메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 16, Issue 2, 1999, Pages 52-92

Negligence

(1)  Simons, Kenneth W a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0040784495     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0265052500002399     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (150)
  • 1
    • 0005226850 scopus 로고
    • The myth of the Ford Pinto case
    • Summer
    • See Gary T. Schwartz, "The Myth of the Ford Pinto Case," Rutgers Law Review 43, no. 4 (Summer 1991): 1013-68, for a full account. See also Richard A. Posner, Tort Law: Cases and Economic Analysis (Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1982), 225-26. The account in the text reflects the popular mythical account of the Ford Pinto controversy, but it is misleading in critical respects. On the one hand, it ignores the question of Ford's responsibility and liability for an original negligent design in locating the fuel tank in an unusually vulnerable position. Of course, if the original design was defective, Ford should be liable for any resulting injuries, even if the post-manufacture precaution of strengthening the fuel tank was too costly. On the other hand, the dollar values were computed in 1973; Ford did not, in fact, rely on these figures in deciding against strengthening the fuel tank; the controversially low "value of life" figures were supplied by a federal government agency, not by Ford; the vehicles included all cars sold in the United States in a typical year, not just the Ford Pinto; and the study in question focused on rollover accidents, not rear-end collisions. See Schwartz, "Myth," 1020-28.
    • (1991) Rutgers Law Review , vol.43 , Issue.4 , pp. 1013-1068
    • Schwartz, G.T.1
  • 2
    • 0011030142 scopus 로고
    • Boston: Little, Brown & Co.
    • See Gary T. Schwartz, "The Myth of the Ford Pinto Case," Rutgers Law Review 43, no. 4 (Summer 1991): 1013-68, for a full account. See also Richard A. Posner, Tort Law: Cases and Economic Analysis (Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1982), 225-26. The account in the text reflects the popular mythical account of the Ford Pinto controversy, but it is misleading in critical respects. On the one hand, it ignores the question of Ford's responsibility and liability for an original negligent design in locating the fuel tank in an unusually vulnerable position. Of course, if the original design was defective, Ford should be liable for any resulting injuries, even if the post-manufacture precaution of strengthening the fuel tank was too costly. On the other hand, the dollar values were computed in 1973; Ford did not, in fact, rely on these figures in deciding against strengthening the fuel tank; the controversially low "value of life" figures were supplied by a federal government agency, not by Ford; the vehicles included all cars sold in the United States in a typical year, not just the Ford Pinto; and the study in question focused on rollover accidents, not rear-end collisions. See Schwartz, "Myth," 1020-28.
    • (1982) Tort Law: Cases and Economic Analysis , pp. 225-226
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 3
    • 0346260846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gary T. Schwartz, "The Myth of the Ford Pinto Case," Rutgers Law Review 43, no. 4 (Summer 1991): 1013-68, for a full account. See also Richard A. Posner, Tort Law: Cases and Economic Analysis (Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1982), 225-26. The account in the text reflects the popular mythical account of the Ford Pinto controversy, but it is misleading in critical respects. On the one hand, it ignores the question of Ford's responsibility and liability for an original negligent design in locating the fuel tank in an unusually vulnerable position. Of course, if the original design was defective, Ford should be liable for any resulting injuries, even if the post-manufacture precaution of strengthening the fuel tank was too costly. On the other hand, the dollar values were computed in 1973; Ford did not, in fact, rely on these figures in deciding against strengthening the fuel tank; the controversially low "value of life" figures were supplied by a federal government agency, not by Ford; the vehicles included all cars sold in the United States in a typical year, not just the Ford Pinto; and the study in question focused on rollover accidents, not rear-end collisions. See Schwartz, "Myth," 1020-28.
    • Myth , pp. 1020-1028
    • Schwartz1
  • 4
    • 0039823508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Broadly speaking, utilitarian approaches judge the morality of an act by the aggregate utility of the consequences of that act, while deontological approaches instead (or also) consider whether the act is right or wrong in itself.
  • 5
    • 0041010139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • However, the question of whether an actor's beliefs are reasonable is, in a limited way, relevant to whether the actor's conduct is reasonable. For we cannot make sense of the concept of an ex ante probability of a risk of harm without an epistemic account of risk. See Section IIB below.
  • 6
    • 0041010136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Suppose no precaution would have avoided the accident, even if the driver had been paying proper attention. In law, negligence is sometimes a culpability requirement of only one element of a crime, tort, or other legal norm, in which case it might have subsidiary importance. In the crime of assaulting a police officer, for example, liability might depend on the actor being at least "negligent" as to the risk that the person he is assaulting is a police officer; but the more serious culpability obviously is that entailed by the act and intention of assaulting a person.
  • 7
    • 0039231519 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • As a matter of ordinary language, "negligence" might indeed presuppose inadvertence: "Carelessness" and, consequently, "negligence" signify neither a "state of mind," such as indifference, nor merely a "type of conduct," such as a failure to take precautions against harm. "Carelessness" or "negligence" is a failure to give active measure-taking attention to the risks inherent in the successful prosecution of some activity. Alan R. White, Grounds of Liability (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985), 102. However, I use the term in the broader sense that White calls a "type of conduct." The ordinary language usage is, I believe, beginning to expand toward this broader usage. In any event, the sense of negligence as unreasonably risky conduct has more general importance in morality and law. Of course, inadvertence is not always culpable. Moreover, when inadvertence is culpable, this might be because one should have adopted a different action-guiding strategy that would have avoided risk, not simply because one "should have been aware" of the risk. See Joel Feinberg, "Sua Culpa," in Feinberg, Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), 194 ("Overly attentive drivers with the strongest scruples and the best intentions can drive as negligently as inattentive drivers and, indeed, a good deal more negligently than experienced drivers of strong and reliable habits who rely on those habits while daydreaming. . . ."); see also Kenneth W. Simons, "Rethinking Mental States," Boston University Law Review 72, no. 3 (May 1992): 550-51.
    • (1985) Grounds of Liability , pp. 102
    • White, A.R.1
  • 8
    • 4344611822 scopus 로고
    • Sua culpa
    • Feinberg, Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • As a matter of ordinary language, "negligence" might indeed presuppose inadvertence: "Carelessness" and, consequently, "negligence" signify neither a "state of mind," such as indifference, nor merely a "type of conduct," such as a failure to take precautions against harm. "Carelessness" or "negligence" is a failure to give active measure-taking attention to the risks inherent in the successful prosecution of some activity. Alan R. White, Grounds of Liability (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985), 102. However, I use the term in the broader sense that White calls a "type of conduct." The ordinary language usage is, I believe, beginning to expand toward this broader usage. In any event, the sense of negligence as unreasonably risky conduct has more general importance in morality and law. Of course, inadvertence is not always culpable. Moreover, when inadvertence is culpable, this might be because one should have adopted a different action-guiding strategy that would have avoided risk, not simply because one "should have been aware" of the risk. See Joel Feinberg, "Sua Culpa," in Feinberg, Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), 194 ("Overly attentive drivers with the strongest scruples and the best intentions can drive as negligently as inattentive drivers and, indeed, a good deal more negligently than experienced drivers of strong and reliable habits who rely on those habits while daydreaming. . . ."); see also Kenneth W. Simons, "Rethinking Mental States," Boston University Law Review 72, no. 3 (May 1992): 550-51.
    • (1970) Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility , pp. 194
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 9
    • 0039362396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking mental states
    • May
    • As a matter of ordinary language, "negligence" might indeed presuppose inadvertence: "Carelessness" and, consequently, "negligence" signify neither a "state of mind," such as indifference, nor merely a "type of conduct," such as a failure to take precautions against harm. "Carelessness" or "negligence" is a failure to give active measure-taking attention to the risks inherent in the successful prosecution of some activity. Alan R. White, Grounds of Liability (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985), 102. However, I use the term in the broader sense that White calls a "type of conduct." The ordinary language usage is, I believe, beginning to expand toward this broader usage. In any event, the sense of negligence as unreasonably risky conduct has more general importance in morality and law. Of course, inadvertence is not always culpable. Moreover, when inadvertence is culpable, this might be because one should have adopted a different action-guiding strategy that would have avoided risk, not simply because one "should have been aware" of the risk. See Joel Feinberg, "Sua Culpa," in Feinberg, Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), 194 ("Overly attentive drivers with the strongest scruples and the best intentions can drive as negligently as inattentive drivers and, indeed, a good deal more negligently than experienced drivers of strong and reliable habits who rely on those habits while daydreaming. . . ."); see also Kenneth W. Simons, "Rethinking Mental States," Boston University Law Review 72, no. 3 (May 1992): 550-51.
    • (1992) Boston University Law Review , vol.72 , Issue.3 , pp. 550-551
    • Simons, K.W.1
  • 10
    • 0039823501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is an oversimplification. The law typically predefines certain categories of force as conclusively reasonable, and adds an explicit "reasonable person" criterion only for certain questions, including the actor's belief that force was being threatened or that defensive force was immediately necessary.
  • 11
    • 0039823500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To be sure, sometimes "negligence" is used in a wider sense. One can negligently forget a spouse's birthday, or make a negligent accounting mistake that causes only economic harm. And the epistemic sense of "negligence" is very wide: with respect to any subject whatsoever, a belief can be formed negligently (i.e., without sufficient grounds), or one can be negligent in failing to form a true belief (based on the grounds available). In law, however, the most important sense of negligence is with respect to risks of physical injury, for those are the dominant uses of negligence in tort and criminal law, which in turn are the dominant legal fields in which the negligence concept is used. In morality, as well, negligent creation of physical harms has special importance.
  • 12
    • 0039823505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • However, certain descriptions of intentional harms do presuppose that the harms are unjustifiable. To "murder" another is not merely to cause his death intentionally, but also to do so without justification. I thank Larry Solum for this point.
  • 13
    • 0040416025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In criminal law, when the probability and seriousness of the risk are sufficiently great (e.g., when one knowingly or intentionally kills), the burden of persuading the fact-finder of lack of justification sometimes shifts to the defendant, and the grounds of justification are also limited to certain narrow categories such as self-defense, defense of others, or necessity. These legal features reflect the fact that such risks are more often morally unjustifiable. But it would, in principle, be possible to have a "sliding scale" test encompassing all wrongs, and requiring stronger justification as the perceived probability of the risk approaches 100 percent.
  • 14
    • 0041010131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A fully consequentialist account does have difficulty making sense of ex post justification, insofar as we cannot be certain, until the end of time, whether an act will turn out for the best. (I thank David Lyons for this point.) On the other hand, if we relativize the ex post judgment to the information known at the time of judgment, a qualified consequentialist assessment is possible. The idea of an ex post judgment of an act normally does presuppose such a relative judgment, occurring at some time subsequent to the act being judged.
  • 15
    • 0039823498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In law, negligence sometimes refers to unreasonable conduct, and sometimes to unreasonable conduct that incurs legal liability (usually, but not always, in the form of ex post compensation).
  • 16
    • 0041875905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deontology, negligence, tort, and crime
    • February/April
    • The unjustifiable bringing about of a harm or death is often conceptualized as "wrongdoing" (the badness of an act), as compared to "culpability" (the blameworthiness of an actor). The latter category concerns the offender's degree of blame for bringing about a wrong, and thus includes the actor's mental states and excuses. For some doubts about this conceptualization, see Kenneth W. Simons, "Deontology, Negligence, Tort, and Crime," Boston University Law Review 76, nos. 1 and 2 (February/April 1996): 285-89.
    • (1996) Boston University Law Review , vol.76 , Issue.1-2 , pp. 285-289
    • Simons, K.W.1
  • 17
    • 0039823499 scopus 로고
    • Moral luckn
    • Nagel, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For endorsements of moral luck, see Thomas Nagel, "Moral Luck," in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); Bernard Williams, "Moral Luck," in Williams, Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973-1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Tony Honoré, "Responsibility and Luck," Law Quarterly Review 104 (October 1988): 530-53. For criticism, see Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, 31-33; and Steven Sverdlik, "Crime and Moral Luck," American Philosophical Quarterly 25, no. 1 (January 1988): 79-86.
    • (1979) Mortal Questions
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 18
    • 0002025908 scopus 로고
    • Moral luck
    • Williams, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For endorsements of moral luck, see Thomas Nagel, "Moral Luck," in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); Bernard Williams, "Moral Luck," in Williams, Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973-1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Tony Honoré, "Responsibility and Luck," Law Quarterly Review 104 (October 1988): 530-53. For criticism, see Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, 31-33; and Steven Sverdlik, "Crime and Moral Luck," American Philosophical Quarterly 25, no. 1 (January 1988): 79-86.
    • (1981) Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973-1980
    • Williams, B.1
  • 19
    • 0011297243 scopus 로고
    • Responsibility and luck
    • October
    • For endorsements of moral luck, see Thomas Nagel, "Moral Luck," in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); Bernard Williams, "Moral Luck," in Williams, Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973-1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Tony Honoré, "Responsibility and Luck," Law Quarterly Review 104 (October 1988): 530-53. For criticism, see Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, 31-33; and Steven Sverdlik, "Crime and Moral Luck," American Philosophical Quarterly 25, no. 1 (January 1988): 79-86.
    • (1988) Law Quarterly Review , vol.104 , pp. 530-553
    • Honoré, T.1
  • 20
    • 0004156082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For endorsements of moral luck, see Thomas Nagel, "Moral Luck," in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); Bernard Williams, "Moral Luck," in Williams, Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973-1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Tony Honoré, "Responsibility and Luck," Law Quarterly Review 104 (October 1988): 530-53. For criticism, see Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, 31-33; and Steven Sverdlik, "Crime and Moral Luck," American Philosophical Quarterly 25, no. 1 (January 1988): 79-86.
    • Doing and Deserving , pp. 31-33
    • Feinberg1
  • 21
    • 0041010122 scopus 로고
    • Crime and moral luck
    • January
    • For endorsements of moral luck, see Thomas Nagel, "Moral Luck," in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); Bernard Williams, "Moral Luck," in Williams, Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973-1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Tony Honoré, "Responsibility and Luck," Law Quarterly Review 104 (October 1988): 530-53. For criticism, see Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, 31-33; and Steven Sverdlik, "Crime and Moral Luck," American Philosophical Quarterly 25, no. 1 (January 1988): 79-86.
    • (1988) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.25 , Issue.1 , pp. 79-86
    • Sverdlik, S.1
  • 22
    • 0040870052 scopus 로고
    • The independent moral significance of wrongdoing
    • Spring
    • See Michael S. Moore, "The Independent Moral Significance of Wrongdoing," Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 5 (Spring 1994): 281; and Kenneth W. Simons, "When Is Strict Criminal Liability Just?" Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 87, no. 4 (Summer 1997): 1111-12.
    • (1994) Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues , vol.5 , pp. 281
    • Moore, M.S.1
  • 23
    • 0347108278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When is strict criminal liability just?
    • Summer
    • See Michael S. Moore, "The Independent Moral Significance of Wrongdoing," Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 5 (Spring 1994): 281; and Kenneth W. Simons, "When Is Strict Criminal Liability Just?" Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 87, no. 4 (Summer 1997): 1111-12.
    • (1997) Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology , vol.87 , Issue.4 , pp. 1111-1112
    • Simons, K.W.1
  • 24
    • 0001925436 scopus 로고
    • For those condemned to study the past: Heuristics and biases in hindsight
    • D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, and A. Tversky, eds., New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Baruch Fischhoff, "For Those Condemned to Study the Past: Heuristics and Biases in Hindsight," in D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, and A. Tversky, eds., Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 341; Baruch Fischhoff, "Debiasing," in ibid., 427-31. For an experimental study finding hindsight bias in judgments of negligence, see Susan J. LaBine and Gary LaBine, "Determinations of Negligence and the Hindsight Bias," Law and Human Behavior 20, no. 5 (1996): 501-16.
    • (1982) Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases , pp. 341
    • Fischhoff, B.1
  • 25
    • 84869826392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Debiasing
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Baruch Fischhoff, "For Those Condemned to Study the Past: Heuristics and Biases in Hindsight," in D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, and A. Tversky, eds., Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 341; Baruch Fischhoff, "Debiasing," in ibid., 427-31. For an experimental study finding hindsight bias in judgments of negligence, see Susan J. LaBine and Gary LaBine, "Determinations of Negligence and the Hindsight Bias," Law and Human Behavior 20, no. 5 (1996): 501-16.
    • Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases , pp. 427-431
    • Fischhoff, B.1
  • 26
    • 0029838363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Determinations of negligence and the hindsight bias
    • Baruch Fischhoff, "For Those Condemned to Study the Past: Heuristics and Biases in Hindsight," in D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, and A. Tversky, eds., Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 341; Baruch Fischhoff, "Debiasing," in ibid., 427-31. For an experimental study finding hindsight bias in judgments of negligence, see Susan J. LaBine and Gary LaBine, "Determinations of Negligence and the Hindsight Bias," Law and Human Behavior 20, no. 5 (1996): 501-16.
    • (1996) Law and Human Behavior , vol.20 , Issue.5 , pp. 501-516
    • LaBine, S.J.1    LaBine, G.2
  • 27
    • 0041010124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The risk that negligence analysis presupposes is typically risk about future harm, not about future benefit. Is this a necessary feature of the negligence concept? Is an actor negligent if the risk pertains only to the future benefit that might justify imposing the risk of harm, and not to the future harm itself? Suppose I speed my car through your rose bushes, with a high probability of causing property damage, because I believe I must bring my child to the hospital. If I am unreasonable in thinking that there is any significant health risk to my child, am I negligent in causing that damage? In a sense, I am; but the more typical sense of negligence confines the concept to low-probability risks of harm. This issue also arises with the use of defensive force, insofar as one might be justified even if there is only a modest probability that the use of such force will be socially beneficial (in preventing harm to the victim).
  • 28
    • 0040567445 scopus 로고
    • Risk, harm, and responsibility
    • David G. Owen, ed., New York: Oxford University Press, ch. 14
    • Probabilities can be either "objective" or "epistemic." That a coin toss will come up heads half the time is an "objective" probability; that a particular medical technique, even when carefully performed, creates a 2 percent risk of death is an "epistemic" probability. Epistemic probability is the form that is relevant to negligence. For a helpful explanation, see Stephen R. Perry, "Risk, Harm, and Responsibility," in David G. Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), ch. 14. One can also distinguish "risk" (probabilities that can be precisely measured) from "uncertainty" (all other probabilities). See W. Kip Viscusi, Fatal Tradeoffs (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), 153-54; Nicholas Rescher, Risk: A Philosophical Introduction to the Theory of Risk Evaluation and Management (Washington, DC: University Press of America, 1983), ch. 8; and Clayton P. Gillette and James E. Krier, "Risk, Courts, and Agencies," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 138, no. 4 (April 1990): 1028 n. 1. But for purposes of understanding the general concept of negligence, this distinction is not critical.
    • (1995) Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law
    • Perry, S.R.1
  • 29
    • 0003812283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Probabilities can be either "objective" or "epistemic." That a coin toss will come up heads half the time is an "objective" probability; that a particular medical technique, even when carefully performed, creates a 2 percent risk of death is an "epistemic" probability. Epistemic probability is the form that is relevant to negligence. For a helpful explanation, see Stephen R. Perry, "Risk, Harm, and Responsibility," in David G. Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), ch. 14. One can also distinguish "risk" (probabilities that can be precisely measured) from "uncertainty" (all other probabilities). See W. Kip Viscusi, Fatal Tradeoffs (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), 153-54; Nicholas Rescher, Risk: A Philosophical Introduction to the Theory of Risk Evaluation and Management (Washington, DC: University Press of America, 1983), ch. 8; and Clayton P. Gillette and James E. Krier, "Risk, Courts, and Agencies," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 138, no. 4 (April 1990): 1028 n. 1. But for purposes of understanding the general concept of negligence, this distinction is not critical.
    • (1992) Fatal Tradeoffs , pp. 153-154
    • Viscusi, W.K.1
  • 30
    • 0003552940 scopus 로고
    • Washington, DC: University Press of America, ch. 8
    • Probabilities can be either "objective" or "epistemic." That a coin toss will come up heads half the time is an "objective" probability; that a particular medical technique, even when carefully performed, creates a 2 percent risk of death is an "epistemic" probability. Epistemic probability is the form that is relevant to negligence. For a helpful explanation, see Stephen R. Perry, "Risk, Harm, and Responsibility," in David G. Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), ch. 14. One can also distinguish "risk" (probabilities that can be precisely measured) from "uncertainty" (all other probabilities). See W. Kip Viscusi, Fatal Tradeoffs (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), 153-54; Nicholas Rescher, Risk: A Philosophical Introduction to the Theory of Risk Evaluation and Management (Washington, DC: University Press of America, 1983), ch. 8; and Clayton P. Gillette and James E. Krier, "Risk, Courts, and Agencies," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 138, no. 4 (April 1990): 1028 n. 1. But for purposes of understanding the general concept of negligence, this distinction is not critical.
    • (1983) Risk: A Philosophical Introduction to the Theory of Risk Evaluation and Management
    • Rescher, N.1
  • 31
    • 77949723059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Risk, courts, and agencies
    • April
    • Probabilities can be either "objective" or "epistemic." That a coin toss will come up heads half the time is an "objective" probability; that a particular medical technique, even when carefully performed, creates a 2 percent risk of death is an "epistemic" probability. Epistemic probability is the form that is relevant to negligence. For a helpful explanation, see Stephen R. Perry, "Risk, Harm, and Responsibility," in David G. Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), ch. 14. One can also distinguish "risk" (probabilities that can be precisely measured) from "uncertainty" (all other probabilities). See W. Kip Viscusi, Fatal Tradeoffs (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), 153-54; Nicholas Rescher, Risk: A Philosophical Introduction to the Theory of Risk Evaluation and Management (Washington, DC: University Press of America, 1983), ch. 8; and Clayton P. Gillette and James E. Krier, "Risk, Courts, and Agencies," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 138, no. 4 (April 1990): 1028 n. 1. But for purposes of understanding the general concept of negligence, this distinction is not critical.
    • (1990) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.138 , Issue.4 , pp. 1028
    • Gillette, C.P.1    Krier, J.E.2
  • 32
    • 0041010120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In this essay, I place quotation marks around the term "knowing" when I use the term in the special sense just noted in the text. This sense is unconventional in an important respect: we do not normally say that an agent has "knowingly" created a harm when the actor should have known that the harm was highly likely to occur. Rather, we reserve the term "knowingly" for one who subjectively believes that the harm was highly likely. I sometimes use the less conventional form in order to focus on negligence as a form of unreasonable risk-creation, and to contrast it with more risky behavior. If I were instead focusing on negligence as a form of inadvertent risk-creation, then I would contrast such inadvertence with knowledge as conventionally understood (subjective awareness of a high-probability risk of harm) and with one meaning of recklessness (subjective awareness of a low-probability risk of harm). Negligent and "knowing" actors differ in their estimates of the probability of harm. A separate question is the severity or extent of the relevant harm. A ceteris paribus condition is implicit in my comparison of negligent and "knowing" actors. Negligently creating a risk of a nuclear disaster is obviously more culpable than "knowingly" stepping on someone's foot.
  • 33
    • 0040416015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, if she intends to cause the pedestrian fear, then she indeed intends a "harm," insofar as fear is an actual (though intangible) harm. Still, one who intends a more serious form of harm (such as physical harm) is more culpable. It is much easier to justify intentionally creating a risk of a given type of harm than to justify intentionally causing that harm. As an instance of the former, consider the promoter of a trapeze act who chooses not to use a safety net, in order to make the act more exciting.
  • 34
    • 0039362396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On a deontological account, whether an actor intends to create a risk, as opposed to creating it as a knowing side-effect, is indeed relevant to whether, all things considered, the actor's risk-creation is justified, as I will argue below. There is much more to say about the relevance of intention and of other conative states such as "culpable indifference" to risk or to harm. For a thorough account of the moral and legal differences between cognitive and conative mental states, see Simons, "Rethinking Mental States."
    • Rethinking Mental States
    • Simons1
  • 35
    • 0041010114 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Ronald Milo adopts a wider version that he calls "moral negligence" to encompass "any kind of morally wrong act due to a particular kind of shortcoming on the part of the agent - namely, a culpable failure to take those precautions necessary to assure oneself, before acting, that what one proposes to do is not in violation of one's moral principles." Ronald D. Milo, Immorality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), 84. This is an epistemic duty, to ascertain whether one's act would violate moral principles; Milo points out that an additional question is whether (and in what way) we are culpable for nevertheless taking the risk of violating our principles. See ibid., 85.
    • (1984) Immorality , pp. 84
    • Milo, R.D.1
  • 36
    • 0039823491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ronald Milo adopts a wider version that he calls "moral negligence" to encompass "any kind of morally wrong act due to a particular kind of shortcoming on the part of the agent - namely, a culpable failure to take those precautions necessary to assure oneself, before acting, that what one proposes to do is not in violation of one's moral principles." Ronald D. Milo, Immorality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), 84. This is an epistemic duty, to ascertain whether one's act would violate moral principles; Milo points out that an additional question is whether (and in what way) we are culpable for nevertheless taking the risk of violating our principles. See ibid., 85.
    • Immorality , pp. 85
  • 37
    • 0009386072 scopus 로고
    • The problem of abortion and the doctrine of the double effect
    • Berkely: University of California Press
    • See Philippa Foot, "The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect," in Foot, Virtues and Vices (Berkely: University of California Press, 1978), 23-24; and Judith Jarvis Thompson, "The Trolley Problem," in Thompson, The Realm of Rights (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990) ch. 7. The trolley problem is often posed in contrast with the following "transplant" problem: a surgeon is considering whether to carve up an unwilling patient and transplant his organs as the only means available to save five other lives. See Thompson, Realm of Rights, 137. Some explain the impermissibility of the trade-off in the transplant case, and its permissibility in the trolley case, by reference to the doctrine of double effect (insofar as the deaths of the workmen supposedly are foreseen but not intended, while the death of the patient supposedly in inteded). But I agree with Thomson and others that this explanation does not suffice.
    • (1978) Foot, Virtues and Vices , pp. 23-24
    • Foot, P.1
  • 38
    • 0039231510 scopus 로고
    • The trolley problem
    • Thompson, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, ch. 7
    • See Philippa Foot, "The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect," in Foot, Virtues and Vices (Berkely: University of California Press, 1978), 23-24; and Judith Jarvis Thompson, "The Trolley Problem," in Thompson, The Realm of Rights (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990) ch. 7. The trolley problem is often posed in contrast with the following "transplant" problem: a surgeon is considering whether to carve up an unwilling patient and transplant his organs as the only means available to save five other lives. See Thompson, Realm of Rights, 137. Some explain the impermissibility of the trade-off in the transplant case, and its permissibility in the trolley case, by reference to the doctrine of double effect (insofar as the deaths of the workmen supposedly are foreseen but not intended, while the death of the patient supposedly in inteded). But I agree with Thomson and others that this explanation does not suffice.
    • (1990) The Realm of Rights
    • Thompson, J.J.1
  • 39
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Philippa Foot, "The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect," in Foot, Virtues and Vices (Berkely: University of California Press, 1978), 23-24; and Judith Jarvis Thompson, "The Trolley Problem," in Thompson, The Realm of Rights (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990) ch. 7. The trolley problem is often posed in contrast with the following "transplant" problem: a surgeon is considering whether to carve up an unwilling patient and transplant his organs as the only means available to save five other lives. See Thompson, Realm of Rights, 137. Some explain the impermissibility of the trade-off in the transplant case, and its permissibility in the trolley case, by reference to the doctrine of double effect (insofar as the deaths of the workmen supposedly are foreseen but not intended, while the death of the patient supposedly in inteded). But I agree with Thomson and others that this explanation does not suffice.
    • Realm of Rights , pp. 137
    • Thompson1
  • 40
    • 0039362396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n. 69
    • Or, to return to the Ford Pinto example, the risk that any individual Ford Pinto vehicle would catch fire and cause a burn death (that reasonable precaution would have avoided) was .0000144, over a fleet of 12.5 million vehicles; but the expected number of burn deaths over the entire fleet of Ford Pintos was a probability greater than one - namely, 180 expected deaths. See Simons, "Rethinking Mental States," 292 n. 69. To be sure, a more careful identification of the relevant frame of reference for assessing probabilities might eliminate this arbitrariness. (Compare the question of whether an individual owner must take a precaution, with the question of whether Ford must do so for all cars with the problem.) Under this approach, however, it becomes difficult to identify risks, acontextually, as "low" rather than "high" probability, i.e., as negligent rather than "knowing." In the end, a completely acontextual identification of risks as "low" rather than "high" seems impossible. The distinction between negligence and "knowledge" appears to be a relative judgment. Consider a question that has troubled legal scholars: whether a manufacturer of a product who knows that a small number of users (out of a much larger class) are virtually certain to suffer physical harm should be treated as "knowingly" inflicting that harm. If the issue is whether his conduct demands as strong a justification as a manufacturer who knows that every user will suffer the same degree of physical harm, the answer is clearly no. And if the issue is whether the conduct of either manufacturer would demand as strong a justification if the risks of harm were substantially lower, again the answer is clearly no. But there might be no nonarbitrary way to characterize any of these four cases as "negligent" or "knowing" in an absolute sense.
    • Rethinking Mental States , pp. 292
    • Simons1
  • 41
    • 0039823490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thus, one might know to a certainty that one will suffer a harm either in the immediate or in the distant future; the distant harm might cause a different type or degree of emotional stress than the immediate harm. To be sure, the contemporary emotional harm produced by long-latency risks that are virtually certain to result in ultimate harm will often be disproportionately greater than the harm produced by less certain risks. (It will often be more than five times as painful to worry about a virtually certain future death than to worry about a 20 percent risk of death.) But these emotional harm cases do not justify distinct treatment of negligence in general. Not all cases of risk generate significant emotional harm. (In many cases, the risk is unknown or underappreciated.) At most, the considerations just discussed would justify special treatment of certain emotional harm cases.
  • 43
    • 77949723059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gillette and Krier, "Risk, Courts, and Agencies," 1091-93; and Richard H. Pildes and Cass R. Sunstein, "Reinventing the Regulatory State," University of Chicago Law Review 62, no. 1 (Winter 1995): 55-64.
    • Risk, Courts, and Agencies , pp. 1091-1093
    • Gillette1    Krier2
  • 44
    • 84885215480 scopus 로고
    • Reinventing the regulatory state
    • Winter
    • See Gillette and Krier, "Risk, Courts, and Agencies," 1091-93; and Richard H. Pildes and Cass R. Sunstein, "Reinventing the Regulatory State," University of Chicago Law Review 62, no. 1 (Winter 1995): 55-64.
    • (1995) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.62 , Issue.1 , pp. 55-64
    • Pildes, R.H.1    Sunstein, C.R.2
  • 45
    • 0040416016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In the end, however, I will reject this argument.
  • 46
    • 0039231505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To some extent, the law recognizes this distinction, for it sometimes shifts the burden of persuasion, and narrows the grounds of justification, when the conduct moves from negligent to knowing or intentional. See note 9 supra. I have suggested that a constraint of special stringency applies when a person knowingly or intentionally creates a high risk of death. Whether an unusually stringent constraint also applies to a person who knowingly or intentionally creates a high risk of a lesser harm than death is less certain, but I cannot explore the matter here
    • To some extent, the law recognizes this distinction, for it sometimes shifts the burden of persuasion, and narrows the grounds of justification, when the conduct moves from negligent to knowing or intentional. See note 9 supra. I have suggested that a constraint of special stringency applies when a person knowingly or intentionally creates a high risk of death. Whether an unusually stringent constraint also applies to a person who knowingly or intentionally creates a high risk of a lesser harm than death is less certain, but I cannot explore the matter here.
  • 47
    • 0030530625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The deontology of negligence
    • February/April
    • See Heidi M. Hurd, "The Deontology of Negligence," Boston University Law Review 76, nos. 1 and 2 (February/April 1996): 249-72.
    • (1996) Boston University Law Review , vol.76 , Issue.1-2 , pp. 249-272
    • Hurd, H.M.1
  • 49
    • 0040416010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Actually, this test (known as the "BPL" test) contemplates that the rational actor would aggregate the different risks that would be prevented by a precaution, e.g., risks of minor physical injury (discounted by their probability), of major physical injury (also discounted), of death, of major property damage, of minor property damage, and so forth.
  • 50
    • 0011538305 scopus 로고
    • A theory of strict liability
    • January
    • The landmark case is United States v. Carroll Towing Co., 159 F.2d 169, 173 (2d Cir. 1947). Whether Judge Learned Hand actually intended his "BPL" test to be the sort of cost-benefit economic test that Posner defends is a controversial question. In his early writing, Richard Epstein analyzes the contrast differently, concluding that extrapolation from the intrapersonal to the interpersonal case justifies a general rule of strict liability. However, his focus is not on which decision among risky alternatives is best, but rather on who should bear the costs of the decision. In the intrapersonal case, he points out, all the costs and benefits accrue to the actor. In the interpersonal case, however, the actor might derive the benefits while the victim might bear the costs. Epstein suggests that the actor has no right to dump the costs of his action on another. Richard A. Epstein, "A Theory of Strict Liability," Journal of Legal Studies 2, no. 1 (January 1973): 159. For a critique of this argument, see Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995), 171-75.
    • (1973) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.2 , Issue.1 , pp. 159
    • Epstein, R.A.1
  • 51
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • The landmark case is United States v. Carroll Towing Co., 159 F.2d 169, 173 (2d Cir. 1947). Whether Judge Learned Hand actually intended his "BPL" test to be the sort of cost-benefit economic test that Posner defends is a controversial question. In his early writing, Richard Epstein analyzes the contrast differently, concluding that extrapolation from the intrapersonal to the interpersonal case justifies a general rule of strict liability. However, his focus is not on which decision among risky alternatives is best, but rather on who should bear the costs of the decision. In the intrapersonal case, he points out, all the costs and benefits accrue to the actor. In the interpersonal case, however, the actor might derive the benefits while the victim might bear the costs. Epstein suggests that the actor has no right to dump the costs of his action on another. Richard A. Epstein, "A Theory of Strict Liability," Journal of Legal Studies 2, no. 1 (January 1973): 159. For a critique of this argument, see Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995), 171-75.
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 171-175
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 52
    • 0004113926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • See, generally, Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1993), 66-73.
    • (1993) Value in Ethics and Economics , pp. 66-73
    • Anderson, E.1
  • 53
    • 0007317681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ibid., 70, discussing Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), 349.
    • Value in Ethics and Economics , pp. 70
  • 54
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See ibid., 70, discussing Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), 349.
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 349
    • Raz, J.1
  • 55
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 27-29; see also Bernard Williams, in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), 116-17; and Raz, Morality of Freedom, 271-87.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 27-29
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 56
    • 0003619765 scopus 로고
    • J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 27-29; see also Bernard Williams, in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), 116-17; and Raz, Morality of Freedom, 271-87.
    • (1973) Utilitarianism: For and Against , pp. 116-117
    • Williams, B.1
  • 57
    • 0004339288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 27-29; see also Bernard Williams, in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), 116-17; and Raz, Morality of Freedom, 271-87.
    • Morality of Freedom , pp. 271-287
    • Raz1
  • 58
    • 0039823485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • At the same time, simple extrapolation will fail to capture the collective benefits that can be achieved only through social interaction. When and only when the hermit rejoins society, the collective benefits of friendship and community are possible.
  • 59
    • 21844521505 scopus 로고
    • The invisible hand formula
    • August
    • In his attempt to explain American tort law, Stephen Gilles employs the extrapolation approach (which he terms the "single-owner" heuristic) in an especially interesting way. He asks what value the average injurer would assign to precaution costs. But, recognizing that the average injurer might assign too low a value to the expected accident costs to others, Gilles also asks what value the average victim would assign to those costs. "Because the average injurer and the average victim, taken together, constitute the average person, the inquiry reduces to whether the average person would take the precaution if he or she bore both the costs and benefits in full." Stephen G. Gilles, "The Invisible Hand Formula," Virginia Law Review 80, no. 5 (August 1994): 1035. In American tort law, however, the negligence test employs a "reasonable" or "ideal" valuation, not an "average" valuation. Gilles tries to handle this objection by referring to the accident valuation of victims, not of injurers. Still, it seems that he should refer to the "reasonable" precaution valuation of injurers. For the average injurer might place undue weight on the cost of certain precautions (e.g., the average Boston driver is probably unduly worried about his pride when he refuses to allow other drivers to share the road). Gilles ultimately settles on an "altruistic reasonable person standard," asking what care an "average reasonable person takes of his or her own person and property" (ibid., 1037, 1038). The problem remains, however, that "average" and "reasonable" (or ideal) standards can deviate. If one moves from an "average" to a "reasonable" valuation, one has moved from a factual, descriptive account of utilities to a normative, social valuation. (See the discussion below of a modified utilitarian calculus.)
    • (1994) Virginia Law Review , vol.80 , Issue.5 , pp. 1035
    • Gilles, S.G.1
  • 60
    • 79955801861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his attempt to explain American tort law, Stephen Gilles employs the extrapolation approach (which he terms the "single-owner" heuristic) in an especially interesting way. He asks what value the average injurer would assign to precaution costs. But, recognizing that the average injurer might assign too low a value to the expected accident costs to others, Gilles also asks what value the average victim would assign to those costs. "Because the average injurer and the average victim, taken together, constitute the average person, the inquiry reduces to whether the average person would take the precaution if he or she bore both the costs and benefits in full." Stephen G. Gilles, "The Invisible Hand Formula," Virginia Law Review 80, no. 5 (August 1994): 1035. In American tort law, however, the negligence test employs a "reasonable" or "ideal" valuation, not an "average" valuation. Gilles tries to handle this objection by referring to the accident valuation of victims, not of injurers. Still, it seems that he should refer to the "reasonable" precaution valuation of injurers. For the average injurer might place undue weight on the cost of certain precautions (e.g., the average Boston driver is probably unduly worried about his pride when he refuses to allow other drivers to share the road). Gilles ultimately settles on an "altruistic reasonable person standard," asking what care an "average reasonable person takes of his or her own person and property" (ibid., 1037, 1038). The problem remains, however, that "average" and "reasonable" (or ideal) standards can deviate. If one moves from an "average" to a "reasonable" valuation, one has moved from a factual, descriptive account of utilities to a normative, social valuation. (See the discussion below of a modified utilitarian calculus.)
    • Virginia Law Review , pp. 1037
  • 61
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thomson, Realm of Rights, 197-99. It might be permissible to take blood from unconscious X in order to save Y.
    • Realm of Rights , pp. 197-199
    • Thomson1
  • 63
    • 0039231500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n. 2
    • Ibid., 1028 n. 2. They do, however, acknowledge a possible role for distributive principles.
    • Risk, Courts, and Agencies , pp. 1028
  • 64
    • 0011416796 scopus 로고
    • Equality or priority?
    • University of Kansas, November 21
    • See, e.g., Derek Parfit, "Equality or Priority?" The Lindley Lecture (University of Kansas, November 21, 1991); and David O. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 270-73 (where Brink argues that an objective form of utilitarianism can endorse a distribution-sensitive theory of value). Concern about distributive effects is a powerful reason not to adopt Richard Posner's suggested wealth-maximization version of utilitarianism. This version evaluates choices by the criteria of willingness and ability to pay, rather than utility. But these criteria create an additional problem of distributive justice, beyond that entailed by utilitarianism. For example, under the wealth-maximization approach, it is better to endanger the safety of a poor person than the safety of a wealthy person: "a person should feel free to drive faster in a poor than in a wealthy neighborhood because expected accident costs are on average lower in the former," as Posner candidly concedes. Richard A. Posner, "Wealth Maximization and Tort Law: A Philosophical Inquiry," in Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations, 110.
    • (1991) The Lindley Lecture
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 65
    • 0003687747 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • See, e.g., Derek Parfit, "Equality or Priority?" The Lindley Lecture (University of Kansas, November 21, 1991); and David O. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 270-73 (where Brink argues that an objective form of utilitarianism can endorse a distribution-sensitive theory of value). Concern about distributive effects is a powerful reason not to adopt Richard Posner's suggested wealth-maximization version of utilitarianism. This version evaluates choices by the criteria of willingness and ability to pay, rather than utility. But these criteria create an additional problem of distributive justice, beyond that entailed by utilitarianism. For example, under the wealth-maximization approach, it is better to endanger the safety of a poor person than the safety of a wealthy person: "a person should feel free to drive faster in a poor than in a wealthy neighborhood because expected accident costs are on average lower in the former," as Posner candidly concedes. Richard A. Posner, "Wealth Maximization and Tort Law: A Philosophical Inquiry," in Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations, 110.
    • (1989) Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics , pp. 270-273
    • Brink, D.O.1
  • 66
    • 3142736107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wealth maximization and tort law: A philosophical inquiry
    • Owen, ed.
    • See, e.g., Derek Parfit, "Equality or Priority?" The Lindley Lecture (University of Kansas, November 21, 1991); and David O. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 270-73 (where Brink argues that an objective form of utilitarianism can endorse a distribution-sensitive theory of value). Concern about distributive effects is a powerful reason not to adopt Richard Posner's suggested wealth-maximization version of utilitarianism. This version evaluates choices by the criteria of willingness and ability to pay, rather than utility. But these criteria create an additional problem of distributive justice, beyond that entailed by utilitarianism. For example, under the wealth-maximization approach, it is better to endanger the safety of a poor person than the safety of a wealthy person: "a person should feel free to drive faster in a poor than in a wealthy neighborhood because expected accident costs are on average lower in the former," as Posner candidly concedes. Richard A. Posner, "Wealth Maximization and Tort Law: A Philosophical Inquiry," in Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations, 110.
    • Philosophical Foundations , pp. 110
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 67
    • 0004153161 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Criminal law does not redistribute costs. Therefore, if strict criminal liability is justifiable, the justification must be different. See Jules Coleman, Risks and Wrongs (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 222-23; and Simons, "When Is Strict Criminal Liability Just?"
    • (1992) Risks and Wrongs , pp. 222-223
    • Coleman, J.1
  • 68
    • 0041010109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Criminal law does not redistribute costs. Therefore, if strict criminal liability is justifiable, the justification must be different. See Jules Coleman, Risks and Wrongs (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 222-23; and Simons, "When Is Strict Criminal Liability Just?"
    • When Is Strict Criminal Liability Just?
    • Simons1
  • 69
    • 21144460156 scopus 로고
    • Jules Coleman and corrective justice in tort law: A critique and reformulation
    • Summer
    • However, it is also proper to consider not only the actor's primary conduct, but also his ability to insure against the risks of his conduct. The permissibility of engaging in some activity might itself depend on ability to absorb certain risks of one's conduct. We forbid people from driving without insurance, in part because we want them to be financially responsible even for the non-negligent accidents they cause. See Kenneth W. Simons, "Jules Coleman and Corrective Justice in Tort Law: A Critique and Reformulation," Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 15, no. 3 (Summer 1992): 880. See also Thomson, Realm of Rights, 159.
    • (1992) Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy , vol.15 , Issue.3 , pp. 880
    • Simons, K.W.1
  • 70
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, it is also proper to consider not only the actor's primary conduct, but also his ability to insure against the risks of his conduct. The permissibility of engaging in some activity might itself depend on ability to absorb certain risks of one's conduct. We forbid people from driving without insurance, in part because we want them to be financially responsible even for the non-negligent accidents they cause. See Kenneth W. Simons, "Jules Coleman and Corrective Justice in Tort Law: A Critique and Reformulation," Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 15, no. 3 (Summer 1992): 880. See also Thomson, Realm of Rights, 159.
    • Realm of Rights , pp. 159
    • Thomson1
  • 71
    • 0041010107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What counts as a fair distribution is beyond the scope of this essay. In environmental law, government regulators have increasingly attended to the distribution of risk as well as its aggregate level. See Pildes and Sunstein, "Reinventing the Regulatory State," 44. The special concern that many feel about "catastrophic" loss is partly based on a distributive concern: Imagine . . . a decision maker who is forced to choose between two actions. The first action poses a 1 in 1,000 chance of causing 100,000 deaths spread randomly across the country; the second has a 1 in 1,200 chance of causing the near obliteration of a city of 100,000. A rational decision maker could obviously select the first alternative, notwithstanding its larger expected loss. Gillette and Krier, "Risk, Courts, and Agencies," 1078.
    • Reinventing the Regulatory State , pp. 44
    • Pildes1    Sunstein2
  • 72
    • 77949723059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What counts as a fair distribution is beyond the scope of this essay. In environmental law, government regulators have increasingly attended to the distribution of risk as well as its aggregate level. See Pildes and Sunstein, "Reinventing the Regulatory State," 44. The special concern that many feel about "catastrophic" loss is partly based on a distributive concern: Imagine . . . a decision maker who is forced to choose between two actions. The first action poses a 1 in 1,000 chance of causing 100,000 deaths spread randomly across the country; the second has a 1 in 1,200 chance of causing the near obliteration of a city of 100,000. A rational decision maker could obviously select the first alternative, notwithstanding its larger expected loss. Gillette and Krier, "Risk, Courts, and Agencies," 1078.
    • Risk, Courts, and Agencies , pp. 1078
    • Gillette1    Krier2
  • 73
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thomson, Realm of Rights, 166-68; and Raz, Morality of Freedom, 276. For example, the conclusion that it is wrong to humiliate another for fun is unaffected by the number of persons who would derive pleasure from such an act. Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 69.
    • Realm of Rights , pp. 166-168
    • Thomson1
  • 74
    • 0004339288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thomson, Realm of Rights, 166-68; and Raz, Morality of Freedom, 276. For example, the conclusion that it is wrong to humiliate another for fun is unaffected by the number of persons who would derive pleasure from such an act. Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 69.
    • Morality of Freedom , pp. 276
    • Raz1
  • 75
    • 0004113926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thomson, Realm of Rights, 166-68; and Raz, Morality of Freedom, 276. For example, the conclusion that it is wrong to humiliate another for fun is unaffected by the number of persons who would derive pleasure from such an act. Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 69.
    • Value in Ethics and Economics , pp. 69
    • Anderson1
  • 76
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986), 307.
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 307
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 77
    • 0002076816 scopus 로고
    • Laundering preferences
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ch. 9
    • See Robert E. Goodin, Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), ch. 9 ("Laundering Preferences").
    • (1995) Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 79
    • 0004247732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Goodin's terminology, the prohibition on racially motivated actions might reflect a violation of rights and thus might be better understood as an "output filter," not the "input filter" accomplished by laundering preferences. Goodin, Utilitarianism, 133-37.
    • Utilitarianism , pp. 133-137
    • Goodin1
  • 80
    • 0039231488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Strictly speaking, the orientation is "non-prospective" rather than retrospective. Our judgment that a negligent act deserves retributive blame could be contemporaneous with (or even prior to) the act. What I want to distinguish (as "prospective") is a judgment that depends on whether the further consequences of the act are optimal.
  • 81
    • 0039231489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Indeed, the ex ante and action-guiding features of the negligence perspective mean that negligence is necessarily a consequentialist doctrine. But this is so only in the very limited sense that the harmful consequences immediately risked by the negligent act are critical to the actor's culpability. In precisely the same sense, the wrongfulness of attempted murder, too, depends on the expected or intended consequences of the attempted murderer's acts. Only in this limited sense is our reason for blaming negligent actors or attempted murderers necessarily "consequentialist."
  • 82
    • 0003813026 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • We might also ask producers of dangerous products to contribute to a social insurance fund for the victims. On the general idea that tragic choices require a morally sensitive actor to show regret, see Martha Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). See, generally, Jeremy Waldron, "Rights in Conflict," in Waldron, Liberal Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 214-15.
    • (1986) The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 83
    • 52549100332 scopus 로고
    • Rights in conflict
    • Waldron, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • We might also ask producers of dangerous products to contribute to a social insurance fund for the victims. On the general idea that tragic choices require a morally sensitive actor to show regret, see Martha Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). See, generally, Jeremy Waldron, "Rights in Conflict," in Waldron, Liberal Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 214-15.
    • (1993) Liberal Rights , pp. 214-215
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 84
    • 0000247536 scopus 로고
    • Incommensurability and valuation in law
    • February
    • See, generally, Cass Sunstein, "Incommensurability and Valuation in Law," Michigan Law Review 92, no. 4 (February 1994): 779-861.
    • (1994) Michigan Law Review , vol.92 , Issue.4 , pp. 779-861
    • Sunstein, C.1
  • 85
    • 0041010107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an application of this approach to social regulation of risk, see Pildes and Sunstein, "Reinventing the Regulatory State," 64-66, 127 (where they endorse the "disaggregation" of costs and benefits so that citizens and decision makers make value choices more openly).
    • Reinventing the Regulatory State , pp. 64-66
    • Pildes1    Sunstein2
  • 86
    • 0038260135 scopus 로고
    • sections 291-93
    • In American tort law, the Restatement (Second) of Torts catalogues relevant social interests to be balanced. And the commentary to the Restatement does not emphasize the incentive effects of the balancing test that the Restatement endorses, as one would expect if the test were thoroughly consequentialist. See Restatement (Second) of Torts, sections 291-93 (1965).
    • (1965) Restatement (Second) of Torts
  • 87
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 34-40 (where Rawls criticizes such intuitionism, and also distinguishes it from metaethical and epistemological intuitionism).
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 34-40
    • Rawls1
  • 88
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chs. 6
    • See Thomson, Realm of Rights, chs. 6 (on trade-offs) and 7 (on the trolley problem). Moreover, even within the narrower frame of the alternative actions available, the agent's permission to divert the trolley onto an innocent victim does not imply a permission to throw an innocent passenger onto the tracks to stop the trolley (as Thomson observes). Thus, even the immediate consequences (in terms of net lives saved) are not dispositive of permissibility.
    • Realm of Rights
    • Thomson1
  • 89
    • 84922978193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For one endorsement of such a threshold test, see Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law, 148-50. For a response, see Kenneth W. Simons, "Justification in Private Law" (book review of Weinrib), Cornell Law Review 81, no. 3 (March 1996): 711-12. Some proponents of threshold tests mean to endorse strict liability rather than negligence; my disagreement does not extend to them.
    • The Idea of Private Law , pp. 148-150
    • Weinrib1
  • 90
    • 21444455464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justification in private law
    • book review of Weinrib, March
    • For one endorsement of such a threshold test, see Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law, 148-50. For a response, see Kenneth W. Simons, "Justification in Private Law" (book review of Weinrib), Cornell Law Review 81, no. 3 (March 1996): 711-12. Some proponents of threshold tests mean to endorse strict liability rather than negligence; my disagreement does not extend to them.
    • (1996) Cornell Law Review , vol.81 , Issue.3 , pp. 711-712
    • Simons, K.W.1
  • 91
    • 0040415991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Hurd, "Deontology of Negligence." For a critique, see Simons, "Deontology" (supra note 12), 290-95.
    • Deontology of Negligence
    • Hurd1
  • 92
    • 0039231468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12
    • But see Hurd, "Deontology of Negligence." For a critique, see Simons, "Deontology" (supra note 12), 290-95.
    • Deontology , pp. 290-295
    • Simons1
  • 93
    • 0039231476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The standards of care in negligence
    • Owen, ed., listing sources
    • Accordingly, many tort commentators view the "BPL" test and even the vaguer balancing test of the Restatement (Second) of Torts as necessarily utilitarian. See Richard Wright, "The Standards of Care in Negligence Law," in Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations, 250 (listing sources).
    • Philosophical Foundations , vol.250
    • Wright, R.1
  • 94
    • 0040415990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some have asserted that British courts employ the disproportion test, rather than a supposed simple cost-benefit American test, to gauge negligence in tort law. See Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula," 1026 n. 8; and Gregory C. Keating, "Reasonableness and Rationality in Negligence Theory," Stanford Law Review 48, no. 2 (January 1996): 352-53. It is possible, however, that the British test merely shifts the burden of persuasion, and therefore does not create the problems noted in the text. See Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula." Ernest Weinrib appears to endorse some combination of the disproportion test and the "threshold of risk" test. See Simons, "Justification in Private Law," 702-4.
    • Invisible Hand Formula , pp. 1026
    • Gilles1
  • 95
    • 0346675339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasonableness and rationality in negligence theory
    • January
    • Some have asserted that British courts employ the disproportion test, rather than a supposed simple cost-benefit American test, to gauge negligence in tort law. See Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula," 1026 n. 8; and Gregory C. Keating, "Reasonableness and Rationality in Negligence Theory," Stanford Law Review 48, no. 2 (January 1996): 352-53. It is possible, however, that the British test merely shifts the burden of persuasion, and therefore does not create the problems noted in the text. See Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula." Ernest Weinrib appears to endorse some combination of the disproportion test and the "threshold of risk" test. See Simons, "Justification in Private Law," 702-4.
    • (1996) Stanford Law Review , vol.48 , Issue.2 , pp. 352-353
    • Keating, G.C.1
  • 96
    • 0040415990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some have asserted that British courts employ the disproportion test, rather than a supposed simple cost-benefit American test, to gauge negligence in tort law. See Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula," 1026 n. 8; and Gregory C. Keating, "Reasonableness and Rationality in Negligence Theory," Stanford Law Review 48, no. 2 (January 1996): 352-53. It is possible, however, that the British test merely shifts the burden of persuasion, and therefore does not create the problems noted in the text. See Gilles, "Invisible Hand
    • Invisible Hand Formula
    • Gilles1
  • 97
    • 0039823462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some have asserted that British courts employ the disproportion test, rather than a supposed simple cost-benefit American test, to gauge negligence in tort law. See Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula," 1026 n. 8; and Gregory C. Keating, "Reasonableness and Rationality in Negligence Theory," Stanford Law Review 48, no. 2 (January 1996): 352-53. It is possible, however, that the British test merely shifts the burden of persuasion, and therefore does not create the problems noted in the text. See Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula." Ernest Weinrib appears to endorse some combination of the disproportion test and the "threshold of risk" test. See Simons, "Justification in Private Law," 702-4.
    • Justification in Private Law , pp. 702-704
    • Simons1
  • 98
    • 0039823464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Keating, "Reasonableness," 354: "The magnitude of the harm that death, serious physical injury, and property damage threaten to persons' capacity to pursue their conceptions of the good is usually much greater than the magnitude of the harm threatened by increased precaution costs."
    • Reasonableness , pp. 354
    • Keating1
  • 99
    • 0039823467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ibid
    • See ibid.
  • 100
    • 0039823466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ibid., 353
    • See ibid., 353.
  • 101
    • 0004339288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Incommensurability between values A and B occurs in the strongest sense when adding to or subtracting from value A does not affect the choice between A and B. See Raz, Morality of Freedom, 322-26. (An example might be the question of whether Bach or Darwin was "more brilliant"; if either had been a little more or less brilliant than he in fact was, it would still be the case that neither was more brilliant than the other. Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 55-56.) Such incommensurability is rare. For example, if the choice between patient autonomy and burdens to a doctor of disclosing a risk were strongly incommensurable in this sense, then no increase or decrease in the burden to the doctor, or in the value of autonomy, would affect the choice. But that seems highly doubtful. In cases of risky activity, I believe, the competing values are, at most, incommensurable in this strong sense only within a limited range or "margin." See Raz, Morality of Freedom, 327-28.
    • Morality of Freedom , pp. 322-326
    • Raz1
  • 102
    • 0004113926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Incommensurability between values A and B occurs in the strongest sense when adding to or subtracting from value A does not affect the choice between A and B. See Raz, Morality of Freedom, 322-26. (An example might be the question of whether Bach or Darwin was "more brilliant"; if either had been a little more or less brilliant than he in fact was, it would still be the case that neither was more brilliant than the other. Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 55-56.) Such incommensurability is rare. For example, if the choice between patient autonomy and burdens to a doctor of disclosing a risk were strongly incommensurable in this sense, then no increase or decrease in the burden to the doctor, or in the value of autonomy, would affect the choice. But that seems highly doubtful. In cases of risky activity, I believe, the competing values are, at most, incommensurable in this strong sense only within a limited range or "margin." See Raz, Morality of Freedom, 327-28.
    • Value in Ethics and Economics , pp. 55-56
    • Anderson1
  • 103
    • 0004339288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Incommensurability between values A and B occurs in the strongest sense when adding to or subtracting from value A does not affect the choice between A and B. See Raz, Morality of Freedom, 322-26. (An example might be the question of whether Bach or Darwin was "more brilliant"; if either had been a little more or less brilliant than he in fact was, it would still be the case that neither was more brilliant than the other. Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics, 55-56.) Such incommensurability is rare. For example, if the choice between patient autonomy and burdens to a doctor of disclosing a risk were strongly incommensurable in this sense, then no increase or decrease in the burden to the doctor, or in the value of autonomy, would affect the choice. But that seems highly doubtful. In cases of risky activity, I believe, the competing values are, at most, incommensurable in this strong sense only within a limited range or "margin." See Raz, Morality of Freedom, 327-28.
    • Morality of Freedom , pp. 327-328
    • Raz1
  • 104
    • 0039823465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The British adopt a form of the first rule; most American jurisdictions adopt a form of the second; and some American jurisdictions permit the patient to waive disclosure, thus recognizing a version of the third.
  • 105
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For another example of a "relative valuation" approach, see Thomson, Realm of Rights, 197-99, where she argues that, to save A's life, a guardian can authorize a fairly serious nonfatal operation on A (such as cutting off A's leg), while a guardian of both X and Y cannot balance so close to the margin in authorizing an operation on X in order to save Y's life. More generally, insofar as extrapolating from an intrapersonal to an interpersonal case is feasible and defensible, we should at least apply a significant "premium" and should require a much greater total benefit in the interpersonal case than in the intrapersonal, in order to justify nonconsensual imposition of risks on others who do not receive any direct benefit from imposing those risks.
    • Realm of Rights , pp. 197-199
    • Thomson1
  • 106
    • 0039823464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Keating, "Reasonableness," 319-27 (where he discusses balancing the injurer's freedom of action against the victim's interest in physical security); and Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law, 84-113 (where he discusses deriving tort principles from a paradigm of "doing and suffering"). Professor Richard Wright, in "Rights, Justice, and Tort Law," and "The Standards of Care in Negligence Law," in Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations, describes corrective justice in tort law as expressing the Kantian notion that adversely affecting another's person or stock of resources is objectively inconsistent with the other's equal negative freedom. I agree with many of Wright's conclusions, including the inadequacy of the utilitarian account and its failure to explain the relevance of the actor's motive, the victim's consent, and other important factors. However, I am not persuaded that Wright's own reductionist framework can explain all the features of tort doctrine that he purports to explain. Rather, I believe that those features are more readily justified by a pluralistic analysis.
    • Reasonableness , pp. 319-327
    • Keating1
  • 107
    • 84922978193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Keating, "Reasonableness," 319-27 (where he discusses balancing the injurer's freedom of action against the victim's interest in physical security); and Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law, 84-113 (where he discusses deriving tort principles from a paradigm of "doing and suffering"). Professor Richard Wright, in "Rights, Justice, and Tort Law," and "The Standards of Care in Negligence Law," in Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations, describes corrective justice in tort law as expressing the Kantian notion that adversely affecting another's person or stock of resources is objectively inconsistent with the other's equal negative freedom. I agree with many of Wright's conclusions, including the inadequacy of the utilitarian account and its failure to explain the relevance of the actor's motive, the victim's consent, and other important factors. However, I am not persuaded that Wright's own reductionist framework can explain all the features of tort doctrine that he purports to explain. Rather, I believe that those features are more readily justified by a pluralistic analysis.
    • The Idea of Private Law , pp. 84-113
    • Weinrib1
  • 108
    • 0040415988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Rights, justice, and tort law," and "The standards of care in negligence law,"
    • Owen, ed.
    • See Keating, "Reasonableness," 319-27 (where he discusses balancing the injurer's freedom of action against the victim's interest in physical security); and Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law, 84-113 (where he discusses deriving tort principles from a paradigm of "doing and suffering"). Professor Richard Wright, in "Rights, Justice, and Tort Law," and "The Standards of Care in Negligence Law," in Owen, ed., Philosophical Foundations, describes corrective justice in tort law as expressing the Kantian notion that adversely affecting another's person or stock of resources is objectively inconsistent with the other's equal negative freedom. I agree with many of Wright's conclusions, including the inadequacy of the utilitarian account and its failure to explain the relevance of the actor's motive, the victim's consent, and other important factors. However, I am not persuaded that Wright's own reductionist framework can explain all the features of tort doctrine that he purports to explain. Rather, I believe that those features are more readily justified by a pluralistic analysis.
    • Philosophical Foundations
    • Wright, R.1
  • 109
    • 0039823464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Keating, "Reasonableness"; Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law, and Wright, "Rights, Justice, and Tort Law."
    • Reasonableness
    • Keating1
  • 110
  • 113
    • 0039231474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Whether explicit consent is a morally necessary precondition of imposing risk on others depends, in part, on the gravity of the risk. Below a certain threshold of risk, perhaps, no explicit consent is required. But the requirement of obtaining consent turns on the kind, as well as the level, of risk. Direct physical invasions of bodily integrity, such as through medical treatment, are far more likely to require explicit consent than are other risky acts with no greater, or even a lesser, risk of causing physical harm.
  • 114
    • 0039823464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Keating, "Reasonableness," 344. However, I find problematic Keating's explicit reliance on a Rawlsian social-justice framework to justify private tort doctrine.
    • Reasonableness , pp. 344
    • Keating1
  • 115
    • 0039362396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The actor's purpose or intention to bring about a harm has enormous significance. Even if such a purposeful actor reasonably believes that he is unlikely to succeed (and thus would otherwise be considered no more than negligent), he will usually be considered more culpable than an actor who believes he is likely to bring about the harm but does not intend it. See Simons, "Rethinking Mental States," 478-82.
    • Rethinking Mental States , pp. 478-482
    • Simons1
  • 116
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic Books
    • Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 28. See also Raz, Morality of Freedom, 278.
    • (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 28
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 117
    • 0004339288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 28. See also Raz, Morality of Freedom, 278.
    • Morality of Freedom , pp. 278
    • Raz1
  • 118
    • 84937288609 scopus 로고
    • Personal rights and public space
    • Spring
    • See, e.g., Thomas Nagel, "Personal Rights and Public Space," Philosophy and Public Affairs 24, no. 2 (Spring 1995): 89-90 (where Nagel relates this prohibition to the idea of an agent's "inviolability"). See also F. M. Kamm, "Non-consequentialism, the Person as an End-in-Itself, and the Significance of Status," Philosophy and Public Affairs 21, no. 4 (Fall 1992): 381-89.
    • (1995) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.24 , Issue.2 , pp. 89-90
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 119
    • 0026922829 scopus 로고
    • Non-consequentialism, the person as an end-in-itself, and the significance of status
    • Fall
    • See, e.g., Thomas Nagel, "Personal Rights and Public Space," Philosophy and Public Affairs 24, no. 2 (Spring 1995): 89-90 (where Nagel relates this prohibition to the idea of an agent's "inviolability"). See also F. M. Kamm, "Non-consequentialism, the Person as an End-in-Itself, and the Significance of Status," Philosophy and Public Affairs 21, no. 4 (Fall 1992): 381-89.
    • (1992) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.21 , Issue.4 , pp. 381-389
    • Kamm, F.M.1
  • 121
    • 0040415980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We might permit this even where Q rather than P is exposed to Y amount of harm, if P and Q are sufficiently similar in their vulnerability to an original threat of harm, as in a variation of the trolley problem.
  • 122
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 42-45. Rawls describes a "lexical" ordering as one which "requires us to satisfy the first principle in the ordering before we can move on to the second, the second before we can consider the third, and so on."
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 42-45
    • Rawls1
  • 123
    • 0004213898 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • See Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1978), xi (where Dworkin argues that individual rights are political "trumps" held by individuals over collective goals [including utilitarianism]).
    • (1978) Taking Rights Seriously
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 128
    • 0040415976 scopus 로고
    • Mixed theories of tort law: Affirming both deterrence and corrective justice
    • June
    • For a similar analysis in the context of tort doctrine, see Gary Schwartz, "Mixed Theories of Tort Law: Affirming Both Deterrence and Corrective Justice," Texas Law Review 75, no. 7 (June 1977): 1828-33.
    • (1977) Texas Law Review , vol.75 , Issue.7 , pp. 1828-1833
    • Schwartz, G.1
  • 129
    • 0039823459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • On a deontological view, this value need not be equal to the amount provided as compensation after the fact.
  • 131
    • 0006231332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • For an illuminating discussion of this feature of deontological reasoning, see Leo Katz, Ill-Gotten Gains (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997).
    • (1997) Ill-gotten Gains
    • Katz, L.1
  • 132
    • 0040415983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Despite much academic support for automobile no-fault insurance as a replacement for tort negligence liability, and despite evidence that no-fault schemes save considerably on the enforcement costs of negligence liability, many people are offended by the idea that someone can negligently damage their car or their body without paying directly for that harm. (Of course, the opposition of trial lawyers is also an important part of this story.)
  • 133
    • 0007715903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press
    • This division of labor also allows the formal legal standard to remain constant through time, while flexible in its application. (I thank Hugh Baxter for this point.) Whether a virtue-theory approach can give content to a "reasonable person" standard is an interesting question, but one that I do not have the space to explore here. On virtue theory generally, see Daniel Statman, ed., Virtue Ethics (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1997).
    • (1997) Virtue Ethics
    • Statman, D.1
  • 134
    • 0039231463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Insofar as a "reasonable person" test is meant to establish a standard that people can fairly be blamed for not satisfying, the test should be at least partially subjective - i.e., it should assess the individual capacities of the agent. See Perry, "Risk, Harm, and Responsibility," 344. Legal standards are sometimes more "objective" than this, both for practical reasons (avoiding problems of proof and of fraud) and also, perhaps, in order to express a (strict liability) principle of fairness (e.g., the principle that others in the community are entitled to a relatively high standard of conduct, even if this requires blaming or holding liable some who cannot reasonably be expected to meet the standard). Thus, courts typically ignore intellectual deficiencies, and also religious convictions that prompt actors to impose higher than usual risks on others (or on themselves).
    • Risk, Harm, and Responsibility , pp. 344
    • Perry1
  • 135
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • The difficulty that John Rawls has encountered in convincing skeptics of the value of his own attempted solution underscores the seriousness of this problem. See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); and Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," University of Chicago Law Review 64, no. 3 (Summer 1997): 765-807.
    • (1996) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 136
    • 0347873666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea of public reason revisited
    • Summer
    • The difficulty that John Rawls has encountered in convincing skeptics of the value of his own attempted solution underscores the seriousness of this problem. See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); and Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," University of Chicago Law Review 64, no. 3 (Summer 1997): 765-807.
    • (1997) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.64 , Issue.3 , pp. 765-807
    • Rawls1
  • 138
    • 0041010080 scopus 로고
    • Scientific policymaking and the torts revolution
    • Spring
    • See Michael Wells, "Scientific Policymaking and the Torts Revolution," Georgia Law Review 26, no. 3 (Spring 1992): 731; and Catherine Pierce Wells, "Tort Law as Corrective Justice: A Pragmatic Justification for Jury Adjudication," Michigan Law Review 88, no. 8 (August 1990): 2348-2413.
    • (1992) Georgia Law Review , vol.26 , Issue.3 , pp. 731
    • Wells, M.1
  • 139
    • 0039823444 scopus 로고
    • Tort law as corrective justice: A pragmatic justification for jury adjudication
    • August
    • See Michael Wells, "Scientific Policymaking and the Torts Revolution," Georgia Law Review 26, no. 3 (Spring 1992): 731; and Catherine Pierce Wells, "Tort Law as Corrective Justice: A Pragmatic Justification for Jury Adjudication," Michigan Law Review 88, no. 8 (August 1990): 2348-2413.
    • (1990) Michigan Law Review , vol.88 , Issue.8 , pp. 2348-2413
    • Wells, C.P.1
  • 140
    • 0038260135 scopus 로고
    • section 283 cmt. e
    • Sometimes, jury instructions explaining negligence reflect a duty of impartiality, of considering interests of others as you would consider your own. See Restatement (Second) of Torts, section 283 cmt. e (1965); Keating, "Reasonableness," 337-38; and Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula," 1038. For further discussion of the moral content of negligence doctrine, see Simons, "Deontology," 277-85.
    • (1965) Restatement (Second) of Torts
  • 141
    • 0039823464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sometimes, jury instructions explaining negligence reflect a duty of impartiality, of considering interests of others as you would consider your own. See Restatement (Second) of Torts, section 283 cmt. e (1965); Keating, "Reasonableness," 337-38; and Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula," 1038. For further discussion of the moral content of negligence doctrine, see Simons, "Deontology," 277-85.
    • Reasonableness , pp. 337-338
    • Keating1
  • 142
    • 0040415990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sometimes, jury instructions explaining negligence reflect a duty of impartiality, of considering interests of others as you would consider your own. See Restatement (Second) of Torts, section 283 cmt. e (1965); Keating, "Reasonableness," 337-38; and Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula," 1038. For further discussion of the moral content of negligence doctrine, see Simons, "Deontology," 277-85.
    • Invisible Hand Formula , pp. 1038
    • Gilles1
  • 143
    • 0039231468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sometimes, jury instructions explaining negligence reflect a duty of impartiality, of considering interests of others as you would consider your own. See Restatement (Second) of Torts, section 283 cmt. e (1965); Keating, "Reasonableness," 337-38; and Gilles, "Invisible Hand Formula," 1038. For further discussion of the moral content of negligence doctrine, see Simons, "Deontology," 277-85.
    • Deontology , pp. 277-285
    • Simons1
  • 144
    • 21344487971 scopus 로고
    • Compensation and commensurability
    • October
    • The criticism that follows might not apply to much broader interpretations of corrective justice, such as Margaret Radin's understanding of corrective justice as any principles governing our response to the wrongful or unjust unsettling of entitlements. See Margaret Jane Radin, "Compensation and Commensurability," Duke Law Journal 43, no. 1 (October 1993):
    • (1993) Duke Law Journal , vol.43 , Issue.1
    • Radin, M.J.1
  • 145
    • 0040415978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • On the other hand, insofar as Radin's view refers only to ex post "correction" of a wrong, it might not fully encompass the ex ante perspective of negligence.
  • 146
    • 0039823451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These include: abnormally dangerous activities (such as the use of explosives), wild animals, product liability to some extent, and vicarious liability. (The latter imposes strict liability for the tort of another; but that other tort is usually fault-based.)
  • 147
    • 0039231467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Liability for defective design and defective warnings is largely fault-based. Liability for manufacturing defects is strict, however.
  • 148
    • 0041010079 scopus 로고
    • Corrective justice and liability for risk-creation: A comment
    • October
    • Indeed, in nuisance law, if a person's use of his property is unreasonable, and if certain other criteria are satisfied, injunctive relief is presumed to be the proper remedy. The qualification "often" leaves room for a liberty constraint on state power when the moral fault of the defendant is modest. If an actor drives drunk, it is permissible for the state to prevent or enjoin his conduct. If a driver fails to follow the automobile manufacturer's maintenance schedule, enjoining him to do so would be an excessive use of state power. In either case, however, requiring compensation for harms caused by the actor's neglect might be a legitimate use of state power. (See the discussion in the prior section.) A corrective-justice theorist might reply that compensatory liability in such a case exemplifies strict liability rather than fault. But (as I have argued elsewhere) a genuine fault approach could justify imposing an ex ante tort "fine" to approximate the expected costs of the neglect (in either of the cases mentioned in the previous paragraph). Kenneth W. Simons, "Corrective Justice and Liability for Risk-Creation: A Comment," U.C.L.A. Law Review 38, no. 1 (October 1990): 113-42. If this is correct, then ex post compensation can also be viewed as fault-based.
    • (1990) U.C.L.A. Law Review , vol.38 , Issue.1 , pp. 113-142
    • Simons, K.W.1
  • 149
    • 0039231434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I do not address here "strict liability" principles of conditional fault, e.g., a requirement that a business provide insurance or some other ex ante assurance that it will be able to pay for harms that it might cause. See Simons, "Jules Coleman and Corrective Justice," 880.
    • Jules Coleman and Corrective Justice , pp. 880
    • Simons1
  • 150
    • 0039823464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, it would be justifiable to employ a different measure of damages in strict liability cases than in negligence cases - for example, routinely adding a "kicker" to negligence damages (beyond those damages that would leave the victim indifferent between damages and harm) to reflect the special wrong of creating unreasonable risks to others. For similar suggestions, see Keating, "Reasonableness," 349 n. 125, and sources cited there.
    • Reasonableness , pp. 349
    • Keating1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.