메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 17, Issue 2, 2000, Pages 120-139

Privacy and limited democracy: The moral centrality of persons

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041686447     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0265052500002132     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (67)
  • 1
    • 0003667001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • I have developed at some length the arguments regarding this grounding in consent of a morality that can be shared with moral strangers; see my The Foundations of Bioethics, 2d ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) The Foundations of Bioethics, 2d Ed.
  • 2
    • 0041922001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A phenomenology of privacy would offer a presentation of the lived experience of the importance of various forms of privacy.
  • 6
    • 0031514873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Digital People, Digital Places: Rethinking Privacy in a World of Information
    • April
    • Satellites can not only photograph activities on private property that one might take to be unseen, but can also, by mapping, create a universal set of identifiers. See, for example, Michael R. Curry, "Digital People, Digital Places: Rethinking Privacy in a World of Information," Ethics Behavior 7, no. 3 (April 1997): 253-63.
    • (1997) Ethics Behavior , vol.7 , Issue.3 , pp. 253-263
    • Curry, M.R.1
  • 7
    • 0041420669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The ordinary and customary measurement for ranchland in Texas and other civilized regions is in sections; a section contains one square mile, a mile being eight furlongs long. It is because a furlong is ten chains long and a chain 66 feet that a mile is 5,280 feet long. A decent ranch would comprise nine sections, because a league is three miles and Spanish land grants were for a square league of land.
  • 8
    • 0031536396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corporate Appropriation of Privacy: The Transformation of the Personal and Public
    • April
    • See, for example, Timothy H. Engstrom, "Corporate Appropriation of Privacy: The Transformation of the Personal and Public," Ethics Behavior 7, no. 3 (April 1997): 239-52; and M. Gregg Bloche, "Managed Care, Medical Privacy, and the Paradigm of Consent," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 7, no. 4 (December 1997): 381-86.
    • (1997) Ethics Behavior , vol.7 , Issue.3 , pp. 239-252
    • Engstrom, T.H.1
  • 9
    • 0031291877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Managed Care, Medical Privacy, and the Paradigm of Consent
    • December
    • See, for example, Timothy H. Engstrom, "Corporate Appropriation of Privacy: The Transformation of the Personal and Public," Ethics Behavior 7, no. 3 (April 1997): 239-52; and M. Gregg Bloche, "Managed Care, Medical Privacy, and the Paradigm of Consent," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 7, no. 4 (December 1997): 381-86.
    • (1997) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.7 , Issue.4 , pp. 381-386
    • Gregg Bloche, M.1
  • 10
    • 0031261236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Genetics Revolution: Economics, Ethics and Insurance
    • November
    • The mere comparison of blood types within a family often reveals that the wife's husband, whose role as the father of the children had been taken for granted, cannot be the biological father. Genetic science threatens the disclosure of an immense amount of further information with significant social and economic implications. See, for example, Patrick L. Brockett and E. Susan Tankersley, "The Genetics Revolution: Economics, Ethics and Insurance," Journal of Business Ethics 16, no. 15 (November 1997): 1661-76.
    • (1997) Journal of Business Ethics , vol.16 , Issue.15 , pp. 1661-1676
    • Brockett, P.L.1    Tankersley, E.S.2
  • 11
    • 0041420676 scopus 로고
    • reprint, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
    • Rights to privacy have roots in the vaunted rights of Englishmen, which draw on ancient pagan moral, political, and legal understandings that recognized the individual as having inherent and robust rights against the sovereign. See, for example, Henry Charles Lea, Torture (1866; reprint, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1973), 24-25; and the reports of Tacitus in his Germania. Albeit transformed by later influences, these understandings persisted in English law and framed the pagan Icelandic and Viking attitudes toward morals and polity. See Peter Foote and Davis M. Wilson, The Viking Achievement (London: Sidgwick & Jackson, 1980). Among the Vikings in particular, there was a well- developed view of the limits of sovereignty. Foote and Wilson provide one example of this by drawing on the Chronicle of Dido of St. Quentin (ca. 970-1043). Dido reported that Rollo of Normandy, when asked to kiss the foot of King Charles the Simple (the ruler of France [898-929]), responded by lifting the king's foot to his mouth, thus upending the king flat on his back (Foote and Wilson, The Viking Experience, 79).
    • (1866) Torture , pp. 24-25
    • Lea, H.C.1
  • 12
    • 84874908801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rights to privacy have roots in the vaunted rights of Englishmen, which draw on ancient pagan moral, political, and legal understandings that recognized the individual as having inherent and robust rights against the sovereign. See, for example, Henry Charles Lea, Torture (1866; reprint, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1973), 24-25; and the reports of Tacitus in his Germania. Albeit transformed by later influences, these understandings persisted in English law and framed the pagan Icelandic and Viking attitudes toward morals and polity. See Peter Foote and Davis M. Wilson, The Viking Achievement (London: Sidgwick & Jackson, 1980). Among the Vikings in particular, there was a well- developed view of the limits of sovereignty. Foote and Wilson provide one example of this by drawing on the Chronicle of Dido of St. Quentin (ca. 970-1043). Dido reported that Rollo of Normandy, when asked to kiss the foot of King Charles the Simple (the ruler of France [898-929]), responded by lifting the king's foot to his mouth, thus upending the king flat on his back (Foote and Wilson, The Viking Experience, 79).
    • Germania
    • Tacitus1
  • 13
    • 0013381872 scopus 로고
    • London: Sidgwick & Jackson
    • Rights to privacy have roots in the vaunted rights of Englishmen, which draw on ancient pagan moral, political, and legal understandings that recognized the individual as having inherent and robust rights against the sovereign. See, for example, Henry Charles Lea, Torture (1866; reprint, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1973), 24-25; and the reports of Tacitus in his Germania. Albeit transformed by later influences, these understandings persisted in English law and framed the pagan Icelandic and Viking attitudes toward morals and polity. See Peter Foote and Davis M. Wilson, The Viking Achievement (London: Sidgwick & Jackson, 1980). Among the Vikings in particular, there was a well- developed view of the limits of sovereignty. Foote and Wilson provide one example of this by drawing on the Chronicle of Dido of St. Quentin (ca. 970-1043). Dido reported that Rollo of Normandy, when asked to kiss the foot of King Charles the Simple (the ruler of France [898-929]), responded by lifting the king's foot to his mouth, thus upending the king flat on his back (Foote and Wilson, The Viking Experience, 79).
    • (1980) The Viking Achievement
    • Foote, P.1    Wilson, D.M.2
  • 14
    • 0041420685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rights to privacy have roots in the vaunted rights of Englishmen, which draw on ancient pagan moral, political, and legal understandings that recognized the individual as having inherent and robust rights against the sovereign. See, for example, Henry Charles Lea, Torture (1866; reprint, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1973), 24-25; and the reports of Tacitus in his Germania. Albeit transformed by later influences, these understandings persisted in English law and framed the pagan Icelandic and Viking attitudes toward morals and polity. See Peter Foote and Davis M. Wilson, The Viking Achievement (London: Sidgwick & Jackson, 1980). Among the Vikings in particular, there was a well-developed view of the limits of sovereignty. Foote and Wilson provide one example of this by drawing on the Chronicle of Dido of St. Quentin (ca. 970-1043). Dido reported that Rollo of Normandy, when asked to kiss the foot of King Charles the Simple (the ruler of France [898-929]), responded by lifting the king's foot to his mouth, thus upending the king flat on his back (Foote and Wilson, The Viking Experience, 79).
    • The Viking Experience , pp. 79
    • Foote1    Wilson2
  • 15
    • 0037600028 scopus 로고
    • Privacy as an Aspect of Human Dignity
    • Ferdinand David Schoeman, ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Edward J. Bloustein, "Privacy as an Aspect of Human Dignity," in Ferdinand David Schoeman, ed., Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy: An Anthology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 158. The language of rights to privacy was influenced by Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis; see their "The Right to Privacy," Harvard Law Review 4, no. 5 (December 1890): 193-220.
    • (1984) Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy: An Anthology , pp. 158
    • Bloustein, E.J.1
  • 16
    • 0000320829 scopus 로고
    • The Right to Privacy
    • December
    • Edward J. Bloustein, "Privacy as an Aspect of Human Dignity," in Ferdinand David Schoeman, ed., Philosophical Dimensions of Privacy: An Anthology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 158. The language of rights to privacy was influenced by Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis; see their "The Right to Privacy," Harvard Law Review 4, no. 5 (December 1890): 193-220.
    • (1890) Harvard Law Review , vol.4 , Issue.5 , pp. 193-220
    • Warren, S.D.1    Brandeis, L.D.2
  • 17
    • 0042423057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The challenge is not simply to know truly what is right, good, just, and virtuous, but also to know truly when we know this.
  • 18
    • 0004249638 scopus 로고
    • trans. G. Bennington and B. Massumi Manchester: Manchester University Press
    • Here I borrow an image from Jean-François Lyotard. "In contemporary society and culture - postindustrial society, postmodern culture - the question of the legitimization of knowledge is formulated in different terms. The grand narrative has lost its credibility, regardless of what mode of unification it uses, regardless of whether it is a speculative narrative or a narrative of emancipation" (Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, trans. G. Bennington and B. Massumi [Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1984], 37). It is not simply that a universal moral narrative has de facto lost its credibility. More importantly, its credibility cannot be restored in a principled fashion. The moral diversity of postmodernity is not just a socio-moral fact of the matter, but a condition expressing the limits of secular moral knowledge. This recognition, it should be noted, involves a certain epistemological skepticism, but not a metaphysical skepticism. It is not a denial of an ultimate moral truth that should command the assent of all. It involves only a recognition that this truth cannot be conclusively established by sound rational argument.
    • (1984) The Postmodern Condition , pp. 37
    • Lyotard, J.-F.1
  • 19
    • 0042423058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The qualification "secular" is attached to "moral" in order to indicate that there are religious moral insights unavailable to general moral reflection. The author of this essay is, after all, an Orthodox Christian.
  • 20
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • There is a genre of liberalism that, by affirming a very particular understanding of liberty, does not allow persons consensually to choose their own understandings of how freely to relate to each other. For example, John Rawls argues that children should be required to have knowledge of their constitutional and civic rights and that "their education should also prepare them to be fully cooperating members of society and enable them to be self-supporting; it should also encourage the political virtues so that they want to honor the fair terms of social cooperation in their relations with the rest of society" (Rawls, Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1993], 199). Unlike libertarian liberals, cosmopolitan liberals or social democrats in fact affirm a "thick" understanding of community as the foundation of societal relationships. While affirming liberty, they give it a "thick" content which amounts to requiring a particular form of communal life. It is with regard to education or indoctrination about particular understandings of virtues and vices that the most significant conflicts may arise. I have examined the development of the liberal cosmopolitan ethos and its antilibertarian character in my The Foundations of Bioethics, chap. 3.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 199
    • Rawls1
  • 21
    • 0003667001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • There is a genre of liberalism that, by affirming a very particular understanding of liberty, does not allow persons consensually to choose their own understandings of how freely to relate to each other. For example, John Rawls argues that children should be required to have knowledge of their constitutional and civic rights and that "their education should also prepare them to be fully cooperating members of society and enable them to be self-supporting; it should also encourage the political virtues so that they want to honor the fair terms of social cooperation in their relations with the rest of society" (Rawls, Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1993], 199). Unlike libertarian liberals, cosmopolitan liberals or social democrats in fact affirm a "thick" understanding of community as the foundation of societal relationships. While affirming liberty, they give it a "thick" content which amounts to requiring a particular form of communal life. It is with regard to education or indoctrination about particular understandings of virtues and vices that the most significant conflicts may arise. I have examined the development of the liberal cosmopolitan ethos and its antilibertarian character in my The Foundations of Bioethics, chap. 3.
    • The Foundations of Bioethics
  • 22
    • 84937288609 scopus 로고
    • Personal Rights and Public Space
    • Spring
    • In two articles bearing on issues of privacy, Thomas Nagel warns against the communitarian identification of community and society with a "thick" view of human virtue: "The radical communitarian view that nothing in personal life is beyond the legitimate control of the community if its dominant values are at stake is the main contemporary threat to human rights" (Nagel, "Personal Rights and Public Space," Philosophy and Public Affairs 24, no. 2 [Spring 1995]: 106); "Communitarianism - the ambition of collective self-realization - is one of the most persistent threats to the human spirit" (Nagel, "Concealment and Exposure," Philosophy and Public Affairs 27, no. 1 [Winter 1998]: 29).
    • (1995) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.24 , Issue.2 , pp. 106
    • Nagel1
  • 23
    • 0002863111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Concealment and Exposure
    • Winter
    • In two articles bearing on issues of privacy, Thomas Nagel warns against the communitarian identification of community and society with a "thick" view of human virtue: "The radical communitarian view that nothing in personal life is beyond the legitimate control of the community if its dominant values are at stake is the main contemporary threat to human rights" (Nagel, "Personal Rights and Public Space," Philosophy and Public Affairs 24, no. 2 [Spring 1995]: 106); "Communitarianism - the ambition of collective self-realization - is one of the most persistent threats to the human spirit" (Nagel, "Concealment and Exposure," Philosophy and Public Affairs 27, no. 1 [Winter 1998]: 29).
    • (1998) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.27 , Issue.1 , pp. 29
    • Nagel1
  • 24
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It turns out, mirabile factu, that only that pluralism that is reasonable in social democratic terms is accepted as compatible with a social democratic polity. See, for example, Rawls, Political Liberalism, 36ff.
    • Political Liberalism
    • Rawls1
  • 25
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "A doctrine is fully comprehensive if it covers all recognized values and virtues within one rather precisely articulated system. . . ." (ibid., 152).
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 152
  • 26
    • 0347873666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Idea of Public Reason Revisited
    • Summer
    • John Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," University of Chicago Law Review 64, no. 3 (Summer 1997): 776.
    • (1997) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.64 , Issue.3 , pp. 776
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 29
    • 0007310158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The notion of social democratic reason is introduced in order to establish the bar that Rawls wishes to erect against those, such as libertarians, who may have philosophical accounts denying the moral legitimacy of a social democratic state and who will cooperate with a social democratic state only as a modus vivendi. Rawls, for example, holds that, "[t]o be reasonable, political conceptions must justify only constitutions that satisfy this principle" (Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," 771). That is, political conceptions must involve an understanding of political justice that affirms a social democracy as more than a modus vivendi. Therefore, Rawls holds that "comprehensive doctrines that cannot support such a democratic society are not reasonable" (ibid., 801). The principle that Rawls has in mind is: "Our exercise of political power is proper only when we sincerely believe that the reasons we would offer for our political actions - were we to state them as government officials - are sufficient, and we also reasonably think that other citizens might also reasonably accept those reasons" (ibid., 771). Thus, one would be disbarred from arguing that there are unavoidable limits on the authority of citizens to impose constraints on consensual actions, not to mention limits on the imposition of many forms of taxation. If it were the fact of the matter that most citizens accepted social democratic premises - thus, by consent, licensing interferences with consensual actions - then for Rawls an appeal to step back from such commitments would be illegitimate, even if well-founded in libertarian terms. Libertarians may not "accept a democratic government merely as a modus vivendi" (ibid., 780) with the hope that in the future they will be able to persuade enough citizens to amend the constitution in order to erect libertarian constraints on the actions of the majority.
    • The Idea of Public Reason Revisited , pp. 771
    • Rawls1
  • 30
    • 0007310158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The notion of social democratic reason is introduced in order to establish the bar that Rawls wishes to erect against those, such as libertarians, who may have philosophical accounts denying the moral legitimacy of a social democratic state and who will cooperate with a social democratic state only as a modus vivendi. Rawls, for example, holds that, "[t]o be reasonable, political conceptions must justify only constitutions that satisfy this principle" (Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," 771). That is, political conceptions must involve an understanding of political justice that affirms a social democracy as more than a modus vivendi. Therefore, Rawls holds that "comprehensive doctrines that cannot support such a democratic society are not reasonable" (ibid., 801). The principle that Rawls has in mind is: "Our exercise of political power is proper only when we sincerely believe that the reasons we would offer for our political actions - were we to state them as government officials - are sufficient, and we also reasonably think that other citizens might also reasonably accept those reasons" (ibid., 771). Thus, one would be disbarred from arguing that there are unavoidable limits on the authority of citizens to impose constraints on consensual actions, not to mention limits on the imposition of many forms of taxation. If it were the fact of the matter that most citizens accepted social democratic premises - thus, by consent, licensing interferences with consensual actions - then for Rawls an appeal to step back from such commitments would be illegitimate, even if well-founded in libertarian terms. Libertarians may not "accept a democratic government merely as a modus vivendi" (ibid., 780) with the hope that in the future they will be able to persuade enough citizens to amend the constitution in order to erect libertarian constraints on the actions of the majority.
    • The Idea of Public Reason Revisited , pp. 801
  • 31
    • 0007310158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The notion of social democratic reason is introduced in order to establish the bar that Rawls wishes to erect against those, such as libertarians, who may have philosophical accounts denying the moral legitimacy of a social democratic state and who will cooperate with a social democratic state only as a modus vivendi. Rawls, for example, holds that, "[t]o be reasonable, political conceptions must justify only constitutions that satisfy this principle" (Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," 771). That is, political conceptions must involve an understanding of political justice that affirms a social democracy as more than a modus vivendi. Therefore, Rawls holds that "comprehensive doctrines that cannot support such a democratic society are not reasonable" (ibid., 801). The principle that Rawls has in mind is: "Our exercise of political power is proper only when we sincerely believe that the reasons we would offer for our political actions - were we to state them as government officials - are sufficient, and we also reasonably think that other citizens might also reasonably accept those reasons" (ibid., 771). Thus, one would be disbarred from arguing that there are unavoidable limits on the authority of citizens to impose constraints on consensual actions, not to mention limits on the imposition of many forms of taxation. If it were the fact of the matter that most citizens accepted social democratic premises - thus, by consent, licensing interferences with consensual actions - then for Rawls an appeal to step back from such commitments would be illegitimate, even if well-founded in libertarian terms. Libertarians may not "accept a democratic government merely as a modus vivendi" (ibid., 780) with the hope that in the future they will be able to persuade enough citizens to amend the constitution in order to erect libertarian constraints on the actions of the majority.
    • The Idea of Public Reason Revisited , pp. 771
  • 32
    • 0007310158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The notion of social democratic reason is introduced in order to establish the bar that Rawls wishes to erect against those, such as libertarians, who may have philosophical accounts denying the moral legitimacy of a social democratic state and who will cooperate with a social democratic state only as a modus vivendi. Rawls, for example, holds that, "[t]o be reasonable, political conceptions must justify only constitutions that satisfy this principle" (Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," 771). That is, political conceptions must involve an understanding of political justice that affirms a social democracy as more than a modus vivendi. Therefore, Rawls holds that "comprehensive doctrines that cannot support such a democratic society are not reasonable" (ibid., 801). The principle that Rawls has in mind is: "Our exercise of political power is proper only when we sincerely believe that the reasons we would offer for our political actions - were we to state them as government officials - are sufficient, and we also reasonably think that other citizens might also reasonably accept those reasons" (ibid., 771). Thus, one would be disbarred from arguing that there are unavoidable limits on the authority of citizens to impose constraints on consensual actions, not to mention limits on the imposition of many forms of taxation. If it were the fact of the matter that most citizens accepted social democratic premises - thus, by consent, licensing interferences with consensual actions - then for Rawls an appeal to step back from such commitments would be illegitimate, even if well-founded in libertarian terms. Libertarians may not "accept a democratic government merely as a modus vivendi" (ibid., 780) with the hope that in the future they will be able to persuade enough citizens to amend the constitution in order to erect libertarian constraints on the actions of the majority.
    • The Idea of Public Reason Revisited , pp. 780
  • 45
    • 0003667001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chaps. 2, 3, and 4
    • For a more extensive development of this argument, see Engelhardt, The Foundations of Bioethics, chaps. 2, 3, and 4; see also H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., Bioethics and Secular Humanism (Philadelphia: Trinity Press International, 1991), chap. 5. For an introduction to the issues associated with resolving moral controversies by sound rational argument, see H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., and Arthur Caplan, Scientific Controversies (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
    • The Foundations of Bioethics
    • Engelhardt1
  • 46
    • 0003871933 scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia: Trinity Press International, chap. 5.
    • For a more extensive development of this argument, see Engelhardt, The Foundations of Bioethics, chaps. 2, 3, and 4; see also H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., Bioethics and Secular Humanism (Philadelphia: Trinity Press International, 1991), chap. 5. For an introduction to the issues associated with resolving moral controversies by sound rational argument, see H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., and Arthur Caplan, Scientific Controversies (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
    • (1991) Bioethics and Secular Humanism
    • Tristram Engelhardt H., Jr.1
  • 47
    • 0002248824 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • For a more extensive development of this argument, see Engelhardt, The Foundations of Bioethics, chaps. 2, 3, and 4; see also H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., Bioethics and Secular Humanism (Philadelphia: Trinity Press International, 1991), chap. 5. For an introduction to the issues associated with resolving moral controversies by sound rational argument, see H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., and Arthur Caplan, Scientific Controversies (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
    • (1987) Scientific Controversies
    • Tristram Engelhardt H., Jr.1    Caplan, A.2
  • 48
    • 0041921998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In a prisoner's dilemma, cooperation or coordination allows cooperating individuals to improve their outcome over what they would have obtained had they acted independently. Suppose Bubba and J. R. fall upon the Houston branch of the Yankee Bank of Commerce and are arrested by the police with only circumstantial evidence against them. If both of them hold to their story denying their involvement, they will both go free. However, if the police can get one of the pair to confess in exchange for a reduced sentence, the one who first cooperates still receives a sentence (and the other receives a longer sentence), so both will be worse off. However, if J. R. (but not Bubba) has engaged in the robbery on behalf of the Texas National Liberation Front, J. R. may in fact wish to confess so he can be tried as a martyr. Thus, in this situation, Bubba has no possibility of a successful outcome because whatever choice he makes - silence or confession - he cannot win. In other words, Bubba has no winning strategy. Coordination or cooperation only works when the participants share the same values.
  • 50
    • 0010868622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Warren and Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy," 193. Rights to privacy in English law have roots in ancient Germanic proscriptions of battery and their robust recognition of forbearance rights. See, for example, Katherine Fischer Drew, trans., The Lombard Laws (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1973); and Katherine Fischer Drew, trans., The Burgundian Code (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1972). As already noted, in ancient pagan Germany, legal protections were nested within a general notion of a limited government. See, for example, Lea, Torture, 24-25. These protections have a resonance in the Magna Carta (A.D. 1215), especially in sec. 39. All of this underlies a background of concerns that culminate in claims to rights to privacy.
    • The Right to Privacy , pp. 193
    • Warren1    Brandeis2
  • 51
    • 0041432019 scopus 로고
    • trans., Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
    • Warren and Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy," 193. Rights to privacy in English law have roots in ancient Germanic proscriptions of battery and their robust recognition of forbearance rights. See, for example, Katherine Fischer Drew, trans., The Lombard Laws (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1973); and Katherine Fischer Drew, trans., The Burgundian Code (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1972). As already noted, in ancient pagan Germany, legal protections were nested within a general notion of a limited government. See, for example, Lea, Torture, 24-25. These protections have a resonance in the Magna Carta (A.D. 1215), especially in sec. 39. All of this underlies a background of concerns that culminate in claims to rights to privacy.
    • (1973) The Lombard Laws
    • Fischer Drew, K.1
  • 52
    • 0042423049 scopus 로고
    • trans., Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
    • Warren and Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy," 193. Rights to privacy in English law have roots in ancient Germanic proscriptions of battery and their robust recognition of forbearance rights. See, for example, Katherine Fischer Drew, trans., The Lombard Laws (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1973); and Katherine Fischer Drew, trans., The Burgundian Code (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1972). As already noted, in ancient pagan Germany, legal protections were nested within a general notion of a limited government. See, for example, Lea, Torture, 24-25. These protections have a resonance in the Magna Carta (A.D. 1215), especially in sec. 39. All of this underlies a background of concerns that culminate in claims to rights to privacy.
    • (1972) The Burgundian Code
    • Fischer Drew, K.1
  • 53
    • 79956578987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Warren and Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy," 193. Rights to privacy in English law have roots in ancient Germanic proscriptions of battery and their robust recognition of forbearance rights. See, for example, Katherine Fischer Drew, trans., The Lombard Laws (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1973); and Katherine Fischer Drew, trans., The Burgundian Code (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1972). As already noted, in ancient pagan Germany, legal protections were nested within a general notion of a limited government. See, for example, Lea, Torture, 24-25. These protections have a resonance in the Magna Carta (A.D. 1215), especially in sec. 39. All of this underlies a background of concerns that culminate in claims to rights to privacy.
    • Torture , pp. 24-25
    • Lea1
  • 54
    • 0041420679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438, 478 (1928) (Brandeis, J., dissenting)
    • Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438, 478 (1928) (Brandeis, J., dissenting).
  • 55
    • 0041420675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In re President and Directors of Georgetown College, Inc., 331 F.2d 1000, 1017 (D.C. Cir.) cert. denied, 337 U.S. 978 (1964) (Burger, J., dissenting) (emphasis in original)
    • In re President and Directors of Georgetown College, Inc., 331 F.2d 1000, 1017 (D.C. Cir.) cert. denied, 337 U.S. 978 (1964) (Burger, J., dissenting) (emphasis in original).
  • 56
    • 0042923824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The First Amendment states: "Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the government for a redress of grievances."
  • 57
    • 0041420678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The Fourth Amendment states: "The right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects, against unreasonable searches and seizures, shall not be violated, and no warrants shall issue, but upon probable cause, supported by oath or affirmation, and particularly describing the place to be searched, and the persons or things to be seized."
  • 58
    • 0041921992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The Ninth Amendment states: "The enumeration in the Constitution of certain rights shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people."
  • 59
    • 0003858348 scopus 로고
    • St. Paul, MN: West
    • John E. Nowak, Ronald D. Rotunda, and J. Nelson Young, Constitutional Law, 2d ed. (St. Paul, MN: West, 1983), 1412-14. For an exploration of the development of legal concepts of privacy, see Tom Gerety, "Redefining Privacy," Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 12, no. 2 (Spring 1977): 233-96. See also David M. O'Brien, Privacy, Law, and Public Policy (New York: Praeger, 1979), esp. 177-99.
    • (1983) Constitutional Law, 2d Ed. , pp. 1412-1414
    • Nowak, J.E.1    Rotunda, R.D.2    Nelson Young, J.3
  • 60
    • 0001506713 scopus 로고
    • Redefining Privacy
    • Spring
    • John E. Nowak, Ronald D. Rotunda, and J. Nelson Young, Constitutional Law, 2d ed. (St. Paul, MN: West, 1983), 1412-14. For an exploration of the development of legal concepts of privacy, see Tom Gerety, "Redefining Privacy," Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 12, no. 2 (Spring 1977): 233-96. See also David M. O'Brien, Privacy, Law, and Public Policy (New York: Praeger, 1979), esp. 177-99.
    • (1977) Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review , vol.12 , Issue.2 , pp. 233-296
    • Gerety, T.1
  • 61
    • 84938051947 scopus 로고
    • New York: Praeger
    • John E. Nowak, Ronald D. Rotunda, and J. Nelson Young, Constitutional Law, 2d ed. (St. Paul, MN: West, 1983), 1412-14. For an exploration of the development of legal concepts of privacy, see Tom Gerety, "Redefining Privacy," Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 12, no. 2 (Spring 1977): 233-96. See also David M. O'Brien, Privacy, Law, and Public Policy (New York: Praeger, 1979), esp. 177-99.
    • (1979) Privacy, Law, and Public Policy , pp. 177-199
    • O'Brien, D.M.1
  • 62
    • 0041921996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For example, see Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965) (establishing a constitutional right of married couples to use contraception); Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972) (establishing the right of unmarried individuals to acquire contraceptives); and Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973) (establishing a constitutional right to access to abortion).
  • 63
    • 0042423053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In re Cruzan, 58 LW 4916 (1990)
    • In re Cruzan, 58 LW 4916 (1990).
  • 64
    • 0041420677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. Constitution, amend. 9
    • U.S. Constitution, amend. 9.
  • 65
    • 0041420683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Griswold, 381 U.S. at 488
    • Griswold, 381 U.S. at 488.
  • 67
    • 0042423054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In exploring the lineage of legitimacy, the focus must be on bare consent or permission in order to avoid value-laden construals of legitimacy that seek to disclose unfair imbalances of power or the marks of false consciousness. In the absence of a canonical, content-full moral vision, bare procedure must be central.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.