메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 107, Issue 4, 1997, Pages 584-611

Moral Rules

(1)  Shafer Landau, Russ a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041676759     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233761     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (44)

References (40)
  • 1
    • 0347341606 scopus 로고
    • Principles
    • See R. M. Hare ("Principles," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73 [1972]: 1-18) and Martha Nussbaum (Love's Knowledge [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990], pp. 38-39, 67-68) for instructive remarks on the distinction between generality and universality.
    • (1972) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.73 , pp. 1-18
    • Hare, R.M.1
  • 2
    • 0004258484 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See R. M. Hare ("Principles," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73 [1972]: 1-18) and Martha Nussbaum (Love's Knowledge [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990], pp. 38-39, 67-68) for instructive remarks on the distinction between generality and universality.
    • (1990) Love's Knowledge , pp. 38-39
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 3
    • 85033133061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thus my talk of "moral properties" is intended to be metaphysically neutral. Realists will take such talk literally. For an antirealist, a moral rule is genuine just in case the instantiation of a nonmoral grounding property invariably justifies assent to a particular moral evaluation. Those with antirealist preferences are invited to make the necessary substitution in all that follows.
  • 4
    • 0003052576 scopus 로고
    • How Is Weakness of the Will Possible?
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See Donald Davidson ("How Is Weakness of the Will Possible?" in his Essays on Actions and Events [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980], pp. 21-42) for a criticism of this way of putting the logical form of a prima facie rule. Despite this disagreement, however, we agree on the key issue, namely, that the grounding property in any well-formed prima facie rule must be universally morally relevant.
    • (1980) Essays on Actions and Events , pp. 21-42
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 6
    • 0003696550 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press, chap. 7
    • Though sympathetic with many of their claims, here I disagree with Mark Johnson (Moral Imagination [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993], chap. 7) and Albert Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin (The Abuse of Casuistry [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988], chaps. 1, 2), who seem to assume that practitioners of rule- based ethics must view their enterprise as one of parceling out a thoroughly determinate moral order.
    • (1993) Moral Imagination
    • Johnson, M.1
  • 7
    • 0003726685 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press, chaps. 1, 2
    • Though sympathetic with many of their claims, here I disagree with Mark Johnson (Moral Imagination [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993], chap. 7) and Albert Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin (The Abuse of Casuistry [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988], chaps. 1, 2), who seem to assume that practitioners of rule-based ethics must view their enterprise as one of parceling out a thoroughly determinate moral order.
    • (1988) The Abuse of Casuistry
    • Jonsen, A.1    Toulmin, S.2
  • 8
    • 0009070597 scopus 로고
    • On Moral Properties
    • Jonathan Dancy, "On Moral Properties," Mind 90 (1981): 367-85, esp. pp. 376-77. See also Dancy, "Ethical Particularism and Morally Relevant Properties," Mind 92 (1983): 530-47, esp. pp. 533-34, 541-42, and Moral Reasons (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1993), pp. 92-107.
    • (1981) Mind , vol.90 , pp. 367-385
    • Dancy, J.1
  • 9
    • 0007190918 scopus 로고
    • Ethical Particularism and Morally Relevant Properties
    • Jonathan Dancy, "On Moral Properties," Mind 90 (1981): 367-85, esp. pp. 376-77. See also Dancy, "Ethical Particularism and Morally Relevant Properties," Mind 92 (1983): 530-47, esp. pp. 533-34, 541-42, and Moral Reasons (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1993), pp. 92-107.
    • (1983) Mind , vol.92 , pp. 530-547
    • Dancy1
  • 10
    • 0009070597 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • Jonathan Dancy, "On Moral Properties," Mind 90 (1981): 367-85, esp. pp. 376-77. See also Dancy, "Ethical Particularism and Morally Relevant Properties," Mind 92 (1983): 530-47, esp. pp. 533-34, 541-42, and Moral Reasons (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1993), pp. 92-107.
    • (1993) Moral Reasons , pp. 92-107
  • 11
    • 0004312818 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • David McNaughton, Moral Vision (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988), p. 193.
    • (1988) Moral Vision , pp. 193
    • McNaughton, D.1
  • 12
    • 0004206765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for this strategy
    • See Dancy, Moral Reasons, pp. 60-66, for this strategy.
    • Moral Reasons , pp. 60-66
    • Dancy1
  • 14
    • 85033156279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Some may balk at my use of thick concepts to construct counterexamples to the strong particularist thesis. Trepidation may arise from two sources. First, thick concepts have a relatively small set of grounding properties that are definitionally associated with them, and so differ from more general terms of moral appraisal ('right', 'wrong', 'good', 'bad', 'praiseworthy', etc.) that figure in most "fundamental" moral rules. And second, some of the grounding properties that I cite (cruelty, unselfishness) are themselves moral properties, and so cannot be grounding properties in the strict sense. To take these in reverse order: some examples I provide do not employ moral properties as grounding properties, and so escape whatever force this second objection may have. In any event, this second objection misses the mark, because rule-based grounding properties in the strict sense are simply those whose instantiation is invariably relevant to the instantiation of some other property. There is no reason to suppose that moral properties cannot be invariably relevant in this way. If, for instance, cruelty is in every instance a wrong-making feature, then it makes perfect sense to express this fact in a rule (very likely a prima facie one). That the rule relates two moral properties to each other does not make it any less a moral rule. Nor does it matter that many of the examples I supplied rely on grounding properties that have some definitional association with their correlated moral properties. Moral rules exist just in case the instantiation of a moral property is invariably related to that of some other property (or properties). Thick properties seem to me especially good illustrations of this possibility. Though it is admittedly easier to construct rules from thick rather than thin moral properties, the crucial question is whether we can construct them at all; that we can is sufficient to undermine strong particularism.
  • 17
    • 0346080547 scopus 로고
    • Self-Defense and Rights
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Contrast Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Self-Defense and Rights," reprinted in her Rights, Restitution and Risk (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986), pp. 33-48. Thomson seeks to preempt consideration of candidate rules by a set of general arguments against specification. The strongest criticisms are that (i) specified rules fail to be appropriately morally explanatory; (ii) compensatory claims cannot be justified by means of such rules; (iii) specified rules yield a convoluted moral epistemology; (iv) specification entails an odd moral ontology. I defend specificationism against each of these criticisms in "Specifying Absolute Rights."
    • (1986) Rights, Restitution and Risk , pp. 33-48
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 18
    • 84923223030 scopus 로고
    • The Additive Fallacy
    • Shelly Kagan appreciates the force of the relevant generalist intuition here, all the while remaining suspicious of what I am calling the delimiting thesis. For a fine, complementary discussion of many of the issues I raise in this article, see Kagan, "The Additive Fallacy," Ethics 99 (1988): 5-31.
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.99 , pp. 5-31
    • Kagan1
  • 19
    • 85033136143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • No commitment to realism or other forms of objectivism is intended by the reference to brute facts. I mean all references to such facts to be construed according to the reader's metaphysical preferences.
  • 20
    • 0039141809 scopus 로고
    • Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer
    • For (i), see Roderick Firth, "Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12 (1952): 317-45; and Thomas Carson, The Status of Morality (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1984). For (ii), see Thomas Scanlon, "Contractualism and Utilitarianism," in Utilitarianism and Beyond, ed. Bernard Williams and Amartya Sen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 103-28. For (iii), see James Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985).
    • (1952) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.12 , pp. 317-345
    • Firth, R.1
  • 21
    • 0347971861 scopus 로고
    • Dordrecht: Reidel
    • For (i), see Roderick Firth, "Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12 (1952): 317-45; and Thomas Carson, The Status of Morality (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1984). For (ii), see Thomas Scanlon, "Contractualism and Utilitarianism," in Utilitarianism and Beyond, ed. Bernard Williams and Amartya Sen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 103-28. For (iii), see James Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985).
    • (1984) The Status of Morality
    • Carson, T.1
  • 22
    • 0002000290 scopus 로고
    • Contractualism and Utilitarianism
    • ed. Bernard Williams and Amartya Sen Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For (i), see Roderick Firth, "Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12 (1952): 317-45; and Thomas Carson, The Status of Morality (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1984). For (ii), see Thomas Scanlon, "Contractualism and Utilitarianism," in Utilitarianism and Beyond, ed. Bernard Williams and Amartya Sen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 103-28. For (iii), see James Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985).
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and Beyond , pp. 103-128
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 23
    • 0004293486 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For (i), see Roderick Firth, "Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12 (1952): 317-45; and Thomas Carson, The Status of Morality (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1984). For (ii), see Thomas Scanlon, "Contractualism and Utilitarianism," in Utilitarianism and Beyond, ed. Bernard Williams and Amartya Sen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 103-28. For (iii), see James Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985).
    • (1985) Well-Being
    • Griffin, J.1
  • 24
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), "Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory," Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 515-72, and Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); Scanlon.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 25
    • 0001501318 scopus 로고
    • Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), "Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory," Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 515-72, and Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); Scanlon.
    • (1980) Journal of Philosophy , vol.77 , pp. 515-572
  • 26
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press, Scanlon
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), "Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory," Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 515-72, and Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); Scanlon.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
  • 27
    • 85033153179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Firth; and Griffin
    • Firth; and Griffin.
  • 29
    • 85033136467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Not that providing definitional criteria is any guarantee that underspecificity will be eliminated. Though we can define 'bravery', for instance, this isn't sufficient to fix everything that belongs within and without the set of brave things. One is brave if and only if one (i) faces significant danger, (ii) appreciates the nature of the threatened harm, and (iii) stands fast before it, (iv) provided the danger is not too great. But what's to count as "significant," as "too great" - even as "standing fast" - is not itself determined by the rule. Nor is it given by a further set of rules. (What would such rules look like?) These notions, crucial to an understanding of bravery, are themselves underspecific. To know whether someone is brave, or some consequences catastrophic, we need to exercise a kind of judgment that is something very different from trying to apply rules to cases.
  • 30
    • 0004228561 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • If failure to obey an absolute rule is always wrong, and absolute rules can conflict, then genuinely tragic cases of moral dilemma may arise. To avoid this possibility, absolutists need to show either that (i) no such conflict can arise, or (ii) violation of an absolute rule is sometimes permissible. This last has been thought implausible, and so we have a ready explanation of the absolutists' desire to avoid conflict among their favored rules. This explanation forces a particular reading of what it is for a rule to be maximally stringent. This notion is ambiguous between (1) never overridden and (2) always overriding. The stronger (2) is necessary if absolute rules are to fix moral verdicts. Option (1) would allow conflict among rules that would yield moral dilemma. (Walter Sinott-Armstrong [Moral Dilemmas (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988)], seeking to defend the existence of moral dilemmas, endorses [1] but not [2].) To serve a fixing role, the presence of a grounding property in such a rule must be determinative of a verdict. If (1) alone is the proper reading of maximal stringency, then so-called absolute rules can conflict and will no longer be always determinative. Only by thinking of absolute rules as never overridden and always overriding will one ensure a fixing role for such rules, by eliminating the prospects of conflict.
    • (1988) Moral Dilemmas
    • Sinott-Armstrong, W.1
  • 31
    • 0024732716 scopus 로고
    • Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect
    • The general problem for advocates of double effect is their inability to identify a conceptually coherent account of direct and indirect intention that also bears the moral weight needed to make distinctions among their paradigm cases. The most sophisticated defense of the doctrine is presented by Warren Quinn, "Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect," Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (1989): 334-51. It is ably criticized in a wide-ranging article by Donald Marquis, "Four Versions of Double Effect," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16 (1991): 515-44. A similar problem arises for proponents of the doctrine of doing and allowing. Kant and Mill, and many others following in their footsteps, tried to provide a distinction between perfect and imperfect duties that would be both conceptually plausible and morally significant. But all efforts to define the separate spheres have failed to mark an invariably morally relevant distinction. The standard strategy is to divide requirements into a set of negative and positive ones, elevating the negative to absolute or perfect status, while allowing the positive obligations to be overridable. But no one has provided a conceptually plausible account of the negative and the positive duties that also justifies (i) the assumption that negative requirements cannot conflict, and (ii) the absolute moral priority of negative requirements over positive ones. Quinn ("Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing," Philosophical Review 98 [1989]: 287-312) has provided the most sophisticated defense of the doctrine of doing and allowing. It has been soundly criticized by John M. Fischer and Mark Ravizza, "Quinn on Doing and Allowing," Philosophical Review 101 (1992): 343-52.
    • (1989) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.10 , pp. 334-351
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 32
    • 0026232584 scopus 로고
    • Four Versions of Double Effect
    • The general problem for advocates of double effect is their inability to identify a conceptually coherent account of direct and indirect intention that also bears the moral weight needed to make distinctions among their paradigm cases. The most sophisticated defense of the doctrine is presented by Warren Quinn, "Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect," Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (1989): 334-51. It is ably criticized in a wide-ranging article by Donald Marquis, "Four Versions of Double Effect," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16 (1991): 515-44. A similar problem arises for proponents of the doctrine of doing and allowing. Kant and Mill, and many others following in their footsteps, tried to provide a distinction between perfect and imperfect duties that would be both conceptually plausible and morally significant. But all efforts to define the separate spheres have failed to mark an invariably morally relevant distinction. The standard strategy is to divide requirements into a set of negative and positive ones, elevating the negative to absolute or perfect status, while allowing the positive obligations to be overridable. But no one has provided a conceptually plausible account of the negative and the positive duties that also justifies (i) the assumption that negative requirements cannot conflict, and (ii) the absolute moral priority of negative requirements over positive ones. Quinn ("Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing," Philosophical Review 98 [1989]: 287-312) has provided the most sophisticated defense of the doctrine of doing and allowing. It has been soundly criticized by John M. Fischer and Mark Ravizza, "Quinn on Doing and Allowing," Philosophical Review 101 (1992): 343-52.
    • (1991) Journal of Medicine and Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 515-544
    • Marquis, D.1
  • 33
    • 0039757888 scopus 로고
    • Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing
    • The general problem for advocates of double effect is their inability to identify a conceptually coherent account of direct and indirect intention that also bears the moral weight needed to make distinctions among their paradigm cases. The most sophisticated defense of the doctrine is presented by Warren Quinn, "Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect," Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (1989): 334-51. It is ably criticized in a wide-ranging article by Donald Marquis, "Four Versions of Double Effect," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16 (1991): 515-44. A similar problem arises for proponents of the doctrine of doing and allowing. Kant and Mill, and many others following in their footsteps, tried to provide a distinction between perfect and imperfect duties that would be both conceptually plausible and morally significant. But all efforts to define the separate spheres have failed to mark an invariably morally relevant distinction. The standard strategy is to divide requirements into a set of negative and positive ones, elevating the negative to absolute or perfect status, while allowing the positive obligations to be overridable. But no one has provided a conceptually plausible account of the negative and the positive duties that also justifies (i) the assumption that negative requirements cannot conflict, and (ii) the absolute moral priority of negative requirements over positive ones. Quinn ("Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing," Philosophical Review 98 [1989]: 287-312) has provided the most sophisticated defense of the doctrine of doing and allowing. It has been soundly criticized by John M. Fischer and Mark Ravizza, "Quinn on Doing and Allowing," Philosophical Review 101 (1992): 343-52.
    • (1989) Philosophical Review , vol.98 , pp. 287-312
    • Quinn1
  • 34
    • 0347341621 scopus 로고
    • Quinn on Doing and Allowing
    • The general problem for advocates of double effect is their inability to identify a conceptually coherent account of direct and indirect intention that also bears the moral weight needed to make distinctions among their paradigm cases. The most sophisticated defense of the doctrine is presented by Warren Quinn, "Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect," Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (1989): 334-51. It is ably criticized in a wide-ranging article by Donald Marquis, "Four Versions of Double Effect," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16 (1991): 515-44. A similar problem arises for proponents of the doctrine of doing and allowing. Kant and Mill, and many others following in their footsteps, tried to provide a distinction between perfect and imperfect duties that would be both conceptually plausible and morally significant. But all efforts to define the separate spheres have failed to mark an invariably morally relevant distinction. The standard strategy is to divide requirements into a set of negative and positive ones, elevating the negative to absolute or perfect status, while allowing the positive obligations to be overridable. But no one has provided a conceptually plausible account of the negative and the positive duties that also justifies (i) the assumption that negative requirements cannot conflict, and (ii) the absolute moral priority of negative requirements over positive ones. Quinn ("Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing," Philosophical Review 98 [1989]: 287-312) has provided the most sophisticated defense of the doctrine of doing and allowing. It has been soundly criticized by John M. Fischer and Mark Ravizza, "Quinn on Doing and Allowing," Philosophical Review 101 (1992): 343-52.
    • (1992) Philosophical Review , vol.101 , pp. 343-352
    • Fischer, J.M.1    Ravizza, M.2
  • 35
    • 85033153382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • They could claim that the properties are always determinative, but I will assume that this is implausible.
  • 36
    • 0039194058 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • I take it that Samuel Scheffler's arguments against agent-centered restrictions imply the unsoundness of all absolutist theories. But I cannot comment here on the success of his arguments. See Scheffler, The Rejection of Consequentialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), and "Agent-Centered Restrictions, Rationality and the Virtues," Mind 94 (1985): 409-19.
    • (1982) The Rejection of Consequentialism
    • Scheffler1
  • 37
    • 0039194058 scopus 로고
    • Agent-Centered Restrictions, Rationality and the Virtues
    • I take it that Samuel Scheffler's arguments against agent-centered restrictions imply the unsoundness of all absolutist theories. But I cannot comment here on the success of his arguments. See Scheffler, The Rejection of Consequentialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), and "Agent-Centered Restrictions, Rationality and the Virtues," Mind 94 (1985): 409-19.
    • (1985) Mind , vol.94 , pp. 409-419
  • 38
    • 85033134029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished manuscript
    • I provide the details of such a theory in "Ethical Intuitionism Redux" (unpublished manuscript).
    • Ethical Intuitionism Redux
  • 39
    • 0346711073 scopus 로고
    • Ethical Disagreement, Ethical Objectivity and Moral Indeterminacy
    • I have offered an account of the nature and sources of moral indeterminacy in "Ethical Disagreement, Ethical Objectivity and Moral Indeterminacy," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (1994): 331-45, and in "Vagueness, Borderline Cases and Moral Realism," American Philosophical Quarterly 32 (1995): 83-96.
    • (1994) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.54 , pp. 331-345
  • 40
    • 0347971862 scopus 로고
    • Vagueness, Borderline Cases and Moral Realism
    • I have offered an account of the nature and sources of moral indeterminacy in "Ethical Disagreement, Ethical Objectivity and Moral Indeterminacy," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (1994): 331-45, and in "Vagueness, Borderline Cases and Moral Realism," American Philosophical Quarterly 32 (1995): 83-96.
    • (1995) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.32 , pp. 83-96


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.