-
1
-
-
0004048289
-
-
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
-
See, for example, John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1971); and ‘Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory,’ Journal of Philosophy 78 (1980) 515–72.
-
(1971)
A Theory of Justice
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
2
-
-
60949272354
-
Logic: Normative or Descriptive? The Ethics of Belief or A Branch of Psychology?
-
See, for example, Michael Resnik, ‘Logic: Normative or Descriptive? The Ethics of Belief or A Branch of Psychology?’ Philosophy of Science 52 (1985) 221–38; and Ernest Sosa, ‘Equilibrium in Coherence?’ in J.W. Bender, ed., The Current State of the Coherence Theory (Kluwer: Academic Press 1989) 242–50.
-
(1985)
Philosophy of Science
, vol.52
, pp. 221-238
-
-
Resnik, M.1
-
3
-
-
2842528961
-
Reflective Equilibrium and Archimedean Points
-
Norman Daniels has written much to help clarify Rawls’s notion of reflective equilibrium. See his ‘Reflective Equilibrium and Archimedean Points,’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (1980) 83–103, and ‘Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics,’ Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979) 264–73. As an early expositor of Rawls on reflective equilibrium, Daniels has greatly influenced the discussion of this concept. In the following exposition, I stick primarily to Rawls’s text itself, yet my interpretation is no doubt influenced by that of Daniels.
-
(1980)
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.10
, pp. 83-103
-
-
Daniels, N.1
-
6
-
-
84954835661
-
Reflective Equilibrium and Archimedean Points
-
Norman Daniels, in ‘Reflective Equilibrium and Archimedean Points,’ is particularly helpful in clarifying the relevance of these broader theoretical issues to reflective equilibrium. Daniels clarifies Rawls’s distinction between ‘narrow reflective equilibrium’ and ‘wide reflective equilibrium.’ See, however, Margaret Holmgren’s ‘The Wide and Narrow of Reflective Equilibrium,’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (1989) 43–60, for an argument that Daniels overdraws this distinction.
-
Daniels clarifies Rawls’s distinction between ‘narrow reflective equilibrium’
-
-
Daniels, N.1
-
8
-
-
84981425482
-
Reflective Equilibrium and the Transformation of Philosophy
-
Rawls himself suggests this through his use of the term ‘coherent’ to describe beliefs in reflective equilibrium. Norman Daniels seems to suggest that (wide) reflective equilibrium is a coherentist method, although he most explicitly contrasts it with a strong version of foundationalism represented by moral intuitionism (‘Reflective Equilibrium and Archimedean Points,’ 100–3; and ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics,’ 264–73). More recently, Kai Nielsen presents his own modification of the concept of wide reflective equilibrium as ‘a coherentist model of justification’ (‘Reflective Equilibrium and the Transformation of Philosophy,’ Metaphilosophy 20 [1989], 240). Similarly, Mark Timmons has called reflective equilibrium ‘the most popular version of moral coherentism’ (‘On the Epistemic Status of Considered Moral Judgments,’ Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 [1990] Supplement).
-
(1989)
Metaphilosophy
, vol.20
, pp. 240
-
-
-
9
-
-
0040339065
-
Two Conceptions of Coherence Methods in Ethics
-
Michael DePaul, ‘Two Conceptions of Coherence Methods in Ethics,’ Mind 96 (1987) 463–81
-
(1987)
Mind
, vol.96
, pp. 463-481
-
-
DePaul, M.1
-
10
-
-
84859701269
-
Reflective Equilibrium and Foundationalism
-
In ‘Reflective Equilibrium and Foundationalism,’ American Philosophical Quarterly 23 (1986) 59–69, Michael DePaul concludes that reflective equilibrium is consistent with some forms of foundationalism. DePaul argues that Rawls’s method of reflective equilibrium is compatible with foundationalism because the two are really positions on different, but related topics. Reflective equilibrium is ‘a method of theory construction,’ while foimdationalism is ‘a type of account of the epistemic status of our beliefs’ (68). I find his argument well-reasoned and persuasive. His conclusion alone would undermine the thesis that reflective equilibrium provides a coherentist model of justification. The conclusion I am defending, however, is even stronger than DePaul’s. I will argue below that the method of reflective equilibrium, at least when taken as a method of seeking justification, is best construed as involving a form of modest foundationalism.
-
(1986)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.23
, pp. 59-69
-
-
DePaul, M.1
-
11
-
-
84981389497
-
Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Objective Moral Truth
-
We have already seen that Rawls rejects the traditional ‘intuitionist’ interpretation of moral judgments. In seeing justification in the practical way he does, Rawls makes another move that takes him away from classical ‘intuitionist’ foundationalism, which would picture the task of justification as the epistemological one of having reasons for believing that certain principles are objectively true. A careful look at Rawls’s constructivist alternative would take us away from our theme in this paper. For a critical look at several constructivist proposals, including Rawls’s, see Margaret Holmgren, ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Objective Moral Truth,’ Metaphilosophy 18 (1987) 108–24.
-
(1987)
Metaphilosophy
, vol.18
, pp. 108-124
-
-
Holmgren, M.1
-
12
-
-
33751186230
-
Epistemic Conservatism
-
There are, of course, some who defend ‘epistemic conservatism’ according to which the fact that we believe a proposition does increase our justification for beliefs based on that proposition. For a critical discussion of this view, see Richard Foley, ‘Epistemic Conservatism,’ Philosophical Studies 43 (1983) 165–82.
-
(1983)
Philosophical Studies
, vol.43
, pp. 165-182
-
-
Foley, R.1
-
15
-
-
0001443553
-
Moral Realism
-
For one naturalist moral realist view of the supervenience of moral on non-moral properties see Peter Railton, ‘Moral Realism,’ The Philosophical Review 95 (1986) 163–207.
-
(1986)
The Philosophical Review
, vol.95
, pp. 163-207
-
-
Railton, P.1
-
16
-
-
84995007817
-
Moral Epistemology and the Supervenience of Ethical Concepts
-
Supplement
-
For arguments in the defense of rationalist approaches to ethics see Robert Audi, ‘Moral Epistemology and the Supervenience of Ethical Concepts,’ Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 Supplement (1990) 1–24; and Caroline Simon, ‘On Defending a Moral Synthetic A Priori,’ Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (1988) 217–34. In general, a number of philosophers have published recent articles exploring possibilities in the modest objectivist foundationalist direction. Mark Timmons, in ‘Foundationalism and the Structure of Ethical Justification,’ argues that there are ‘a plethora of foundationalist views of justification that are at least worthy of consideration’ (Ethics 97 [1987] 595–609, at 595). Margaret Flolmgren has also published several articles which present helpful arguments in this direction. See, especially, ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Objective Moral Truth’; and ‘The Poverty of Naturalistic Moral Realism: Comments on Timmons,’ Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 Supplement (1990) 131–35. See also Caroline J. Simon, ‘The Intuitionist Argument,’ Southern Journal of Philosophy 28 (1990) 91–114. Both Holmgren and Simon argue that elements of the ‘intuitionist’ view should be taken more seriously than they have been in the contemporary discussion.
-
(1990)
Southern Journal of Philosophy
, vol.29
, pp. 1-24
-
-
Audi, R.1
-
17
-
-
84995047971
-
Normativity and the Very Idea of Moral Epistemology
-
Supplement
-
Along these lines, David Copp, in ‘Normativity and the Very Idea of Moral Epistemology’ (Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 Supplement [1990] 189–210) suggests that normative propositions are justified epistemologically in virtue of their relationship to moral standards, but that these moral standards are justified practically.
-
(1990)
Southern Journal of Philosophy
, vol.29
, pp. 189-210
-
-
Copp, D.1
|