메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 17, Issue 2, 1996, Pages 178-194

Constitutionalism - Medieval and modern: Against neo-figgisite orthodoxy (again)

(1)  Nederman, Cary J a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041115174     PISSN: 0143781X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (23)

References (88)
  • 1
    • 0039674875 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, esp.
    • For some important examples, see The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c.350-c.1450, ed. J.H. Burns (Cambridge, 1988), esp. pp. 650-2; Brian Tierney, Religion, Law, and the Growth of Constitutional Thought, 1150-1650 (Cambridge, 1982); The Cambridge History of Political Thought, 1450-1700, ed. J.H. Burns and Mark Goldie (Cambridge, 1991), esp. pp. 1-6; Antony Black, Political Thought in Europe, 1250-1450 (Cambridge, 1992), esp. p. 191; and Kenneth Pennington, The Prince and the Law, 1200-1600 (Berkeley, 1993).
    • (1988) The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, C.350-C.1450 , pp. 650-652
    • Burns, J.H.1
  • 2
    • 0003924393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • For some important examples, see The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c.350-c.1450, ed. J.H. Burns (Cambridge, 1988), esp. pp. 650-2; Brian Tierney, Religion, Law, and the Growth of Constitutional Thought, 1150-1650 (Cambridge, 1982); The Cambridge History of Political Thought, 1450-1700, ed. J.H. Burns and Mark Goldie (Cambridge, 1991), esp. pp. 1-6; Antony Black, Political Thought in Europe, 1250-1450 (Cambridge, 1992), esp. p. 191; and Kenneth Pennington, The Prince and the Law, 1200-1600 (Berkeley, 1993).
    • (1982) Religion, Law, and the Growth of Constitutional Thought, 1150-1650
    • Tierney, B.1
  • 3
    • 0012440156 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, esp.
    • For some important examples, see The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c.350-c.1450, ed. J.H. Burns (Cambridge, 1988), esp. pp. 650-2; Brian Tierney, Religion, Law, and the Growth of Constitutional Thought, 1150-1650 (Cambridge, 1982); The Cambridge History of Political Thought, 1450-1700, ed. J.H. Burns and Mark Goldie (Cambridge, 1991), esp. pp. 1-6; Antony Black, Political Thought in Europe, 1250-1450 (Cambridge, 1992), esp. p. 191; and Kenneth Pennington, The Prince and the Law, 1200-1600 (Berkeley, 1993).
    • (1991) The Cambridge History of Political Thought, 1450-1700 , pp. 1-6
    • Burns, J.H.1    Goldie, M.2
  • 4
    • 0003570490 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, esp.
    • For some important examples, see The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c.350-c.1450, ed. J.H. Burns (Cambridge, 1988), esp. pp. 650-2; Brian Tierney, Religion, Law, and the Growth of Constitutional Thought, 1150-1650 (Cambridge, 1982); The Cambridge History of Political Thought, 1450-1700, ed. J.H. Burns and Mark Goldie (Cambridge, 1991), esp. pp. 1-6; Antony Black, Political Thought in Europe, 1250-1450 (Cambridge, 1992), esp. p. 191; and Kenneth Pennington, The Prince and the Law, 1200-1600 (Berkeley, 1993).
    • (1992) Political Thought in Europe, 1250-1450 , pp. 191
    • Black, A.1
  • 5
    • 0009200383 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley
    • For some important examples, see The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c.350-c.1450, ed. J.H. Burns (Cambridge, 1988), esp. pp. 650-2; Brian Tierney, Religion, Law, and the Growth of Constitutional Thought, 1150-1650 (Cambridge, 1982); The Cambridge History of Political Thought, 1450-1700, ed. J.H. Burns and Mark Goldie (Cambridge, 1991), esp. pp. 1-6; Antony Black, Political Thought in Europe, 1250-1450 (Cambridge, 1992), esp. p. 191; and Kenneth Pennington, The Prince and the Law, 1200-1600 (Berkeley, 1993).
    • (1993) The Prince and the Law, 1200-1600
    • Pennington, K.1
  • 6
    • 0039674874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven
    • Francis Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre D'Ailly (New Haven, 1964), pp. 1-7; F. Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divine of Paris', American Historical Review, 75 (1969), pp. 368-86; F. Oakley, 'Celestial Hierarchies Revisited: Walter Ullmann's Vision of Medieval Politics', Past and Present, No. 50 (August 1973), pp. 3-48; F. Oakley, 'Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent in Conciliar Thought from John of Paris to Matthias Ugonius', Speculum, 56 (1981), pp. 786-810.
    • (1964) The Political Thought of Pierre D'Ailly , pp. 1-7
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 7
    • 0000746084 scopus 로고
    • Figgis, Constance, and the divine of Paris
    • Francis Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre D'Ailly (New Haven, 1964), pp. 1-7; F. Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divine of Paris', American Historical Review, 75 (1969), pp. 368-86; F. Oakley, 'Celestial Hierarchies Revisited: Walter Ullmann's Vision of Medieval Politics', Past and Present, No. 50 (August 1973), pp. 3-48; F. Oakley, 'Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent in Conciliar Thought from John of Paris to Matthias Ugonius', Speculum, 56 (1981), pp. 786-810.
    • (1969) American Historical Review , vol.75 , pp. 368-386
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 8
    • 0040860987 scopus 로고
    • Celestial hierarchies revisited: Walter Ullmann's vision of medieval politics
    • August
    • Francis Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre D'Ailly (New Haven, 1964), pp. 1-7; F. Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divine of Paris', American Historical Review, 75 (1969), pp. 368-86; F. Oakley, 'Celestial Hierarchies Revisited: Walter Ullmann's Vision of Medieval Politics', Past and Present, No. 50 (August 1973), pp. 3-48; F. Oakley, 'Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent in Conciliar Thought from John of Paris to Matthias Ugonius', Speculum, 56 (1981), pp. 786-810.
    • (1973) Past and Present, No. 50 , vol.50 , pp. 3-48
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 9
    • 84959661624 scopus 로고
    • Natural law, the corpus mysticum, and consent in conciliar thought from John of Paris to Matthias Ugonius
    • Francis Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre D'Ailly (New Haven, 1964), pp. 1-7; F. Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divine of Paris', American Historical Review, 75 (1969), pp. 368-86; F. Oakley, 'Celestial Hierarchies Revisited: Walter Ullmann's Vision of Medieval Politics', Past and Present, No. 50 (August 1973), pp. 3-48; F. Oakley, 'Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent in Conciliar Thought from John of Paris to Matthias Ugonius', Speculum, 56 (1981), pp. 786-810.
    • (1981) Speculum , vol.56 , pp. 786-810
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 10
    • 0003820778 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • The classic works are Brian Tierney, Foundations of the Conciliar Theory (Cambridge, 1955); and Paul E. Sigmund, Nicholas of Cusa and Medieval Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1963).
    • (1955) Foundations of the Conciliar Theory
    • Tierney, B.1
  • 12
    • 0040266697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the references in note 2, above
    • See the references in note 2, above.
  • 13
    • 0040009078 scopus 로고
    • Conciliarism and constitutionalism: Jean Gerson and medieval political thought
    • Cary J. Nederman, 'Conciliarism and Constitutionalism: Jean Gerson and Medieval Political Thought', History of European Ideas, 12 (1990), pp. 189-209.
    • (1990) History of European Ideas , vol.12 , pp. 189-209
    • Nederman, C.J.1
  • 14
    • 84937288377 scopus 로고
    • Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar theory and constitutionalism: Sed contra
    • Spring
    • Francis Oakley, 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism: Sed Contra', History of Political Thought, 16 (Spring 1995), pp. 1-19.
    • (1995) History of Political Thought , vol.16 , pp. 1-19
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 16
    • 0039674871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism', pp. 10-12. must say that I find disturbing Oakley's willingness to countenance a free-ranging conception of modern constitutionalism, detached from some strong and defensible principles of individual rights, responsive government, and the other factors upon which I insist in my original article (Nederman, 'Conciliarism and Constitutionalism', p. 193). Oakley cites as support the proceedings of a series of American Council of Learned Societies conferences held worldwide, which 'repeatedly challenged the notion of a necessary linkage between constitutionalism and liberal democratic commitments' (p 11). My fear is that such conclusions are the result of either political naïvity or Realpolitik instead of serious theoretical reflection. I am thinking, in particular, of the much-discussed Asian model of constitutionalism in nations such as Singapore, which claim to abide by the rule of law, yet which regard their constitutional practices to be consistent with arrest without warrant, detainment without trial, suppression of political opposition and criticism, and other fundamental legal protections. Oakley may well be right that elements of modern constitutionalism do not fit well with the realities of 'group rights' and multicultural claims. But the answer is not to loosen the definition of modern constitutionalism to the point that it becomes so all-inclusive as to be meaningless; rather, we must consider seriously the benefits and costs of abandoning the modern constitutional paradigm for some other arrangement of political power and rights. It is a difficult decision but one we ultimately cannot avoid as we confront the divide between modernity and post-modernity. Coincidentally, Oakley's own institution, Williams College, is confronting just this conflict at the writing of the present article in July 1995, resulting from its decision to award an honorary doctorate to the Prime Minister of Singapore, Goh Chok Tong, whose administration was described by a 1995 US State Department report as willing 'to restrict human rights when it deemed that necessary in pursuit of its policy goals'.
    • Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism , pp. 10-12
    • Oakley1
  • 17
    • 0040861030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism', pp. 10-12. must say that I find disturbing Oakley's willingness to countenance a free-ranging conception of modern constitutionalism, detached from some strong and defensible principles of individual rights, responsive government, and the other factors upon which I insist in my original article (Nederman, 'Conciliarism and Constitutionalism', p. 193). Oakley cites as support the proceedings of a series of American Council of Learned Societies conferences held worldwide, which 'repeatedly challenged the notion of a necessary linkage between constitutionalism and liberal democratic commitments' (p 11). My fear is that such conclusions are the result of either political naïvity or Realpolitik instead of serious theoretical reflection. I am thinking, in particular, of the much-discussed Asian model of constitutionalism in nations such as Singapore, which claim to abide by the rule of law, yet which regard their constitutional practices to be consistent with arrest without warrant, detainment without trial, suppression of political opposition and criticism, and other fundamental legal protections. Oakley may well be right that elements of modern constitutionalism do not fit well with the realities of 'group rights' and multicultural claims. But the answer is not to loosen the definition of modern constitutionalism to the point that it becomes so all-inclusive as to be meaningless; rather, we must consider seriously the benefits and costs of abandoning the modern constitutional paradigm for some other arrangement of political power and rights. It is a difficult decision but one we ultimately cannot avoid as we confront the divide between modernity and post-modernity. Coincidentally, Oakley's own institution, Williams College, is confronting just this conflict at the writing of the present article in July 1995, resulting from its decision to award an honorary doctorate to the Prime Minister of Singapore, Goh Chok Tong, whose administration was described by a 1995 US State Department report as willing 'to restrict human rights when it deemed that necessary in pursuit of its policy goals'.
    • Conciliarism and Constitutionalism , pp. 193
    • Nederman1
  • 18
    • 84928459780 scopus 로고
    • Sovereignty, war and the corporation: Hegel on the medieval foundations of the modern state
    • For example, C.J. Nederman, 'Sovereignty, War and the Corporation: Hegel on the Medieval Foundations of the Modern State', Journal of Politics, 49 (1987), pp. 499-519; C.J. Nederman, 'The Union of Wisdom and Eloquence Before the Renaissance: The Ciceronian Orator in Medieval Thought', Journal of Medieval History, 18 (1992), pp 75-95; C.J. Nederman, 'Freedom, Community and Function: Communitarian Lessons of Medieval Political Theory', American Political Science Review, 86 (1992), pp. 977-86; C.J. Nederman, 'Tolerance and Community: A Medieval Communal Functionalist Argument for Toleration', Journal of Politics, 56 (1994), pp. 901-18.
    • (1987) Journal of Politics , vol.49 , pp. 499-519
    • Nederman, C.J.1
  • 19
    • 38249014309 scopus 로고
    • The union of wisdom and eloquence before the renaissance: The Ciceronian orator in medieval thought
    • For example, C.J. Nederman, 'Sovereignty, War and the Corporation: Hegel on the Medieval Foundations of the Modern State', Journal of Politics, 49 (1987), pp. 499-519; C.J. Nederman, 'The Union of Wisdom and Eloquence Before the Renaissance: The Ciceronian Orator in Medieval Thought', Journal of Medieval History, 18 (1992), pp 75-95; C.J. Nederman, 'Freedom, Community and Function: Communitarian Lessons of Medieval Political Theory', American Political Science Review, 86 (1992), pp. 977-86; C.J. Nederman, 'Tolerance and Community: A Medieval Communal Functionalist Argument for Toleration', Journal of Politics, 56 (1994), pp. 901-18.
    • (1992) Journal of Medieval History , vol.18 , pp. 75-95
    • Nederman, C.J.1
  • 20
    • 84971712422 scopus 로고
    • Freedom, community and function: Communitarian lessons of medieval political theory
    • For example, C.J. Nederman, 'Sovereignty, War and the Corporation: Hegel on the Medieval Foundations of the Modern State', Journal of Politics, 49 (1987), pp. 499-519; C.J. Nederman, 'The Union of Wisdom and Eloquence Before the Renaissance: The Ciceronian Orator in Medieval Thought', Journal of Medieval History, 18 (1992), pp 75-95; C.J. Nederman, 'Freedom, Community and Function: Communitarian Lessons of Medieval Political Theory', American Political Science Review, 86 (1992), pp. 977-86; C.J. Nederman, 'Tolerance and Community: A Medieval Communal Functionalist Argument for Toleration', Journal of Politics, 56 (1994), pp. 901-18.
    • (1992) American Political Science Review , vol.86 , pp. 977-986
    • Nederman, C.J.1
  • 21
    • 84972029024 scopus 로고
    • Tolerance and community: A medieval communal functionalist argument for toleration
    • For example, C.J. Nederman, 'Sovereignty, War and the Corporation: Hegel on the Medieval Foundations of the Modern State', Journal of Politics, 49 (1987), pp. 499-519; C.J. Nederman, 'The Union of Wisdom and Eloquence Before the Renaissance: The Ciceronian Orator in Medieval Thought', Journal of Medieval History, 18 (1992), pp 75-95; C.J. Nederman, 'Freedom, Community and Function: Communitarian Lessons of Medieval Political Theory', American Political Science Review, 86 (1992), pp. 977-86; C.J. Nederman, 'Tolerance and Community: A Medieval Communal Functionalist Argument for Toleration', Journal of Politics, 56 (1994), pp. 901-18.
    • (1994) Journal of Politics , vol.56 , pp. 901-918
    • Nederman, C.J.1
  • 26
    • 0007408091 scopus 로고
    • Legitimation by consent: The question of medieval roots
    • Francis Oakley, 'Legitimation by Consent: The Question of Medieval Roots', Viator, 14 (1983), pp. 303-35, esp. pp. 323-35; F. Oakley, 'Disobedience, Consent, Political Obligation: The Witness of Wessel Gansfort (c. 1419-1489)', History of Political Thought, 9 (1988), pp. 211-21; and Oakley, 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism', pp. 12-14.
    • (1983) Viator , vol.14 , pp. 303-335
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 27
    • 84928507613 scopus 로고
    • Disobedience, consent, political obligation: The witness of wessel gansfort (c. 1419-1489)
    • Francis Oakley, 'Legitimation by Consent: The Question of Medieval Roots', Viator, 14 (1983), pp. 303-35, esp. pp. 323-35; F. Oakley, 'Disobedience, Consent, Political Obligation: The Witness of Wessel Gansfort (c. 1419-1489)', History of Political Thought, 9 (1988), pp. 211-21; and Oakley, 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism', pp. 12-14.
    • (1988) History of Political Thought , vol.9 , pp. 211-221
    • Oakley, F.1
  • 28
    • 0039674871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Francis Oakley, 'Legitimation by Consent: The Question of Medieval Roots', Viator, 14 (1983), pp. 303-35, esp. pp. 323-35; F. Oakley, 'Disobedience, Consent, Political Obligation: The Witness of Wessel Gansfort (c. 1419-1489)', History of Political Thought, 9 (1988), pp. 211-21; and Oakley, 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism', pp. 12-14.
    • Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism , pp. 12-14
    • Oakley1
  • 34
    • 0039082742 scopus 로고
    • Political languages in later Medieval Europe
    • ed. D. Wood Oxford
    • This point has lately been stressed by Antony Black in 'Political Languages in Later Medieval Europe', in The Church and Sovereignty, c.590-1918, ed. D. Wood (Oxford, 1991), and in his Political Thought in Europe, pp. 7-11.
    • (1991) The Church and Sovereignty, C.590-1918
    • Black, A.1
  • 35
    • 0040266692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point has lately been stressed by Antony Black in 'Political Languages in Later Medieval Europe', in The Church and Sovereignty, c.590-1918, ed. D. Wood (Oxford, 1991), and in his Political Thought in Europe, pp. 7-11.
    • Political Thought in Europe , pp. 7-11
  • 36
    • 84929066775 scopus 로고
    • Radicals, conservatives and moderates in early modern political thought: A case of Sandwich Island syndrome?
    • Conal Condren, 'Radicals, Conservatives and Moderates in Early Modern Political Thought: A Case of Sandwich Island Syndrome?', History of Political Thought, 10 (1989), pp. 525-42.
    • (1989) History of Political Thought , vol.10 , pp. 525-542
    • Condren, C.1
  • 44
    • 0039082743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley, 'Legitimation by Consent', pp. 321-2; and Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris', pp. 373-6. In 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism', Oakley remarks that seventeenth-century constitutionalists 'turned instinctively' to conciliar writings (p. 13) and that 'about their reading of those conciliarists there was nothing at all anachronistic (p. 14; my emphasis). For a critical view of the 'influence' issue, see Black, 'Political Languages in Later Medieval Europe', pp. 314-15.
    • Legitimation by Consent , pp. 321-322
    • Oakley1
  • 45
    • 0009200403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley, 'Legitimation by Consent', pp. 321-2; and Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris', pp. 373-6. In 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism', Oakley remarks that seventeenth-century constitutionalists 'turned instinctively' to conciliar writings (p. 13) and that 'about their reading of those conciliarists there was nothing at all anachronistic (p. 14; my emphasis). For a critical view of the 'influence' issue, see Black, 'Political Languages in Later Medieval Europe', pp. 314-15.
    • Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris , pp. 373-376
    • Oakley1
  • 46
    • 0039674846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley remarks that seventeenth-century constitutionalists 'turned instinctively' to conciliar writings
    • Oakley, 'Legitimation by Consent', pp. 321-2; and Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris', pp. 373-6. In 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism', Oakley remarks that seventeenth-century constitutionalists 'turned instinctively' to conciliar writings (p. 13) and that 'about their reading of those conciliarists there was nothing at all anachronistic (p. 14; my emphasis). For a critical view of the 'influence' issue, see Black, 'Political Languages in Later Medieval Europe', pp. 314-15.
    • Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism , pp. 13
  • 47
    • 0039674842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley, 'Legitimation by Consent', pp. 321-2; and Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris', pp. 373-6. In 'Nederman, Gerson, Conciliar Theory and Constitutionalism', Oakley remarks that seventeenth-century constitutionalists 'turned instinctively' to conciliar writings (p. 13) and that 'about their reading of those conciliarists there was nothing at all anachronistic (p. 14; my emphasis). For a critical view of the 'influence' issue, see Black, 'Political Languages in Later Medieval Europe', pp. 314-15.
    • Political Languages in Later Medieval Europe , pp. 314-315
    • Black1
  • 48
    • 0004010928 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • See J.G.A. Pocock, The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law (New York, 1967); and Cary J. Nederman, 'Bracton on Kingship First Visited: The Idea of Sovereignty and Bractonian Political Thought in Seventeenth-Century England', Political Science, 40 (1988), pp. 49-66.
    • (1967) The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law
    • Pocock, J.G.A.1
  • 49
    • 84973222967 scopus 로고
    • Bracton on kingship first visited: The idea of sovereignty and Bractonian political thought in seventeenth-century England
    • See J.G.A. Pocock, The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law (New York, 1967); and Cary J. Nederman, 'Bracton on Kingship First Visited: The Idea of Sovereignty and Bractonian Political Thought in Seventeenth-Century England', Political Science, 40 (1988), pp. 49-66.
    • (1988) Political Science , vol.40 , pp. 49-66
    • Nederman, C.J.1
  • 50
    • 84970629532 scopus 로고
    • Ideas and the model of political events: A problem of historicity in the history of ideas
    • A more elaborate discussion of the underlying methodological issues is presented by Conal Condren, 'Ideas and the Model of Political Events: A Problem of Historicity in the History of Ideas', Political Science, 36 (1984), pp. 53-66.
    • (1984) Political Science , vol.36 , pp. 53-66
    • Condren, C.1
  • 58
    • 77954381239 scopus 로고
    • Edinburgh, Letter #111
    • The Letters of John of Salisbury, Volume One, The Early Years (1153-1161), ed. W.J. Millor, H.E. Butler and C.N.L. Brooke (Edinburgh, 1955), Letter #111, pp. 181-2: 'Mutuis auxiliis constant omnia, et gravia vicissim levibus temperantur, et profecto ea sic universa procedunt, quod tantam dissidentium concordiam et concordium dissidentiam idem unanimitatis "spiritus inus alit" et, ut sibi invicem vicario quodam ministerio consonent, mundani corporis partes velut membra disponit. Sic sic in humano corpore sibi invicem membra deserviunt et singulorum officia publicis usibus deputantur. Absent quidem haec magis illa minus pro mole corporis, sed in effectu salutis eius omnia uniuntur; varios habent effectus, sed si usum salutis penses, in idem universa concurrunt. Non tarnen omnia coaequantur, sed superioribus inferiora deserviunt. Pes enim qui versatur in coeno nequaquam aspirant ad captis dignitatem; sed et caput in caelum erigitur non aspernatur pedem quo inversatur in coeno.'
    • (1955) The Letters of John of Salisbury, Volume One, The Early Years (1153-1161) , pp. 181-182
    • Millor, W.J.1    Butler, H.E.2    Brooke, C.N.L.3
  • 59
  • 60
    • 0040267076 scopus 로고
    • ed. C.C.J. Webb Oxford, Books 5 and 6
    • John of Salisbury, Policraticus, ed. C.C.J. Webb (Oxford, 1909), Books 5 and 6.
    • (1909) Policraticus
    • John Of Salisbury1
  • 61
    • 84928456884 scopus 로고
    • The physiological significance of the organic metaphor in John of Salisbury's Policraticus
    • For a more thorough examination of the themes discussed in this paragraph, see Cary J. Nederman, 'The Physiological Significance of the Organic Metaphor in John of Salisbury's Policraticus', History of Political Thought, 8 (1987), pp. 211-23; and Nederman, 'Freedom, Community and Function', pp. 978-83.
    • (1987) History of Political Thought , vol.8 , pp. 211-223
    • Nederman, C.J.1
  • 62
    • 0040266652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a more thorough examination of the themes discussed in this paragraph, see Cary J. Nederman, 'The Physiological Significance of the Organic Metaphor in John of Salisbury's Policraticus', History of Political Thought, 8 (1987), pp. 211-23; and Nederman, 'Freedom, Community and Function', pp. 978-83.
    • Freedom, Community and Function , pp. 978-983
    • Nederman1
  • 64
    • 0039674832 scopus 로고
    • Head or heart? the political use of body metaphors in the middle ages
    • ed. M. Feher, R. Naddaff and N. Tazi New York
    • As is documented by Jacques Le Goff, 'Head or Heart? The Political Use of Body Metaphors in the Middle Ages', in Fragments for a History of the Human Body, Vol. 3, ed. M. Feher, R. Naddaff and N. Tazi (New York, 1989), pp. 3-26.
    • (1989) Fragments for a History of the Human Body , vol.3 , pp. 3-26
    • Le Goff, J.1
  • 65
    • 0009200403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris', p. 380; cf. Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre d'Ailly, pp. 55-61; and Oakley, 'Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent', pp. 800-1. Oakley ascribes the discovery of this development to Henri de Lubac, but Figgis had made essentially the same observation in Studies of Political Thought from Gerson to Grotius, pp. 48-9.
    • Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris , pp. 380
    • Oakley1
  • 66
    • 0039674874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris', p. 380; cf. Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre d'Ailly, pp. 55-61; and Oakley, 'Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent', pp. 800-1. Oakley ascribes the discovery of this development to Henri de Lubac, but Figgis had made essentially the same observation in Studies of Political Thought from Gerson to Grotius, pp. 48-9.
    • The Political Thought of Pierre D'Ailly , pp. 55-61
    • Oakley1
  • 67
    • 0009201767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris', p. 380; cf. Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre d'Ailly, pp. 55-61; and Oakley, 'Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent', pp. 800-1. Oakley ascribes the discovery of this development to Henri de Lubac, but Figgis had made essentially the same observation in Studies of Political Thought from Gerson to Grotius, pp. 48-9.
    • Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent , pp. 800-801
    • Oakley1
  • 68
    • 0007367384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley, 'Figgis, Constance, and the Divines of Paris', p. 380; cf. Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre d'Ailly, pp. 55-61; and Oakley, 'Natural Law, the Corpus Mysticum, and Consent', pp. 800-1. Oakley ascribes the discovery of this development to Henri de Lubac, but Figgis had made essentially the same observation in Studies of Political Thought from Gerson to Grotius, pp. 48-9.
    • Studies of Political Thought from Gerson to Grotius , pp. 48-49
    • Figgis1
  • 70
    • 0039674874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre d'Ailly, pp. 59-60; John B. Morrall, Gerson and the Great Schism (Manchester, 1960), pp. 64, 82-3 and passim; and Antony Black, Monarchy and Community: Political Ideas in the Later Conciliar Controversy, 1430-1450 (Cambridge, 1970), pp. 13-21.
    • The Political Thought of Pierre D'Ailly , pp. 59-60
    • Oakley1
  • 71
    • 0010153085 scopus 로고
    • Manchester
    • See Oakley, The Political Thought of Pierre d'Ailly, pp. 59-60; John B. Morrall, Gerson and the Great Schism (Manchester, 1960), pp. 64, 82-3 and passim; and Antony Black, Monarchy and Community: Political Ideas in the Later Conciliar Controversy, 1430-1450 (Cambridge, 1970), pp. 13-21.
    • (1960) Gerson and the Great Schism , pp. 64
    • Morrall, J.B.1
  • 74
    • 0040266649 scopus 로고
    • ed. G. Kallen 3 vols., Hamburg, Book 1, ch. 1, para. 5
    • Nicholas of Cusa, De concordantia catholica, ed. G. Kallen (3 vols., Hamburg, 1959-68), Book 1, ch. 1, para. 5.
    • (1959) De Concordantia Catholica
    • Nicholas Of Cusa1
  • 75
    • 0040266646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.1.6
    • Ibid., 1.1.6: 'manifestissimum est omne esse et vivere per concordantium constitui . . . Omnis autem concordantia differentiarum est. Et quanto minor contrarietas in differentiis, tanto fortior concordantia et longior vita'. have relied on the fine translation by Paul E. Sigmund, The Catholic Corcordance (Cambridge, 1991), but have often retranslated passages of Cusa's text.
    • De Concordantia Catholica
  • 76
    • 0040266643 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Ibid., 1.1.6: 'manifestissimum est omne esse et vivere per concordantium constitui . . . Omnis autem concordantia differentiarum est. Et quanto minor contrarietas in differentiis, tanto fortior concordantia et longior vita'. have relied on the fine translation by Paul E. Sigmund, The Catholic Corcordance (Cambridge, 1991), but have often retranslated passages of Cusa's text.
    • (1991) The Catholic Corcordance
    • Sigmund, P.E.1
  • 77
    • 0040860991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.2.12
    • Cusa, De corcordantia catholica, 1.2.12: 'Dum enim istae admirandae differentes concordantiae totius universi investigantur, quanta ibi miranda naturarum combinatio, quanta orbicularis et influentialis mutua participatio quantusve in hiis ad unum finem ordo invenitur, sapientes cognoscunt. Sufficiat pro prasenti scire pro nostra investigatione, quod, licet omnia creata in esse . . . per concordantiam uniantur naturali et originali principio . . . tamen nostra ecclesia, de qua sermo est, ex rationabilibus spiritibus et hominibus, qui cum Chrsto uniuntur, licet non omnes pariformiter, sed gradatim . . . tantum constituitur.'
    • De Corcordantia Catholica
    • Cusa1
  • 80
    • 0040860991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.34.261
    • Ibid., 2.34.261: 'nisi in ipso principe ecclesiastico, absque tamen ipso domimo, quo principes eorum dominantur eis, sit coertio aliqua, non polest recte unitas conservari. Oportet enim membra putrida et pedem abscindi et oculum scandalizantem ab ecclesia erui, si corpus ecclesiae sanum debet conservari'.
    • De Corcordantia Catholica
  • 82
    • 0040266646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.27.214
    • Cusa, De concordantia catholica, 2.27.214: 'Membra omnia unius ecclesiae et corporis Christi mystici habent sua singularia officia, in quibus per alia impediri absque ordinis turbatione non possunt.'
    • De Concordantia Catholica
    • Cusa1
  • 83
    • 0040266646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.27.213
    • Ibid., 2.27.213: 'Si ita fit, ut omnis potestas regulis per universalia concilia traditis in suo regimine utatur, necessario optima reformatio sequitur.'
    • De Concordantia Catholica
  • 84
    • 0040266646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.27.214
    • Ibid., 2.27.214: 'Quare, si sciverimus, quae cuique membro ex antiquorum regulis conveniunt, videbimus, unde corpus ecclesiae deformatum exsistit. Non enim deformatum foret, nisi excessus et abusus intervenisset. Et quia, dum caput aegrotat, cetera membra dolent, hinc integritas praesidentium salus est subditorum . . . Quare nulla maior difformitas ab aliquo potent exoriri quam ab illo, qui suae magnae potestatis intuitu licere sibi cuncta credens in subditorum iura prorumpit.'
    • De Concordantia Catholica


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.