메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 8, Issue 3, 2002, Pages 249-268

The rhetoric of deliberation: Some problems in Kantian theories of deliberative democracy

Author keywords

Aristotle; Deliberative democracy; Emotion; Kant; Rhetoric; Testimony

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041655145     PISSN: 13564765     EISSN: 15728692     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/A:1020899224058     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (72)

References (90)
  • 1
    • 0003852332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S. Benhabib, ed., Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • S. Benhabib, ed., Democracy and Difference (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996);
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference
  • 3
    • 0002161865 scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy
    • A. Hamlin and P. Pettit, eds, Oxford: Blackwell
    • J. Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy", in A. Hamlin and P. Pettit, eds, The Good Polity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989), 17-34;
    • (1989) The Good Polity , pp. 17-34
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 5
    • 0000454866 scopus 로고
    • The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political Theory
    • J. Elster and A. Holland, eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • J. Elster, "The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political Theory", in J. Elster and A. Holland, eds, Foundations of Social Choice Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 103-32;
    • (1986) Foundations of Social Choice Theory , pp. 103-132
    • Elster, J.1
  • 6
    • 0003903245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • J. Elster, ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • J. Elster, ed., Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998);
    • (1998) Deliberative Democracy
  • 9
    • 84972609043 scopus 로고
    • On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation
    • B. Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation", Political Theory 15 (1987), 338-68;
    • (1987) Political Theory , vol.15 , pp. 338-368
    • Manin, B.1
  • 10
    • 0002959322 scopus 로고
    • Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice
    • D. Miller, "Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice", Political Studies 40 (1992), 54-67.
    • (1992) Political Studies , vol.40 , pp. 54-67
    • Miller, D.1
  • 11
    • 0002230997 scopus 로고
    • The Citizens' Jury as Model of Public Participation: A Critical Evaluation
    • O. Renn, T. Webler and P. Wiedemann, eds, Dordrecht: Kluwer
    • For useful recent discussions see A. Armour, "The Citizens' Jury as Model of Public Participation: A Critical Evaluation", in O. Renn, T. Webler and P. Wiedemann, eds, Fairness and Competence in Citizen Participation (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995), 175-88;
    • (1995) Fairness and Competence in Citizen Participation , pp. 175-188
    • Armour, A.1
  • 13
    • 0002282767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Environmental Valuations, Deliberative Democracy and Public Decision-Making Institutions
    • J. Foster, ed., London: Routledge
    • ; M. Jacobs, "Environmental Valuations, Deliberative Democracy and Public Decision-Making Institutions", in J. Foster, ed., Valuing Nature? (London: Routledge, 1997), 211-31;
    • (1997) Valuing Nature? , pp. 211-231
    • Jacobs, M.1
  • 16
    • 0032917229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy and Environmental Decision-Making
    • K.P. Rippe and P. Schaber, "Democracy and Environmental Decision-Making", Environmental Values 8 (1999), 75-88.
    • (1999) Environmental Values , vol.8 , pp. 75-88
    • Rippe, K.P.1    Schaber, P.2
  • 19
    • 0003001215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An Answer to the Question: 'What is Enlightenment?
    • H. Reiss, ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • I. Kant, "An Answer to the Question: 'What is Enlightenment?'", in H. Reiss, ed., Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 54-5.
    • (1991) Political Writings , pp. 54-55
    • Kant, I.1
  • 20
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. N. Kemp Smith London: Macmillan, A738/B766
    • Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1933), A738/B766.
    • (1933) Critique of Pure Reason
    • Kant1
  • 24
    • 52649168357 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Common Saying: 'This May be True in Theory, but it does not Apply in Practice'
    • Reiss, ed.
    • "For a concept of the understanding, which contains the general rule, must be supplemented by an act of judgement whereby the practitioner distinguishes instances where the rule applies from those where it does not. And since rules cannot be in turn provided on every occasion to direct the judgement in subsuming each instance under a previous rule (for that would involve an infinite regress), theoreticians will be found who can never in all their lives become practical, since they lack judgement." - Kant, "On the Common Saying: 'This May be True in Theory, but it does not Apply in Practice'", in H. Reiss, ed., op cit.
    • Op Cit.
    • Kant1
  • 26
    • 0004118035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. W. Pluhar Indianapolis: Hackett
    • Kant, Critique of Judgement, trans. W. Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987), 293-4.
    • (1987) Critique of Judgement , pp. 293-294
    • Kant1
  • 27
    • 0004118035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critique of Judgement
    • Kant, Critique of Judgement, Critique of Judgement, op. cit., 294-5;
    • Critique of Judgement , pp. 294-295
    • Kant1
  • 30
    • 0008709278 scopus 로고
    • trans. D. Zeyl Indianapolis: Hackett
    • Plato, Gorgias, trans. D. Zeyl (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987), 454e.
    • (1987) Gorgias
    • Plato1
  • 33
    • 0002247751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy
    • S. Benhabib, ed., Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • In the same tradition, see also the criticisms of Young's defence of rhetoric in public communication in S. Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy", in S. Benhabib, ed., Democracy and Difference (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94, p. 92ff.
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference , pp. 67-94
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 34
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • J. Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), 220.
    • (1996) Political Liberalism , pp. 220
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 36
    • 0011273226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans R. McKirahan Indianapolis: Hackett
    • translation from P. Curd, A Presocratics Reader, trans R. McKirahan (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996), 376-7.
    • (1996) A Presocratics Reader , pp. 376-377
    • Curd, P.1
  • 39
    • 52649099486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against Reductionist Explanations of Human Behaviour: Rational Choice and the Unified Social Science
    • "Against Reductionist Explanations of Human Behaviour: Rational Choice and the Unified Social Science", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume LXXII (1998), 173-88.
    • (1998) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume , vol.72 , pp. 173-188
  • 40
    • 0002509101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric, Science and Philosophy
    • I discuss these views in O'Neill, "Rhetoric, Science and Philosophy", Philosophy of the Social Sciences 28 (1998), 205-25
    • (1998) Philosophy of the Social Sciences , vol.28 , pp. 205-225
    • O'Neill1
  • 42
    • 0346810770 scopus 로고
    • I gotta use words when I talk to you
    • O'Neill, "I gotta use words when I talk to you", History of Human Sciences 8 (1995), 99-106.
    • (1995) History of Human Sciences , vol.8 , pp. 99-106
    • O'Neill1
  • 43
    • 0000365342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy
    • S. Benhabib, ed.
    • Young's defence of rhetoric, storytelling and greeting in public discourse is open to being read in this way - I. Young, "Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy", in S. Benhabib, ed., ", History of Human Sciences op. cit., 120-35.
    • History of Human Sciences , pp. 120-135
    • Young, I.1
  • 45
    • 0041073778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. W. Roberts Oxford: Clarendon, Book 1.2
    • Aristotle, Rhetoric, trans. W. Roberts (Oxford: Clarendon, 1946), Book 1.2.
    • (1946) Rhetoric
    • Aristotle1
  • 49
    • 0003001215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An Answer to the Question: 'What is Enlightenment?
    • Kant, "An Answer to the Question: 'What is Enlightenment?Rhetoric, '", op. cit., 54.
    • Rhetoric , pp. 54
    • Kant1
  • 50
    • 0004163779 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper and Row
    • A classic statement of what I describe as the Kantian position is offered by Wolff, in his In Defense of Anarchism (New York: Harper and Row, 1970), 13-14:
    • (1970) Defense of Anarchism , pp. 13-14
    • Wolff1
  • 51
    • 0003758126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit., ch. 7
    • The responsible man is not capricious or anarchic, for he does acknowledge himself bound by moral constraints. But he insists that he alone is the judge of those constraints. He may listen to the advice of others, but he makes it his own by determining for himself whether it is good advice. He may learn from others his moral obligations, but only in the sense that a mathematician learns from other mathematicians - namely by hearing from them arguments whose validity he recognizes even though he did not think of them himself. He does not learn in the sense that one learns from an explorer, by accepting as true his accounts of things one cannot see for oneself. Since the responsible man arrives at moral decisions which he expresses to himself in the form of imperatives, we may say that he gives laws to himself, or he is self-legislating. In short, he is autonomous. I criticise this view of the autonomous thinker at length in O'Neill, The Market: Ethics, Information and Politics, op. cit., ch. 7.
    • The Market: Ethics, Information and Politics
    • O'Neill1
  • 52
    • 0004118035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit.
    • How far Kant is himself a Kantian in this sense is, I think, a moot question. Unlike Wolff, Kant does recognise the fact that much of our belief is founded upon testimony and hence relies upon faith in others (Kant, Critique of Judgement, op. cit., 468-9).
    • Critique of Judgement , pp. 468-469
    • Kant1
  • 53
    • 0004118035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit.
    • However, his writings on enlightenment do tend to assume epistemic self-sufficiency as a condition of intellectual autonomy. It is also the case that Kant's positive remarks on testimony suggest that he takes individual observation to have epistemic priority over testimony - we are justified in trusting testimony since "for one of those witnesses it was after all his own experience" (Kant, Critique of Judgement, op. cit., 469).
    • Critique of Judgement , pp. 469
    • Kant1
  • 54
    • 0004121811 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon, chs. 1, 4 and passim
    • For critical discussion of this form of individualism, see A. Coady, Testimony (Oxford: Clarendon, 1992), chs. 1, 4 and passim.
    • (1992) Testimony
    • Coady, A.1
  • 56
    • 0041073778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit., 1356a
    • Aristotle, Rhetoric, op. cit., 1356a 1-20.
    • Rhetoric , pp. 1-20
    • Aristotle1
  • 57
    • 0342970524 scopus 로고
    • trans. W. Pickard-Cambridge Oxford: Oxford University Press, Book I, ch. 1
    • Aristotle, Topics, trans. W. Pickard-Cambridge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1928), Book I, ch. 1.
    • (1928) Topics
    • Aristotle1
  • 58
    • 0003986649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. T. Irwin Indianapolis: Hackett, Book I, ch. 3
    • Nicomachean Ethics, trans. T. Irwin (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1985), Book I, ch. 3.
    • (1985) Nicomachean Ethics
  • 59
    • 23944506795 scopus 로고
    • Enthymeme: Aristotle on the Logic of Persuasion
    • D. Furley and A. Nehamas, eds, Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • M. Burnyeat, "Enthymeme: Aristotle on the Logic of Persuasion", in D. Furley and A. Nehamas, eds, Philosophy and Rhetoric: Essays on Aristotle's Rhetoric (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), 3-56.
    • (1994) Philosophy and Rhetoric: Essays on Aristotle's Rhetoric , pp. 3-56
    • Burnyeat, M.1
  • 61
    • 0346593305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit., Book I ch. 4
    • Aristotle, Topics, op. cit., Book I ch. 4.
    • Topics
    • Aristotle1
  • 62
    • 0004158981 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1908), 3.1.
    • (1908) Metaphysics
    • Aristotle1
  • 66
    • 84937289924 scopus 로고
    • Cordelia's Love: Credibility and the Social Studies of Science
    • S. Shapin, "Cordelia's Love: Credibility and the Social Studies of Science", Perspectives on Science 3 (1995) 255-75, pp. 255-6;
    • (1995) Perspectives on Science , vol.3 , pp. 255-275
    • Shapin, S.1
  • 67
  • 68
    • 0001817653 scopus 로고
    • Relativism, Rationalism and the Sociology of Knowledge
    • M. Hollis, ed., Oxford: Blackwell
    • I have little quarrel with some of the more carefully stated claims of Barnes and Bloor: "[O]ur equivalence postulate is that all beliefs are on par with one another with respect to the causes of their credibility. It is not that all beliefs are equally true or false, but that regardless of truth and falsity the fact of their credibility is to be seen as equally problematic." - B. Barnes and D. Bloor, "Relativism, Rationalism and the Sociology of Knowledge", in M. Hollis, ed., Rationality and Relativism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1982), 21-47, p. 23. I reject the claim that credibility is purely a matter of sociology.
    • (1982) Rationality and Relativism , pp. 21-47
    • Barnes, B.1    Bloor, D.2
  • 69
    • 0003757606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit., is quite consistent with the position developed here
    • Likewise, much in Shapin's A Social History of Truth, op. cit., is quite consistent with the position developed here.
    • A Social History of Truth
    • Shapin1
  • 70
    • 0032012342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Epistemology of Testimony
    • My main disagreement is with the book title and the justification offered for it in chapter one: the book is a social history of credibility. For an excellent discussion of the issues of realism and relativism in Shapin's book see P. Lipton, "The Epistemology of Testimony", Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29 (1998), 1-31.
    • (1998) Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , vol.29 , pp. 1-31
    • Lipton, P.1
  • 71
    • 52649161317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cordelia's Love: Credibility and the Social Studies of Science
    • Shapin, "Cordelia's Love: Credibility and the Social Studies of Science", Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ", op. cit., 257.
    • Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , pp. 257
    • Shapin1
  • 72
    • 0003757606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit.
    • For a discussion of the issues involved here see the last chapter of Shapin, A Social History of Truth, op. cit..
    • A Social History of Truth
    • Shapin1
  • 75
    • 0002250656 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press, IV ch. 13 paragraph 29
    • See for example Augustine, On Christian Doctrine (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952), IV ch. 13 paragraph 29.
    • (1952) On Christian Doctrine
    • Augustine1
  • 77
    • 0002341908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • for a discussion see Sherman, Making a Necessity of Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 178-9 and passim.
    • (1997) Making a Necessity of Virtue , pp. 178-179
    • Sherman1
  • 78
    • 52649101995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit., Book ii ch. 2 1378a and ch 8 1885b
    • Aristotle, Rhetoric, op. cit., Book ii ch. 2 1378a 31-3 and ch 8 1885b 12-5.
    • Rhetoric , pp. 31-33
    • Aristotle1
  • 79
    • 0003986649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit., book II ch. 6 1106b
    • Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, op. cit., book II ch. 6 1106b 18-23.
    • Nicomachean Ethics , pp. 18-23
    • Aristotle1
  • 83
    • 52649132365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cantona and Aquinas on Good and Evil
    • O'Neill, "Cantona and Aquinas on Good and Evil", Journal of Applied Philosophy 14 (1997), 97-106.
    • (1997) Journal of Applied Philosophy , vol.14 , pp. 97-106
    • O'Neill1
  • 84
    • 84905761680 scopus 로고
    • On Anger
    • J. Cooper and J. Procope, eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Seneca, "On Anger", in J. Cooper and J. Procope, eds, Seneca: Moral and Political Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
    • (1995) Seneca: Moral and Political Essays
    • Seneca1
  • 85
    • 0003593142 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press, ch. 11
    • For a discussion see M. Nussbaum, The Therapy of Desire (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), ch. 11.
    • (1994) The Therapy of Desire
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 86
    • 0011005574 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth: Penguin
    • However, Seneca's view of the role of emotion in rhetoric is complex. He defends what might be called a two-audience view - that there is the unadorned language of truth that the wise talk to each other, and the rhetorical language suitable for the masses: "[L]anguage . . . which devotes its attention to truth ought to be plain and unadorned. Popular style has nothing to do with truth. Its object is to sway a mass audience, to carry away unpracticed ears by the force of its onslaught. . . ." - Seneca, Letters from a Stoic (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1969), 83.
    • (1969) Letters from a Stoic , pp. 83
    • Seneca1
  • 87
    • 0346810772 scopus 로고
    • The Decisive Treatise Determining the Nature of the Connection between Religion and Philosophy
    • A. Hyman and J. Walsh, eds, Indianapolis: Hackett, ch. 1 and ch. 3, 301 and 311
    • This two-audience view is popular in the history of rhetoric. It is defended for example by Averroes, for whom the division of labour between logic and rhetoric is related to their respective audiences: logic addresses those educated in the arts of demonstrative argument, rhetoric those who lack either the natural ability or the time to learn them - Averroes, The Decisive Treatise Determining the Nature of the Connection between Religion and Philosophy, in A. Hyman and J. Walsh, eds, Philosophy in the Middle Ages (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1973), ch. 1 and ch. 3, 301 and 311.
    • (1973) Philosophy in the middle Ages
    • Averroes1
  • 88
    • 0003553033 scopus 로고
    • P. Nidditch, ed. Oxford: Clarendon, Book III ch. X, paragraph 34
    • Locke also defends it: see An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, P. Nidditch, ed. (Oxford: Clarendon, 1975), Book III ch. X, paragraph 34, 508.
    • (1975) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding , pp. 508
  • 89
    • 52649148614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Anger
    • II.17
    • Given this view, Seneca's concern with the role of emotions in rhetoric is more to do with its effect on the speaker than on the audience. He allows the rhetorician to feign emotions such as anger in oratory in order to move others, but not to be himself moved by them - Seneca, "On Anger", An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, op. cit., II. 17.
    • An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
    • Seneca1
  • 90
    • 52649141619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This paper was written with the support of a grant from the Leverhulme Trust. Earlier versions of the paper were read to a symposium on Beyond Cost-Benefit Analysis: Deliberation, Judgement and Public Policy, at the University of Zurich and conferences on Environmental Justice, Global Ethics for the 21st Century (University of Melbourne) and on Kantian Approaches to Applied Ethics (University of Central Lancashire): my thanks for comments made on those occasions. My special thanks to Bob Brecher, Graeme Chesters, John Dryzek, Alan Holland, Tom Regan and Peter Schaber for their comments.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.