메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 22, Issue 2, 2000, Pages 133-148

Beyond sax and welfare interests: A case for environmental rights

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041417982     PISSN: 01634275     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/enviroethics200022231     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (15)

References (51)
  • 1
    • 7444220433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • While I recognize that air, water, and soil can be further reduced to constituent elements (and are thus not the most basic or fundamental), because I am not a scientist I restrict my discussion to the environmental rights as stated. Also, I recognize that what constitutes "clean" air, water, and soil can be compromised by earthquakes, volcanoes, etc. However, I am interested in the ways that these may be compromised by human activity. While the tolerance for pollutants in air, water, and soil varies, I am interested in the level that children, the elderly, sick people, and certain indicator organisms in various ecosystems can tolerate, for these are the minimum standards and are informative in assessing the integrity and sustainability of the ecosystem, as well as sustainability of all that depends upon the ecosystem.
  • 9
    • 0040380306 scopus 로고
    • Imposing Risks
    • ed. William Parent (Cambridge: Harvard University Press)
    • Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Imposing Risks," in Rights, Restitution, & Risk, ed. William Parent (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986), pp. 173-91.
    • (1986) Rights, Restitution, & Risk , pp. 173-191
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 11
    • 0021440678 scopus 로고
    • Environmental Pollution and the Threshold of Harm
    • June
    • See Joel Feinberg, "Environmental Pollution and the Threshold of Harm," The Hastings Center Report, June 1984, pp. 27-31. Feinberg again defines harm as crossing a threshold, not the steps that weaken health, and does not address synergistic effects. See also Andrew Kernohan, "Rights against Polluters," in Environmental Ethics 17 (1995): 245-57.
    • (1984) The Hastings Center Report , pp. 27-31
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 12
    • 84937289737 scopus 로고
    • Rights against Polluters
    • See Joel Feinberg, "Environmental Pollution and the Threshold of Harm," The Hastings Center Report, June 1984, pp. 27-31. Feinberg again defines harm as crossing a threshold, not the steps that weaken health, and does not address synergistic effects. See also Andrew Kernohan, "Rights against Polluters," in Environmental Ethics 17 (1995): 245-57.
    • (1995) Environmental Ethics , vol.17 , pp. 245-257
    • Kernohan, A.1
  • 15
    • 0004247732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shue also includes the right to physical security as a basic right. However, I leave aside this discussion as I am interested in what are the most basic rights, and as Shue points out, people who are healthy can fight back against attackers or flee. In addition, and here he quotes John Stuart Mill's Utilitarianism, the right to physical security is "most indispensable of all necessaries, after physical nutriment." Shue, Basic Rights, p. 182.
    • Utilitarianism
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 16
    • 0003408858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shue also includes the right to physical security as a basic right. However, I leave aside this discussion as I am interested in what are the most basic rights, and as Shue points out, people who are healthy can fight back against attackers or flee. In addition, and here he quotes John Stuart Mill's Utilitarianism, the right to physical security is "most indispensable of all necessaries, after physical nutriment." Shue, Basic Rights, p. 182.
    • Basic Rights , pp. 182
    • Shue1
  • 17
    • 7444242908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By clean soil, I mean uncontaminated soil necessary for sustained production of edible food.
  • 18
    • 7444237333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Clean, fertile soil is soil that can sustain life without harmful effects. Such soil would be without radioactivity (that concentrates in the food chain); without pesticides (such as the Riverside, California pesticide absorption in watermelons that killed people in 1983); and without fungicides (as destroyed the soil in Florida citrus groves); and would not be too saline (as is left by crops grown in soil unsuited to agricultural practices).
  • 19
    • 0003759091 scopus 로고
    • Los Angeles: University of California Press
    • See Daniel Hillel, Out of the Earth: Civilization and the Life of the Soil (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1981). Hillel traces the use of chemical fertilizers in agricultural production and the subsequent soil degradation.
    • (1981) Out of the Earth: Civilization and the Life of the Soil
    • Hillel, D.1
  • 21
    • 0000445855 scopus 로고
    • The Human Right to a Safe Environment: Philosophical Perspectives on Its Scope and Justification
    • James W. Nickel, "The Human Right to a Safe Environment: Philosophical Perspectives on Its Scope and Justification," Yale Journal of International Law 18 (1993): 284.
    • (1993) Yale Journal of International Law , vol.18 , pp. 284
    • Nickel, J.W.1
  • 26
    • 7444247748 scopus 로고
    • The Confusion of Goals and Instruments: The Explicit Consideration of Cost in Setting National Ambient Air Quality Standards
    • ed. Mary Gibson (Totowa: N.J.: Rowman and Allanheld)
    • See also George Eads, "The Confusion of Goals and Instruments: The Explicit Consideration of Cost in Setting National Ambient Air Quality Standards," in To Breathe Freely, ed. Mary Gibson (Totowa: N.J.: Rowman and Allanheld, 1985), pp. 222-32. Eads points out difficulties in determining air quality standards and how significantly costs can increase with small changes in air quality.
    • (1985) To Breathe Freely , pp. 222-232
    • Eads, G.1
  • 27
    • 0003491171 scopus 로고
    • At the Shrine of Our Lady of Fatima or Why Political Questions Are Not All Economic
    • While I acknowledge that I am obviously firmly entrenched (there is little to no option to opt out) in such a market economy, and as a white, middle-class woman I benefit from this system, I nonetheless question my privileges, the privileges of others, and the costs of these privileges to those not similarly privileged, as well as the costs to and destruction of the ecosystem. In addition, I acknowledge the schizophrenic nature of participating in the market economy as a consumer, while simultaneously arguing for an end to its harms, or at least to minimize those harms. For a discussion of this schizophrenic nature, see Mark Sagoff, "At the Shrine of Our Lady of Fatima or Why Political Questions Are Not All Economic," Arizona Law Review 23 (1981): 1283-98.
    • (1981) Arizona Law Review , vol.23 , pp. 1283-1298
    • Sagoff, M.1
  • 28
    • 84937291757 scopus 로고
    • Making Peace with the Earth: Indigenous Agriculture and the Green Revolution
    • See Deane Curtin, "Making Peace with the Earth: Indigenous Agriculture and the Green Revolution," Environmental Ethics 17 (1985): 59-73; and Devon Peña, ed., Chicano Culture, Ecology, Politics (Tucson: University of Arizona Press, 1998).
    • (1985) Environmental Ethics , vol.17 , pp. 59-73
    • Curtin, D.1
  • 29
    • 0008765249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tucson: University of Arizona Press
    • See Deane Curtin, "Making Peace with the Earth: Indigenous Agriculture and the Green Revolution," Environmental Ethics 17 (1985): 59-73; and Devon Peña, ed., Chicano Culture, Ecology, Politics (Tucson: University of Arizona Press, 1998).
    • (1998) Chicano Culture, Ecology, Politics
    • Peña, D.1
  • 32
    • 7444223900 scopus 로고
    • ed. Gertrude Himmelfarb (New York: Penguin Books)
    • John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, ed. Gertrude Himmelfarb (New York: Penguin Books, 1978), pp. 68-69.
    • (1978) On Liberty , pp. 68-69
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 34
    • 0003504091 scopus 로고
    • San Francisco: W. H. Freeman and Company
    • Regarding ecological scarcity, see William Ophuls, Ecology and the Politics of Scarcity (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman and Company, 1977).
    • (1977) Ecology and the Politics of Scarcity
    • Ophuls, W.1
  • 35
    • 0043126703 scopus 로고
    • Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield
    • Carl Wellman, Welfare Rights (Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield, 1982), p. 174.
    • (1982) Welfare Rights , pp. 174
    • Wellman, C.1
  • 36
    • 7444255306 scopus 로고
    • The Principle of Utility and Minimizing Utilitarianism
    • See also Rem Edwards, "The Principle of Utility and Minimizing Utilitarianism," Journal of Value Inquiry 20 (1986): 125-36. Edwards argues that to prevent harm or provide for minimum essentials, it is not only justified to restrict others' liberty, but is "worth the price of negative social enforcement" (p. 132). See also Andrew Kernohan, "Accumulative Harms and the Interpretation of the Harm Principle," Social Theory and Practice 19 (1993): 51-72. Kernohan argues that even on the strictest conception of harm, the Harm Principle should be understood to require interference to prevent harm. Also see Dudley R. Knowles, "A Reformulation of the Harm Principle," Political Theory 6 (May 1978): 233-46 . Knowles argues that our physical security interest is a higher-order interest and the Harm Principle justifies the prohibition of others from jeopardizing this.
    • (1986) Journal of Value Inquiry , vol.20 , pp. 125-136
    • Edwards, R.1
  • 37
    • 85055296856 scopus 로고
    • Accumulative Harms and the Interpretation of the Harm Principle
    • See also Rem Edwards, "The Principle of Utility and Minimizing Utilitarianism," Journal of Value Inquiry 20 (1986): 125-36. Edwards argues that to prevent harm or provide for minimum essentials, it is not only justified to restrict others' liberty, but is "worth the price of negative social enforcement" (p. 132). See also Andrew Kernohan, "Accumulative Harms and the Interpretation of the Harm Principle," Social Theory and Practice 19 (1993): 51-72. Kernohan argues that even on the strictest conception of harm, the Harm Principle should be understood to require interference to prevent harm. Also see Dudley R. Knowles, "A Reformulation of the Harm Principle," Political Theory 6 (May 1978): 233-46 . Knowles argues that our physical security interest is a higher-order interest and the Harm Principle justifies the prohibition of others from jeopardizing this.
    • (1993) Social Theory and Practice , vol.19 , pp. 51-72
    • Kernohan, A.1
  • 38
    • 84972654437 scopus 로고
    • A Reformulation of the Harm Principle
    • May
    • See also Rem Edwards, "The Principle of Utility and Minimizing Utilitarianism," Journal of Value Inquiry 20 (1986): 125-36. Edwards argues that to prevent harm or provide for minimum essentials, it is not only justified to restrict others' liberty, but is "worth the price of negative social enforcement" (p. 132). See also Andrew Kernohan, "Accumulative Harms and the Interpretation of the Harm Principle," Social Theory and Practice 19 (1993): 51-72. Kernohan argues that even on the strictest conception of harm, the Harm Principle should be understood to require interference to prevent harm. Also see Dudley R. Knowles, "A Reformulation of the Harm Principle," Political Theory 6 (May 1978): 233-46 . Knowles argues that our physical security interest is a higher-order interest and the Harm Principle justifies the prohibition of others from jeopardizing this.
    • (1978) Political Theory , vol.6 , pp. 233-246
    • Knowles, D.R.1
  • 39
    • 0003442784 scopus 로고
    • Albany: State University of New York Press
    • Peter S. Wenz, Environmental Justice (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988), p. 105.
    • (1988) Environmental Justice , pp. 105
    • Wenz, P.S.1
  • 41
    • 7444222024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I do not exclude the possibility that there are also nonanthropocentric animal and ecosystem rights. I am very sympathetic with this extension; however, I neither include nor defend this extension here.
  • 42
    • 0342683234 scopus 로고
    • Ethics and Ecology
    • ed. William T. Blackstone (Athens: University of Georgia Press)
    • See William T. Blackstone, "Ethics and Ecology," in Philosophy and Environmental Crisis, ed. William T. Blackstone (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1974). Blackstone argues that no rights are realizable without the right to a livable or decent environment. Much of the rights literature is engaged in defining, defending, and discussing rights that are relevant after environmental rights have been secured. Thus, I am not disputing the rights theorists, but am stepping back to that which I argue is prior, and focusing there.
    • (1974) Philosophy and Environmental Crisis
    • Blackstone, W.T.1
  • 45
    • 7444260451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am assuming that there is a right to life.
  • 46
    • 84861995470 scopus 로고
    • Directions of Justification in the Negative-Positive Duty Debate
    • See H. M. Malm, "Directions of Justification in the Negative-Positive Duty Debate," American Philosophical Quarterly 27, no. 4 (1990): 125-36. Malm provides a clear distinction between negative and positive duties regarding harm, however he concludes that our positive duties to prevent harm are not as strict as our negative duties not to cause harm.
    • (1990) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.27 , Issue.4 , pp. 125-136
    • Malm, H.M.1
  • 47
    • 7444223755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As is widely known, bleaching with chlorine compounds necessarily involves pollution from organochlorines, such as dioxin associated with reproductive disorders, cancer, birth defects, and immune system disorders.
  • 48
    • 7444251293 scopus 로고
    • "Toxic Effects of Pesticides: Experimental and Clinical Data," and "Short- and Long-Term Health Effects of Pesticides: Epidemiological Data,"
    • Geneva: World Health Organization
    • Pesticides do not merely harm target species, they harm and impose risk of harm in a wide and persistent manner. Pesticides disrupt reproductive behavior; cause cancer; cause cell mutations; result in abnormal eggs and young; harm the nervous system and gastrointestinal tract; result in hair loss, kidney and liver problems, neurological problems; and can result in sterility, and hormone imbalances. Pesticides pollute air, water, and soil and it is estimated that 20,000 cases of cancer a year in the United States are caused from pesticide residues. See "Toxic Effects of Pesticides: Experimental and Clinical Data," and "Short- and Long-Term Health Effects of Pesticides: Epidemiological Data," in Public Health Impact of Pesticides (Geneva: World Health Organization, 1990).
    • (1990) Public Health Impact of Pesticides
  • 49
    • 7444231271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am grateful to Peter Wenz for this point.
  • 50
    • 7444239952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am assuming that the government has a duty to protect its citizens from harm, especially harm imposed on citizens.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.