1993): 143-45; Alan D. Ogilvie and S. G. Potts, "Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience," British Medical Journal 309, no. 6953 (August 20-21, 1994): 492-93; Raymond J. Devettere, "Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning," Journal of Clinical Ethics 3, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 298; David Orentlicher, "Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide," Journal of the American Medical Association 262, no. 13 (October 6, 1989): 1844-45; and C. Everett Koop and Edward R. Grant, "The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 2, no. 3 (Spring 1986): 585-634.
-
(1989)
Journal of the American Medical Association
, vol.262
, Issue.13
, pp. 1844-1845
-
-
Orentlicher, D.1
-
62
-
-
0022681888
-
The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing
-
Spring
-
See Peter A. Singer and Mark Siegler, "Euthanasia - A Critique," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (June 28, 1990): 1881-83; Joanne Lynn, "The Health Care Professional's Role When Active Euthanasia Is Sought," Journal of Palliative Care 4, nos. 1 and 2 (May 1988): 100-102; Susan Wolf, "Holding the Line on Euthanasia," Hastings Center Report 19, no. 1 (January/February 1989): S13-S15; Leon R. Kass, "Neither for Love Nor Money: Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Public Interest 94 (1989): 25-46; H. Hendin and Gerald Klerman, "Physician-Assisted Suicide: The Dangers of Legalization," American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 1 (January 1993): 143-45; Alan D. Ogilvie and S. G. Potts, "Assisted Suicide for Depression: The Slippery Slope in Action?: Learning from the Dutch Experience," British Medical Journal 309, no. 6953 (August 20-21, 1994): 492-93; Raymond J. Devettere, "Slippery Slopes and Moral Reasoning," Journal of Clinical Ethics 3, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 298; David Orentlicher, "Physician Participation in Assisted Suicide," Journal of the American Medical Association 262, no. 13 (October 6, 1989): 1844-45; and C. Everett Koop and Edward R. Grant, "The 'Small Beginnings' of Euthanasia: Examining the Erosion in Legal Prohibitions against Mercy-Killing," Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 2, no. 3 (Spring 1986): 585-634.
-
(1986)
Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy
, vol.2
, Issue.3
, pp. 585-634
-
-
Koop, C.E.1
Grant, E.R.2
|