메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 50, Issue 4, 1997, Pages 841-872

Descartes on causation

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0040683414     PISSN: 00346632     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (13)

References (278)
  • 1
    • 0039683219 scopus 로고
    • ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery, republished by Nouvelle Presentation, ed. B. Rochot, P. Costabel, and J. Beaude, 11 vols. Paris: J. Vrin
    • René Descartes, Oeuvres de Descartes (hereafter, "AT"), ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery, republished by Nouvelle Presentation, ed. B. Rochot, P. Costabel, and J. Beaude, 11 vols. (Paris: J. Vrin, 1964-76), 7:49-50; The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (CSM), trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, with the correspondence translated in part by Anthony Kenny, 3 vols. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984, 1985, and 1991), 2:34.
    • (1964) Oeuvres de Descartes (Hereafter, "AT") , vol.7 , pp. 49-50
    • Descartes, R.1
  • 2
    • 0040274984 scopus 로고
    • with the correspondence translated in part by Anthony Kenny, 3 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985
    • René Descartes, Oeuvres de Descartes (hereafter, "AT"), ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery, republished by Nouvelle Presentation, ed. B. Rochot, P. Costabel, and J. Beaude, 11 vols. (Paris: J. Vrin, 1964-76), 7:49-50; The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (CSM), trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, with the correspondence translated in part by Anthony Kenny, 3 vols. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984, 1985, and 1991), 2:34.
    • (1984) The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (CSM) , vol.2 , pp. 34
    • Cottingham, J.1    Stoothoff, R.2    Murdoch, D.3
  • 3
    • 0039090964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM 2:68; AT, 7:207-13, CSM, 2:146-50.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 95
  • 4
    • 0040274980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM 2:68; AT, 7:207-13, CSM, 2:146-50.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 68
  • 5
    • 0039090965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM 2:68; AT, 7:207-13, CSM, 2:146-50.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 207-213
  • 6
    • 0040869240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM 2:68; AT, 7:207-13, CSM, 2:146-50.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 146-150
  • 7
    • 0039090963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Some philosophers might argue that the Cartesian texts are so under-determined with respect to a theory of causation that any project to delineate such a theory is a form of wishful thinking. We find this contention a bit premature and leave it to our readers to judge whether we have succeeded in demonstrating that a Cartesian theory of causation can be gleaned from Descartes' writings.
  • 8
    • 0039683215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:49-50, CSM, 2:34.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 49-50
  • 9
    • 0039683216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:49-50, CSM, 2:34.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 34
  • 10
    • 0040274981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:108-9, CSM, 2:78.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 108-109
  • 11
    • 0040274982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:108-9, CSM, 2:78.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 78
  • 12
    • 0040869239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM, 2:68.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 95
  • 13
    • 0039683217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM, 2:68.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 68
  • 14
    • 0039683218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM, 2:68-9.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 95
  • 15
    • 0039090962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM, 2:68-9.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 68-69
  • 16
    • 0040869238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM, 2:69.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 95
  • 17
    • 0040274978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:95, CSM, 2:69.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 69
  • 18
    • 0040869227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Alfred Freddoso New Haven: Yale University Press
    • See Francisco Suarez, On Efficient Causality: Metaphysical Disputations 17, 18, and 19, trans. Alfred Freddoso (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994), Disputation 18, §7, pp. 131-77, and Disputation 17, Introductory Remarks, 3. For careful discussion of Aristotle's, Aquinas's, and Suarez's criteria for deeming a cause an efficient cause, see J. E. K. Secada, "Descartes on Time and Causality," Philosophical Review 99 (1990): 45-72, esp. 49-51.
    • (1994) On Efficient Causality: Metaphysical Disputations 17, 18, and 19
    • Suarez, F.1
  • 19
    • 0040274972 scopus 로고
    • Descartes on time and causality
    • See Francisco Suarez, On Efficient Causality: Metaphysical Disputations 17, 18, and 19, trans. Alfred Freddoso (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994), Disputation 18, §7, pp. 131-77, and Disputation 17, Introductory Remarks, 3. For careful discussion of Aristotle's, Aquinas's, and Suarez's criteria for deeming a cause an efficient cause, see J. E. K. Secada, "Descartes on Time and Causality," Philosophical Review 99 (1990): 45-72, esp. 49-51.
    • (1990) Philosophical Review , vol.99 , pp. 45-72
    • Secada, J.E.K.1
  • 20
    • 0040869236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:108, CSM, 2:78.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 108
  • 21
    • 0040274979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:108, CSM, 2:78.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 78
  • 22
    • 0040274981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:108-9, CSM, 2:78.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 108-109
  • 23
    • 0039683213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:108-9, CSM, 2:78.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 78
  • 24
    • 79958659660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:109, CSM, 2:79.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 109
  • 25
    • 0039683212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:109, CSM, 2:79.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 79
  • 26
    • 0040869233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:110, CSM, 2:79.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 110
  • 27
    • 0040869235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:110, CSM, 2:79.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 79
  • 28
    • 0040869233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:110, CSM, 2:79-80.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 110
  • 29
    • 0040869234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:110, CSM, 2:79-80.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 79-80
  • 30
    • 0039683211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 8B:368, CSM, 2:310.
    • AT , vol.8 B , pp. 368
  • 31
    • 0039683210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 8B:368, CSM, 2:310.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 310
  • 32
    • 85173365250 scopus 로고
    • Is there radical dissimulation in descartes' meditations?
    • ed. Amélie Oksenberg Rorty Berkeley: University of California Press
    • One might think that "blur" is too weak a word here. It appears that Descartes is attempting to make an exception to the standard criteria for efficient causality in the case of God's causing himself. However, this would make nonsense of the argument in Meditation 3, since it would introduce an equivocation on the notion of an efficient cause. Taken in this strict sense, such a move might provide evidence for elements of the dissimulation thesis, that is, the thesis that the Descartes of the Meditations intentionally misrepresented important elements of his philosophy. See Louis E. Loeb, "Is There Radical Dissimulation in Descartes' Meditations?" in Essays on Descartes's Meditations, ed. Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986), 243-70, for a discussion of the dissimulation thesis. To examine the thesis is beyond the scope of this paper.
    • (1986) Essays on Descartes's Meditations , pp. 243-270
    • Loeb, L.E.1
  • 33
    • 79958659660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:109, CSM, 2:79.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 109
  • 34
    • 0039090960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:109, CSM, 2:79.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 79
  • 35
    • 0040869232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Such a move would conflate Descartes' cosmological argument with his ontological argument, and we believe he had methodological reasons for not wanting to do so. To examine those reasons, however, is beyond the scope of the present paper.
  • 36
    • 0039090959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:55, 5:158; CSM, 2:38-9, 3:341; Principles 1:28, AT, 8A:15-16, CSM, 1:202-3.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 55
  • 37
    • 0040274976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:55, 5:158; CSM, 2:38-9, 3:341; Principles 1:28, AT, 8A:15-16, CSM, 1:202-3.
    • AT , vol.5 , pp. 158
  • 38
    • 0040869230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:55, 5:158; CSM, 2:38-9, 3:341; Principles 1:28, AT, 8A:15-16, CSM, 1:202-3.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 38-39
  • 39
    • 0039090958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:55, 5:158; CSM, 2:38-9, 3:341; Principles 1:28, AT, 8A:15-16, CSM, 1:202-3.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 341
  • 40
    • 0039683206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:55, 5:158; CSM, 2:38-9, 3:341; Principles 1:28, AT, 8A:15-16, CSM, 1:202-3.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 28
  • 41
    • 0040274974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:55, 5:158; CSM, 2:38-9, 3:341; Principles 1:28, AT, 8A:15-16, CSM, 1:202-3.
    • AT , vol.8 A , pp. 15-16
  • 42
    • 0039683207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:55, 5:158; CSM, 2:38-9, 3:341; Principles 1:28, AT, 8A:15-16, CSM, 1:202-3.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 202-203
  • 43
    • 0039090931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:242, 366; CSM, 2:169, 252.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 242
  • 44
    • 0040869228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:242, 366; CSM, 2:169, 252.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 169
  • 45
    • 0004158981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 5.2
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, 5.2, 1013a29-33, trans. W. D. Ross, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 752. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 93a36-94b8, trans. G. R. G. Mure, Basic Works, 171; and Physics, 2.3, 194b29-32, trans. R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye, Basic Works, 241.
    • Metaphysics
    • Aristotle1
  • 46
    • 0039683205 scopus 로고
    • ed. Richard McKeon New York: Random House
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, 5.2, 1013a29-33, trans. W. D. Ross, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 752. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 93a36-94b8, trans. G. R. G. Mure, Basic Works, 171; and Physics, 2.3, 194b29-32, trans. R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye, Basic Works, 241.
    • (1941) The Basic Works of Aristotle , pp. 752
    • Ross, W.D.1
  • 47
    • 33751184353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.11
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, 5.2, 1013a29-33, trans. W. D. Ross, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 752. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 93a36-94b8, trans. G. R. G. Mure, Basic Works, 171; and Physics, 2.3, 194b29-32, trans. R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye, Basic Works, 241.
    • Posterior Analytics
  • 48
    • 0039683160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, 5.2, 1013a29-33, trans. W. D. Ross, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 752. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 93a36-94b8, trans. G. R. G. Mure, Basic Works, 171; and Physics, 2.3, 194b29-32, trans. R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye, Basic Works, 241.
    • Basic Works , pp. 171
    • Mure, G.R.G.1
  • 49
    • 4243570175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.3
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, 5.2, 1013a29-33, trans. W. D. Ross, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 752. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 93a36-94b8, trans. G. R. G. Mure, Basic Works, 171; and Physics, 2.3, 194b29-32, trans. R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye, Basic Works, 241.
    • Physics
  • 50
    • 0039090934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, 5.2, 1013a29-33, trans. W. D. Ross, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 752. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 93a36-94b8, trans. G. R. G. Mure, Basic Works, 171; and Physics, 2.3, 194b29-32, trans. R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye, Basic Works, 241.
    • Basic Works , pp. 241
    • Hardie, R.P.1    Gaye, R.K.2
  • 51
    • 0040869203 scopus 로고
    • trans. F. R. Larcher Albany, NY: Magi Books
    • See Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle, trans. F. R. Larcher (Albany, NY: Magi Books, 1970), 198-9; Peter of Spain, Topics, in The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. 1, Logic and the Philosophy of Language, ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 236; William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, trans. Norman Kretzmann (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1966), 86-7; Suarez, On Efficient Causality; and Antoine Arnauld, The Art of Thinking: Port-Royal Logic, trans. James Dickoff and Patricia James, Library of Liberal Arts (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964), 243.
    • (1970) Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle , pp. 198-199
    • Aquinas, T.1
  • 52
    • 0040869189 scopus 로고
    • Topics
    • ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle, trans. F. R. Larcher (Albany, NY: Magi Books, 1970), 198-9; Peter of Spain, Topics, in The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. 1, Logic and the Philosophy of Language, ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 236; William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, trans. Norman Kretzmann (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1966), 86-7; Suarez, On Efficient Causality; and Antoine Arnauld, The Art of Thinking: Port-Royal Logic, trans. James Dickoff and Patricia James, Library of Liberal Arts (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964), 243.
    • (1988) The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, Vol. 1, Logic and the Philosophy of Language , vol.1 , pp. 236
    • Peter1
  • 53
    • 0039683163 scopus 로고
    • Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • See Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle, trans. F. R. Larcher (Albany, NY: Magi Books, 1970), 198-9; Peter of Spain, Topics, in The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. 1, Logic and the Philosophy of Language, ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 236; William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, trans. Norman Kretzmann (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1966), 86-7; Suarez, On Efficient Causality; and Antoine Arnauld, The Art of Thinking: Port-Royal Logic, trans. James Dickoff and Patricia James, Library of Liberal Arts (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964), 243.
    • (1966) William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic , pp. 86-87
    • Kretzmann, N.1
  • 54
    • 0040869227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle, trans. F. R. Larcher (Albany, NY: Magi Books, 1970), 198-9; Peter of Spain, Topics, in The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. 1, Logic and the Philosophy of Language, ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 236; William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, trans. Norman Kretzmann (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1966), 86-7; Suarez, On Efficient Causality; and Antoine Arnauld, The Art of Thinking: Port-Royal Logic, trans. James Dickoff and Patricia James, Library of Liberal Arts (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964), 243.
    • On Efficient Causality
    • Suarez1
  • 55
    • 0040274943 scopus 로고
    • trans. James Dickoff and Patricia James, Library of Liberal Arts Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
    • See Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle, trans. F. R. Larcher (Albany, NY: Magi Books, 1970), 198-9; Peter of Spain, Topics, in The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. 1, Logic and the Philosophy of Language, ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 236; William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, trans. Norman Kretzmann (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1966), 86-7; Suarez, On Efficient Causality; and Antoine Arnauld, The Art of Thinking: Port-Royal Logic, trans. James Dickoff and Patricia James, Library of Liberal Arts (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964), 243.
    • (1964) The Art of Thinking: Port-Royal Logic , pp. 243
    • Arnauld, A.1
  • 56
    • 0040274939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236, CSM, 2:165.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 236
  • 57
    • 0040869195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236, CSM, 2:165.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 165
  • 58
    • 0040869202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §§34-36
    • See Descartes' Passion of the Soul (hereafter, "POS"), §§34-36, AT, 11:354-7, CSM, 1:341-2. See also Suarez, On Efficient Causality, Disputation 18, §2, n. 40, p. 88; Disputation 19, §2, nn. 12-23, pp. 290-300. See also Daniel Garber, "Descartes and Occasionalism," in Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony, ed. Steven Nadler (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993), 9-26.
    • Passion of the Soul (Hereafter, "POS")
    • Descartes1
  • 59
    • 0039683166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Descartes' Passion of the Soul (hereafter, "POS"), §§34-36, AT, 11:354-7, CSM, 1:341-2. See also Suarez, On Efficient Causality, Disputation 18, §2, n. 40, p. 88; Disputation 19, §2, nn. 12-23, pp. 290-300. See also Daniel Garber, "Descartes and Occasionalism," in Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony, ed. Steven Nadler (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993), 9-26.
    • AT , vol.11 , pp. 354-357
  • 60
    • 84925962699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Descartes' Passion of the Soul (hereafter, "POS"), §§34-36, AT, 11:354-7, CSM, 1:341-2. See also Suarez, On Efficient Causality, Disputation 18, §2, n. 40, p. 88; Disputation 19, §2, nn. 12-23, pp. 290-300. See also Daniel Garber, "Descartes and Occasionalism," in Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony, ed. Steven Nadler (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993), 9-26.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 341-342
  • 61
    • 0039683164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Disputation 18, §2
    • See Descartes' Passion of the Soul (hereafter, "POS"), §§34-36, AT, 11:354-7, CSM, 1:341-2. See also Suarez, On Efficient Causality, Disputation 18, §2, n. 40, p. 88; Disputation 19, §2, nn. 12-23, pp. 290-300. See also Daniel Garber, "Descartes and Occasionalism," in Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony, ed. Steven Nadler (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993), 9-26.
    • On Efficient Causality , vol.40 , pp. 88
    • Suarez1
  • 62
    • 0040869152 scopus 로고
    • Descartes and occasionalism
    • ed. Steven Nadler University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press
    • See Descartes' Passion of the Soul (hereafter, "POS"), §§34-36, AT, 11:354-7, CSM, 1:341-2. See also Suarez, On Efficient Causality, Disputation 18, §2, n. 40, p. 88; Disputation 19, §2, nn. 12-23, pp. 290-300. See also Daniel Garber, "Descartes and Occasionalism," in Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony, ed. Steven Nadler (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993), 9-26.
    • (1993) Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony , pp. 9-26
    • Garber, D.1
  • 63
    • 0039090930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The sophisma 'every man is of necessity an animal'
    • See Boethius of Dacia, "The Sophisma 'Every Man is of Necessity an Animal'," in The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. 1, 499; and Suarez, On Efficient Causality, Disputation 18, §3, n. 12, pp. 98-9.
    • The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts , vol.1 , pp. 499
    • Boethius1
  • 64
    • 0040274940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Disputation 18, §3
    • See Boethius of Dacia, "The Sophisma 'Every Man is of Necessity an Animal'," in The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. 1, 499; and Suarez, On Efficient Causality, Disputation 18, §3, n. 12, pp. 98-9.
    • On Efficient Causality , vol.12 , pp. 98-99
    • Suarez1
  • 66
    • 0039683160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, 5.2, 1013a27-9, in Basic Works, 752.
    • Basic Works , pp. 752
  • 67
    • 0039090931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:242, CSM, 2:169.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 242
  • 68
    • 0040869228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:242, CSM, 2:169.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 169
  • 69
    • 0004323473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.11
    • Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 94a27-35, in Basic Works, 171. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.8, 93a3-14, in Basic Works, 167; Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics, 198.
    • Posterior Analytics
    • Aristotle1
  • 70
    • 0039683160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 94a27-35, in Basic Works, 171. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.8, 93a3-14, in Basic Works, 167; Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics, 198.
    • Basic Works , pp. 171
  • 71
    • 33751184353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.8
    • Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 94a27-35, in Basic Works, 171. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.8, 93a3-14, in Basic Works, 167; Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics, 198.
    • Posterior Analytics
  • 72
    • 0039683160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 94a27-35, in Basic Works, 171. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.8, 93a3-14, in Basic Works, 167; Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics, 198.
    • Basic Works , pp. 167
  • 73
    • 0040274937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, 2.11, 94a27-35, in Basic Works, 171. See also Posterior Analytics, 2.8, 93a3-14, in Basic Works, 167; Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics, 198.
    • Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics , pp. 198
  • 75
    • 0039683165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is comparable to doing a formal proof in logic. While one is typically asked to show that the conclusion follows from the premises and a certain set of rules, the same procedure can be seen as explaining why the conclusion follows from the premises and a set of rules.
  • 77
    • 0039683157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peter of Spain, Topics, 237; Arnauld, The Art of Thinking, 244; see also William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, 86-7.
    • Topics , pp. 237
    • Peter1
  • 78
    • 0039683154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peter of Spain, Topics, 237; Arnauld, The Art of Thinking, 244; see also William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, 86-7.
    • The Art of Thinking , pp. 244
    • Arnauld1
  • 80
    • 0040274939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236, CSM, 2:165.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 236
  • 81
    • 0040869195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236, CSM, 2:165.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 165
  • 82
    • 0040274941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:209, CSM, 2:147; quoted from AT, 7:108, CSM, 2:78.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 209
  • 83
    • 0040274936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:209, CSM, 2:147; quoted from AT, 7:108, CSM, 2:78.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 147
  • 84
    • 0040869236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:209, CSM, 2:147; quoted from AT, 7:108, CSM, 2:78.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 108
  • 85
    • 0039683161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:209, CSM, 2:147; quoted from AT, 7:108, CSM, 2:78.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 78
  • 86
    • 0040274941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:209, CSM, 2:147.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 209
  • 87
    • 0040274936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:209, CSM, 2:147.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 147
  • 88
    • 0039683156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 2:209-10, CSM, 2:147, 147-8.
    • AT , vol.2 , pp. 209-210
  • 89
    • 0040274936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 2:209-10, CSM, 2:147, 147-8.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 147
  • 90
    • 0040869200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:210, CSM, 2:147.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 210
  • 91
    • 0040274936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:210, CSM, 2:147.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 147
  • 92
    • 0039090924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:211, CSM, 2:148.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 211
  • 93
    • 0040869198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:211, CSM, 2:148.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 148
  • 94
    • 0039090924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:211, CSM, 2:148.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 211
  • 95
    • 0040869198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:211, CSM, 2:148.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 148
  • 96
    • 0039090924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:211, CSM, 2:148-9.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 211
  • 97
    • 0039090925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:211, CSM, 2:148-9.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 148-149
  • 98
    • 0039090927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:211-12, CSM, 2:149.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 211-212
  • 99
    • 0039090926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:211-12, CSM, 2:149.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 149
  • 100
    • 0039090923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:212, CSM, 2:149.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 212
  • 101
    • 0039090926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:212, CSM, 2:149.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 149
  • 102
    • 0039090923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:212, CSM, 7:149. This is a position Descartes rejects, as we shall see below when examining elements of his voluntarism. Further, the contention that essences are uncreated was not universally accepted. See Suarez, On the Essence of Finite Being as such, on the Existence of that Essence and Their Distinction, trans. Norman J. Wells (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1983), Disputation 31, §2, 57-66. This is not to say that Descartes' views were in complete compliance with Suarez's. On the differences, see Gary Hatfield, "Reason, Nature, and God in Descartes," in Essays on the Philosophy and Science of René Descartes, ed. Stephen Voss (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 269-75.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 212
  • 103
    • 0040274933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:212, CSM, 7:149. This is a position Descartes rejects, as we shall see below when examining elements of his voluntarism. Further, the contention that essences are uncreated was not universally accepted. See Suarez, On the Essence of Finite Being as such, on the Existence of that Essence and Their Distinction, trans. Norman J. Wells (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1983), Disputation 31, §2, 57-66. This is not to say that Descartes' views were in complete compliance with Suarez's. On the differences, see Gary Hatfield, "Reason, Nature, and God in Descartes," in Essays on the Philosophy and Science of René Descartes, ed. Stephen Voss (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 269-75.
    • CSM , vol.7 , pp. 149
  • 104
    • 0040869151 scopus 로고
    • trans. Norman J. Wells Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, Disputation 31, §2
    • AT, 7:212, CSM, 7:149. This is a position Descartes rejects, as we shall see below when examining elements of his voluntarism. Further, the contention that essences are uncreated was not universally accepted. See Suarez, On the Essence of Finite Being as such, on the Existence of that Essence and Their Distinction, trans. Norman J. Wells (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1983), Disputation 31, §2, 57-66. This is not to say that Descartes' views were in complete compliance with Suarez's. On the differences, see Gary Hatfield, "Reason, Nature, and God in Descartes," in Essays on the Philosophy and Science of René Descartes, ed. Stephen Voss (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 269-75.
    • (1983) On the Essence of Finite Being as Such, on the Existence of That Essence and Their Distinction , pp. 57-66
    • Suarez1
  • 105
    • 0040274898 scopus 로고
    • Reason, nature, and god in Descartes
    • ed. Stephen Voss New York: Oxford University Press
    • AT, 7:212, CSM, 7:149. This is a position Descartes rejects, as we shall see below when examining elements of his voluntarism. Further, the contention that essences are uncreated was not universally accepted. See Suarez, On the Essence of Finite Being as such, on the Existence of that Essence and Their Distinction, trans. Norman J. Wells (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1983), Disputation 31, §2, 57-66. This is not to say that Descartes' views were in complete compliance with Suarez's. On the differences, see Gary Hatfield, "Reason, Nature, and God in Descartes," in Essays on the Philosophy and Science of René Descartes, ed. Stephen Voss (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 269-75.
    • (1993) Essays on the Philosophy and Science of René Descartes , pp. 269-275
    • Hatfield, G.1
  • 106
    • 0039090923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:212, CSM, 2:149.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 212
  • 107
    • 0039090926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:212, CSM, 2:149.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 149
  • 108
    • 0040274934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 2:212-13, CSM, 2:149-50.
    • AT , vol.2 , pp. 212-213
  • 109
    • 0040274927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 2:212-13, CSM, 2:149-50.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 149-150
  • 110
    • 0040869183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 18
    • See note 18.
  • 111
    • 0347957435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:235, CSM, 2:164-5.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 235
  • 112
    • 0040274928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:235, CSM, 2:164-5.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 164-165
  • 113
    • 0039090922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:235-6, CSM, 2:165.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 235-236
  • 114
    • 0040869195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:235-6, CSM, 2:165.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 165
  • 115
    • 0040274939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236, CSM, 2:165.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 236
  • 116
    • 0040869195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236, CSM, 2:165.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 165
  • 117
    • 0040274939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236, CSM, 2:165.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 236
  • 118
    • 0040869195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236, CSM, 2:165.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 165
  • 119
    • 0039683152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236-7; CSM, 2:165.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 236-237
  • 120
    • 0040869195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:236-7; CSM, 2:165.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 165
  • 121
    • 0040869191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:238, CSM, 2:166.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 238
  • 122
    • 0040869185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:238, CSM, 2:166.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 166
  • 123
    • 0040869191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:238, CSM, 2:166.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 238
  • 124
    • 0040869185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:238, CSM, 2:166.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 166
  • 125
    • 0040274929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:238-9, CSM, 2:166-7.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 238-239
  • 126
    • 0040869186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:238-9, CSM, 2:166-7.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 166-167
  • 127
    • 0040869143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:243, CSM, 2:170.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 243
  • 128
    • 0039683155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:243, CSM, 2:170.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 170
  • 129
    • 0040274925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:239, CSM, 2:167.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 239
  • 130
    • 0039090914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:239, CSM, 2:167.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 167
  • 131
    • 0039683148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:239-40, CSM, 2:167; see also AT, 7:245, CSM, 2:170-1.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 239-240
  • 132
    • 0039090914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:239-40, CSM, 2:167; see also AT, 7:245, CSM, 2:170-1.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 167
  • 133
    • 0040869178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:239-40, CSM, 2:167; see also AT, 7:245, CSM, 2:170-1.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 245
  • 134
    • 0039090916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:239-40, CSM, 2:167; see also AT, 7:245, CSM, 2:170-1.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 170-171
  • 135
    • 0040869181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We shift from the Cartesian term "indefinite" to "infinite" because Descartes holds that God's causal efficacy is truly infinite. See the following note.
  • 136
    • 0039090915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, AT, 7:220, CSM, 2:155.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 220
  • 137
    • 0039683145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, AT, 7:220, CSM, 2:155.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 155
  • 138
    • 0040274923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:107-8; CSM, 2:78.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 107-108
  • 139
    • 0039683146 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:107-8; CSM, 2:78.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 78
  • 140
    • 0040274924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:85, CSM, 1:155-6; see also AT, 6:112, CSM, 1:165.
    • AT , vol.6 , pp. 85
  • 141
    • 0040869180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:85, CSM, 1:155-6; see also AT, 6:112, CSM, 1:165.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 155-156
  • 142
    • 0040869147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:85, CSM, 1:155-6; see also AT, 6:112, CSM, 1:165.
    • AT , vol.6 , pp. 112
  • 143
    • 0040869179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:85, CSM, 1:155-6; see also AT, 6:112, CSM, 1:165.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 165
  • 144
    • 0040274922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:239, CSM, 2:173n2.
    • AT , vol.6 , pp. 239
  • 145
    • 4244034801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:239, CSM, 2:173n2.
    • CSM , vol.2
  • 146
    • 0040274900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:491-2, CSM, 3:205.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 491-492
  • 147
    • 84873622584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:491-2, CSM, 3:205.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 205
  • 148
    • 0039090876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We examine this is greater detail below.
  • 149
    • 0039683128 scopus 로고
    • ed. Catherine M. Dunn Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College
    • The Logike of the Most Excellent Philosopher P. Ramus Martyr, trans. Roland MacIlmaine (1574), ed. Catherine M. Dunn (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1969), 15. See also William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, 85-6; Thomas Wilson, The Rule of Reason (1553), ed. Richard S. Sprague (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1972), 111-12; John Poinsot (John of St. Thomas), Tractatus de Signis (1632), trans. John N. Deely (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), 382. By a hundred years after Descartes, the formal/efficient causality distinction seems distinctly to have fallen out of favor. Thus it is that Hume, giving the results of his analysis of causation, could write: "We may learn from the foregoing doctrine, that all causes are of the same kind, and that in particular there is no foundation for that distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt efficient causes, and causes sine qua non; or betwixt efficient causes, and formal, and material, and exemplary, and final causes. For as our idea of efficiency is deriv'd from the constant conjunction of two objects, wherever this is observ'd, the cause is efficient; and where it is not, there can never be a cause of any kind"; David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 171. Hume's conclusion is unacceptable. Insofar as he held that the truths of arithmetic and algebra, although perhaps not geometry, are known on the basis of relations of ideas, they are subject to demonstration; see Treatise, 71. Corresponding to every arithmetic or algebraic demonstration, however, there is an explanation from formal causes. It is thus false that "where it is not [for efficient causality], there can never be a cause of any kind." Nonetheless, as history shows, Hume was on the winning side in the intellectual war over the number and kind of causes. Hence, insofar as Descartes' attempt to extend the notion of an efficient cause to God's self-causality, Descartes was on the winning side in the war, even though we must grant that Arnauld won the battle.
    • (1574) The Logike of the Most Excellent Philosopher P. Ramus Martyr , pp. 15
    • MacIlmaine, R.1
  • 150
    • 0039683153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Logike of the Most Excellent Philosopher P. Ramus Martyr, trans. Roland MacIlmaine (1574), ed. Catherine M. Dunn (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1969), 15. See also William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, 85-6; Thomas Wilson, The Rule of Reason (1553), ed. Richard S. Sprague (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1972), 111-12; John Poinsot (John of St. Thomas), Tractatus de Signis (1632), trans. John N. Deely (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), 382. By a hundred years after Descartes, the formal/efficient causality distinction seems distinctly to have fallen out of favor. Thus it is that Hume, giving the results of his analysis of causation, could write: "We may learn from the foregoing doctrine, that all causes are of the same kind, and that in particular there is no foundation for that distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt efficient causes, and causes sine qua non; or betwixt efficient causes, and formal, and material, and exemplary, and final causes. For as our idea of efficiency is deriv'd from the constant conjunction of two objects, wherever this is observ'd, the cause is efficient; and where it is not, there can never be a cause of any kind"; David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 171. Hume's conclusion is unacceptable. Insofar as he held that the truths of arithmetic and algebra, although perhaps not geometry, are known on the basis of relations of ideas, they are subject to demonstration; see Treatise, 71. Corresponding to every arithmetic or algebraic demonstration, however, there is an explanation from formal causes. It is thus false that "where it is not [for efficient causality], there can never be a cause of any kind." Nonetheless, as history shows, Hume was on the winning side in the intellectual war over the number and kind of causes. Hence, insofar as Descartes' attempt to extend the notion of an efficient cause to God's self-causality, Descartes was on the winning side in the war, even though we must grant that Arnauld won the battle.
    • William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic , pp. 85-86
  • 151
    • 0040274896 scopus 로고
    • ed. Richard S. Sprague Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College
    • The Logike of the Most Excellent Philosopher P. Ramus Martyr, trans. Roland MacIlmaine (1574), ed. Catherine M. Dunn (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1969), 15. See also William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, 85-6; Thomas Wilson, The Rule of Reason (1553), ed. Richard S. Sprague (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1972), 111-12; John Poinsot (John of St. Thomas), Tractatus de Signis (1632), trans. John N. Deely (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), 382. By a hundred years after Descartes, the formal/efficient causality distinction seems distinctly to have fallen out of favor. Thus it is that Hume, giving the results of his analysis of causation, could write: "We may learn from the foregoing doctrine, that all causes are of the same kind, and that in particular there is no foundation for that distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt efficient causes, and causes sine qua non; or betwixt efficient causes, and formal, and material, and exemplary, and final causes. For as our idea of efficiency is deriv'd from the constant conjunction of two objects, wherever this is observ'd, the cause is efficient; and where it is not, there can never be a cause of any kind"; David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 171. Hume's conclusion is unacceptable. Insofar as he held that the truths of arithmetic and algebra, although perhaps not geometry, are known on the basis of relations of ideas, they are subject to demonstration; see Treatise, 71. Corresponding to every arithmetic or algebraic demonstration, however, there is an explanation from formal causes. It is thus false that "where it is not [for efficient causality], there can never be a cause of any kind." Nonetheless, as history shows, Hume was on the winning side in the intellectual war over the number and kind of causes. Hence, insofar as Descartes' attempt to extend the notion of an efficient cause to God's self-causality, Descartes was on the winning side in the war, even though we must grant that Arnauld won the battle.
    • (1553) The Rule of Reason , pp. 111-112
    • Wilson, T.1
  • 152
    • 0008694043 scopus 로고
    • trans. John N. Deely Berkeley: University of California Press
    • The Logike of the Most Excellent Philosopher P. Ramus Martyr, trans. Roland MacIlmaine (1574), ed. Catherine M. Dunn (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1969), 15. See also William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, 85-6; Thomas Wilson, The Rule of Reason (1553), ed. Richard S. Sprague (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1972), 111-12; John Poinsot (John of St. Thomas), Tractatus de Signis (1632), trans. John N. Deely (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), 382. By a hundred years after Descartes, the formal/efficient causality distinction seems distinctly to have fallen out of favor. Thus it is that Hume, giving the results of his analysis of causation, could write: "We may learn from the foregoing doctrine, that all causes are of the same kind, and that in particular there is no foundation for that distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt efficient causes, and causes sine qua non; or betwixt efficient causes, and formal, and material, and exemplary, and final causes. For as our idea of efficiency is deriv'd from the constant conjunction of two objects, wherever this is observ'd, the cause is efficient; and where it is not, there can never be a cause of any kind"; David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 171. Hume's conclusion is unacceptable. Insofar as he held that the truths of arithmetic and algebra, although perhaps not geometry, are known on the basis of relations of ideas, they are subject to demonstration; see Treatise, 71. Corresponding to every arithmetic or algebraic demonstration, however, there is an explanation from formal causes. It is thus false that "where it is not [for efficient causality], there can never be a cause of any kind." Nonetheless, as history shows, Hume was on the winning side in the intellectual war over the number and kind of causes. Hence, insofar as Descartes' attempt to extend the notion of an efficient cause to God's self-causality, Descartes was on the winning side in the war, even though we must grant that Arnauld won the battle.
    • (1632) Tractatus de Signis , pp. 382
    • Poinsot, J.1
  • 153
    • 84897850928 scopus 로고
    • ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • The Logike of the Most Excellent Philosopher P. Ramus Martyr, trans. Roland MacIlmaine (1574), ed. Catherine M. Dunn (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1969), 15. See also William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, 85-6; Thomas Wilson, The Rule of Reason (1553), ed. Richard S. Sprague (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1972), 111-12; John Poinsot (John of St. Thomas), Tractatus de Signis (1632), trans. John N. Deely (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), 382. By a hundred years after Descartes, the formal/efficient causality distinction seems distinctly to have fallen out of favor. Thus it is that Hume, giving the results of his analysis of causation, could write: "We may learn from the foregoing doctrine, that all causes are of the same kind, and that in particular there is no foundation for that distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt efficient causes, and causes sine qua non; or betwixt efficient causes, and formal, and material, and exemplary, and final causes. For as our idea of efficiency is deriv'd from the constant conjunction of two objects, wherever this is observ'd, the cause is efficient; and where it is not, there can never be a cause of any kind"; David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 171. Hume's conclusion is unacceptable. Insofar as he held that the truths of arithmetic and algebra, although perhaps not geometry, are known on the basis of relations of ideas, they are subject to demonstration; see Treatise, 71. Corresponding to every arithmetic or algebraic demonstration, however, there is an explanation from formal causes. It is thus false that "where it is not [for efficient causality], there can never be a cause of any kind." Nonetheless, as history shows, Hume was on the winning side in the intellectual war over the number and kind of causes. Hence, insofar as Descartes' attempt to extend the notion of an efficient cause to God's self-causality, Descartes was on the winning side in the war, even though we must grant that Arnauld won the battle.
    • (1978) A Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 171
    • Hume, D.1
  • 154
    • 79955153903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Logike of the Most Excellent Philosopher P. Ramus Martyr, trans. Roland MacIlmaine (1574), ed. Catherine M. Dunn (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1969), 15. See also William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, 85-6; Thomas Wilson, The Rule of Reason (1553), ed. Richard S. Sprague (Northridge, CA: San Fernando Valley State College, 1972), 111-12; John Poinsot (John of St. Thomas), Tractatus de Signis (1632), trans. John N. Deely (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), 382. By a hundred years after Descartes, the formal/efficient causality distinction seems distinctly to have fallen out of favor. Thus it is that Hume, giving the results of his analysis of causation, could write: "We may learn from the foregoing doctrine, that all causes are of the same kind, and that in particular there is no foundation for that distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt efficient causes, and causes sine qua non; or betwixt efficient causes, and formal, and material, and exemplary, and final causes. For as our idea of efficiency is deriv'd from the constant conjunction of two objects, wherever this is observ'd, the cause is efficient; and where it is not, there can never be a cause of any kind"; David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 171. Hume's conclusion is unacceptable. Insofar as he held that the truths of arithmetic and algebra, although perhaps not geometry, are known on the basis of relations of ideas, they are subject to demonstration; see Treatise, 71. Corresponding to every arithmetic or algebraic demonstration, however, there is an explanation from formal causes. It is thus false that "where it is not [for efficient causality], there can never be a cause of any kind." Nonetheless, as history shows, Hume was on the winning side in the intellectual war over the number and kind of causes. Hence, insofar as Descartes' attempt to extend the notion of an efficient cause to God's self-causality, Descartes was on the winning side in the war, even though we must grant that Arnauld won the battle.
    • Treatise , pp. 71
  • 155
    • 0040869143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:243, CSM, 2:170.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 243
  • 156
    • 0039683155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:243, CSM, 2:170.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 170
  • 157
    • 0039683122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Disputation 31, §2
    • Descartes' divine voluntarism regarding essences and eternal truths is not without precedents. See Suarez, On the Essence of Finite Being, Disputation 31, §2, pp. 57-64.
    • On the Essence of Finite Being , pp. 57-64
    • Suarez1
  • 159
    • 0040274893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There is an ambiguity in the expression "natural law." It is sometimes taken to be certain uniformities in nature; at other times it is taken to be statement describing those uniformities. We are using it within this paragraph and the next in the second way, although nothing in our interpretation of Descartes' treatment of natural laws hangs on how we use the expression.
  • 160
    • 0039683124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophers of science often distinguish two kinds of natural law: laws of simultaneity and transtemporal laws. An examination of Descartes' examples of natural laws suggest that they are all laws of simultaneity, though such a construal might be more temporal than Descartes requires; see AT, 9:38-48, CSM, 1:92-8; Principles, 2:37-52. Descartes has a problem with time. Principles 1:57 suggest that he understands time as a theoretical construct; Descartes maintains motion as primary in his physics and time as measured on the basis of arbitrarily chosen motions. A thorough examination of this issue is beyond the scope of the present paper.
    • AT , vol.9 , pp. 38-48
  • 161
    • 0040869144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophers of science often distinguish two kinds of natural law: laws of simultaneity and transtemporal laws. An examination of Descartes' examples of natural laws suggest that they are all laws of simultaneity, though such a construal might be more temporal than Descartes requires; see AT, 9:38-48, CSM, 1:92-8; Principles, 2:37-52. Descartes has a problem with time. Principles 1:57 suggest that he understands time as a theoretical construct; Descartes maintains motion as primary in his physics and time as measured on the basis of arbitrarily chosen motions. A thorough examination of this issue is beyond the scope of the present paper.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 92-98
  • 162
    • 0039090874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophers of science often distinguish two kinds of natural law: laws of simultaneity and transtemporal laws. An examination of Descartes' examples of natural laws suggest that they are all laws of simultaneity, though such a construal might be more temporal than Descartes requires; see AT, 9:38-48, CSM, 1:92-8; Principles, 2:37-52. Descartes has a problem with time. Principles 1:57 suggest that he understands time as a theoretical construct; Descartes maintains motion as primary in his physics and time as measured on the basis of arbitrarily chosen motions. A thorough examination of this issue is beyond the scope of the present paper.
    • Principles , vol.2 , pp. 37-52
  • 163
    • 0039683056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophers of science often distinguish two kinds of natural law: laws of simultaneity and transtemporal laws. An examination of Descartes' examples of natural laws suggest that they are all laws of simultaneity, though such a construal might be more temporal than Descartes requires; see AT, 9:38-48, CSM, 1:92-8; Principles, 2:37-52. Descartes has a problem with time. Principles 1:57 suggest that he understands time as a theoretical construct; Descartes maintains motion as primary in his physics and time as measured on the basis of arbitrarily chosen motions. A thorough examination of this issue is beyond the scope of the present paper.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 57
  • 164
    • 0002218740 scopus 로고
    • Towards an Aristotelian theory of scientific explanation
    • If we are right on this point, of course, it is ironic that the logical positivists were both the foremost proponents of the deductive-nomological account of explanation and purported champions of a nonmetaphysical philosophy of science. See also B. A. Brody, "Towards an Aristotelian Theory of Scientific Explanation," Philosophy of Science 39 (1972): 20-31.
    • (1972) Philosophy of Science , vol.39 , pp. 20-31
    • Brody, B.A.1
  • 165
    • 0040274891 scopus 로고
    • An enquiry concerning human understanding
    • ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 3d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • David Hume, An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, in Enquiries concerning the Human Understanding and concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 3d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), 35 and 37-8. Jonathan Bennett in "Descartes' Theory of Modality," Philosophical Review 103 (1994): 639-67, argues that the domain of the conceivable the possible are one and the same for Descartes. He is uneasy about our argument here. He objects that natural laws are not eternal truths because their falsehood is conceivable. This he takes as one upshot of his paper. We grant Bennett the thesis of his paper, but deny this conclusion. To see why, consider two cases. First, one may confront a necessary truth without recognizing it as such. Hobbes relates with delight his astonishment at finding a seemingly false, indeed, necessarily false, theorem in Euclid's Elements. Only after tracing its deductive ancestry back to Euclid's most basic elements did he recognize that the theorem was not only true, but necessarily so. Hobbes has discovered a feature of nonbasic eternal truths, namely, that those truths derived from the more basic need not be self-evident on first consideration. Second, nor does the apparent conceivability of a state of affairs demonstrate that it is possible. Consider a perpetual motion machine consisting of an electric motor and a generator. The generator produces enough electricity to power the motor, which turns the generator. So far no obvious trouble arises. Upon closer and more careful scrutiny, however, one finds reasons that, while the machine may be possible, it cannot be a perpetual motion machine. Physics tells us that both the motor and generator are subject to friction. Therefore, the system will slowly lose energy that will need to be replaced if the machine were to run perpetually. When all the laws of physics are brought to bear on this system, we discover that what we had taken as a clear and possible idea was not. These two cases show that if the eternal truths are arranged in a hierarchical structure, then one clearly conceives an eternal truth lower in the hierarchy only when one understands its relationships to the more fundamental eternal truths. Thus, if Descartes construed natural laws as lower level eternal truths, then he can at once reject Hume's maxim and embrace Bennett's account of Cartesian modalities.
    • (1975) Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals , pp. 35
    • Hume, D.1
  • 166
    • 0039683052 scopus 로고
    • Descartes' theory of modality
    • David Hume, An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, in Enquiries concerning the Human Understanding and concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 3d ed., rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), 35 and 37-8. Jonathan Bennett in "Descartes' Theory of Modality," Philosophical Review 103 (1994): 639-67, argues that the domain of the conceivable the possible are one and the same for Descartes. He is uneasy about our argument here. He objects that natural laws are not eternal truths because their falsehood is conceivable. This he takes as one upshot of his paper. We grant Bennett the thesis of his paper, but deny this conclusion. To see why, consider two cases. First, one may confront a necessary truth without recognizing it as such. Hobbes relates with delight his astonishment at finding a seemingly false, indeed, necessarily false, theorem in Euclid's Elements. Only after tracing its deductive ancestry back to Euclid's most basic elements did he recognize that the theorem was not only true, but necessarily so. Hobbes has discovered a feature of nonbasic eternal truths, namely, that those truths derived from the more basic need not be self-evident on first consideration. Second, nor does the apparent conceivability of a state of affairs demonstrate that it is possible. Consider a perpetual motion machine consisting of an electric motor and a generator. The generator produces enough electricity to power the motor, which turns the generator. So far no obvious trouble arises. Upon closer and more careful scrutiny, however, one finds reasons that, while the machine may be possible, it cannot be a perpetual motion machine. Physics tells us that both the motor and generator are subject to friction. Therefore, the system will slowly lose energy that will need to be replaced if the machine were to run perpetually. When all the laws of physics are brought to bear on this system, we discover that what we had taken as a clear and possible idea was not. These two cases show that if the eternal truths are arranged in a hierarchical structure, then one clearly conceives an eternal truth lower in the hierarchy only when one understands its relationships to the more fundamental eternal truths. Thus, if Descartes construed natural laws as lower level eternal truths, then he can at once reject Hume's maxim and embrace Bennett's account of Cartesian modalities.
    • (1994) Philosophical Review , vol.103 , pp. 639-667
    • Bennett, J.1
  • 167
    • 0040274890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 1:149-50, CSM, 3:24.
    • AT , vol.1 , pp. 149-150
  • 168
    • 0040869137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 1:149-50, CSM, 3:24.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 24
  • 169
    • 0039683107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 1:152-2, CSM, 3:25, see also AT, 1:145, 152-3, 2:138; CSM, 3:23, 25-6, 103.
    • AT , vol.1 , pp. 152-152
  • 170
    • 0039683117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 1:152-2, CSM, 3:25, see also AT, 1:145, 152-3, 2:138; CSM, 3:23, 25-6, 103.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 25
  • 171
    • 80054553254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 1:152-2, CSM, 3:25, see also AT, 1:145, 152-3, 2:138; CSM, 3:23, 25-6, 103.
    • AT , vol.1 , pp. 145
  • 172
    • 84940264237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 1:152-2, CSM, 3:25, see also AT, 1:145, 152-3, 2:138; CSM, 3:23, 25-6, 103.
    • AT , vol.2 , pp. 138
  • 173
    • 0039683118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 1:152-2, CSM, 3:25, see also AT, 1:145, 152-3, 2:138; CSM, 3:23, 25-6, 103.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 23
  • 174
    • 0039090861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:432, CSM, 2:291.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 432
  • 175
    • 0039683105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:432, CSM, 2:291.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 291
  • 176
    • 0040869136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 2:268, CSM, 3:119; see also AT, 1:476, 3:39; CSM, 3:77, 145.
    • AT , vol.2 , pp. 268
  • 177
    • 0039090864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 2:268, CSM, 3:119; see also AT, 1:476, 3:39; CSM, 3:77, 145.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 119
  • 178
    • 0039683111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 2:268, CSM, 3:119; see also AT, 1:476, 3:39; CSM, 3:77, 145.
    • AT , vol.1 , pp. 476
  • 179
    • 0040869129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 2:268, CSM, 3:119; see also AT, 1:476, 3:39; CSM, 3:77, 145.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 39
  • 180
    • 0039683106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 2:268, CSM, 3:119; see also AT, 1:476, 3:39; CSM, 3:77, 145.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 77
  • 181
    • 0039683112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:43, CSM, 1:132.
    • AT , vol.6 , pp. 43
  • 182
    • 0040274881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:43, CSM, 1:132.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 132
  • 183
    • 0040869131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That he held this should be clear from the fact that, in The World, he introduced the assumption that God will never perform miracles and that "rational souls . . . will not disrupt in any way the ordinary course of nature"; AT, 6:48, CSM, 1:97. Note further that, assuming similar principles, the Descartes of the Principles claimed that all phenomena in the physical world could be explained. See Principles, 3:47, AT, 8A:102-3, CSM, 1:257-8.
    • AT , vol.6 , pp. 48
  • 184
    • 0040274880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That he held this should be clear from the fact that, in The World, he introduced the assumption that God will never perform miracles and that "rational souls . . . will not disrupt in any way the ordinary course of nature"; AT, 6:48, CSM, 1:97. Note further that, assuming similar principles, the Descartes of the Principles claimed that all phenomena in the physical world could be explained. See Principles, 3:47, AT, 8A:102-3, CSM, 1:257-8.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 97
  • 185
    • 0040869122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That he held this should be clear from the fact that, in The World, he introduced the assumption that God will never perform miracles and that "rational souls . . . will not disrupt in any way the ordinary course of nature"; AT, 6:48, CSM, 1:97. Note further that, assuming similar principles, the Descartes of the Principles claimed that all phenomena in the physical world could be explained. See Principles, 3:47, AT, 8A:102-3, CSM, 1:257-8.
    • Principles , vol.3 , pp. 47
  • 186
    • 0039090862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That he held this should be clear from the fact that, in The World, he introduced the assumption that God will never perform miracles and that "rational souls . . . will not disrupt in any way the ordinary course of nature"; AT, 6:48, CSM, 1:97. Note further that, assuming similar principles, the Descartes of the Principles claimed that all phenomena in the physical world could be explained. See Principles, 3:47, AT, 8A:102-3, CSM, 1:257-8.
    • AT , vol.8 A , pp. 102-103
  • 187
    • 0039090859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That he held this should be clear from the fact that, in The World, he introduced the assumption that God will never perform miracles and that "rational souls . . . will not disrupt in any way the ordinary course of nature"; AT, 6:48, CSM, 1:97. Note further that, assuming similar principles, the Descartes of the Principles claimed that all phenomena in the physical world could be explained. See Principles, 3:47, AT, 8A:102-3, CSM, 1:257-8.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 257-258
  • 188
    • 80054398782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:233, CSM, 3:157.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 233
  • 189
    • 0040274859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:233, CSM, 3:157.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 157
  • 190
    • 0040274875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:298, CSM, 3:173. See also the Conversation with Burman, AT, 5:165, CSM, 3:346-7.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 298
  • 191
    • 0040274879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:298, CSM, 3:173. See also the Conversation with Burman, AT, 5:165, CSM, 3:346-7.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 173
  • 192
    • 0039090853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:298, CSM, 3:173. See also the Conversation with Burman, AT, 5:165, CSM, 3:346-7.
    • AT , vol.5 , pp. 165
    • Burman1
  • 193
    • 0039683054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:298, CSM, 3:173. See also the Conversation with Burman, AT, 5:165, CSM, 3:346-7.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 346-347
  • 194
    • 0039683101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 11:43, CSM, 1:96.
    • AT , vol.11 , pp. 43
  • 195
    • 0040274873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 11:43, CSM, 1:96.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 96
  • 196
    • 0040274874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 11:47, CSM, 1:97.
    • AT , vol.11 , pp. 47
  • 197
    • 0040274872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 11:47, CSM, 1:97.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 97
  • 198
    • 0040869067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:17, CSM, 2:12.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 17
  • 199
    • 0040274818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:17, CSM, 2:12.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 12
  • 200
    • 0039090856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:39, CSM, 3:145; see also AT, 1:140-1; CSM, 3:22.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 39
  • 201
    • 0040274819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:39, CSM, 3:145; see also AT, 1:140-1; CSM, 3:22.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 145
  • 202
    • 0040869116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:39, CSM, 3:145; see also AT, 1:140-1; CSM, 3:22.
    • AT , vol.1 , pp. 140-141
  • 203
    • 0040274871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:39, CSM, 3:145; see also AT, 1:140-1; CSM, 3:22.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 22
  • 204
    • 0040274865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles, 4:206, AT, 8A:328-9, CSM, 1:290-1.
    • Principles , vol.4 , pp. 206
  • 205
    • 0039683100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles, 4:206, AT, 8A:328-9, CSM, 1:290-1.
    • AT , vol.8 A , pp. 328-329
  • 206
    • 0040274866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles, 4:206, AT, 8A:328-9, CSM, 1:290-1.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 290-291
  • 207
    • 0039090816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Our discussion assumes that the distinction between God's action(s) and God's character (immutability) collapses. Following traditional theology, speaking of change in God's case can only be metaphorical. God's acts are not in time. Thus, all God's acts are "at the same time" because they are not at any time at all. Descartes accepted the traditional theology in part because he sought to avoid theological controversy. We believe that his theory of time also supports a traditional theology. See note 72.
  • 208
    • 0040869073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles, 1:49, AT, 8A:23-4, CSM, 1:209.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 49
  • 209
    • 0040274820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles, 1:49, AT, 8A:23-4, CSM, 1:209.
    • AT , vol.8 A , pp. 23-24
  • 210
    • 0040869110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles, 1:49, AT, 8A:23-4, CSM, 1:209.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 209
  • 211
    • 0040869068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:41, CSM, 1:131.
    • AT , vol.6 , pp. 41
  • 212
    • 0039683098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 6:41, CSM, 1:131.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 131
  • 213
    • 0039683091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 5:275, CSM, 3:364-5.
    • AT , vol.5 , pp. 275
  • 214
    • 0039683090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 5:275, CSM, 3:364-5.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 364-365
  • 215
    • 0039683096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:57, CSM, 2:40.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 57
  • 216
    • 0039683097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:57, CSM, 2:40.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 40
  • 217
    • 0040274792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375.
    • AT , vol.5 , pp. 347
  • 218
    • 0039683031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 375
  • 219
    • 0040869109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:57, CSM, 2:40; see also POS, §41.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 57
  • 220
    • 0040274864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:57, CSM, 2:40; see also POS, §41.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 40
  • 221
    • 0040869106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §41
    • AT, 7:57, CSM, 2:40; see also POS, §41.
    • POS
  • 222
    • 0040869105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §41
    • POS, §41, AT, 11:359-60, CSM, 1:343.
    • POS
  • 223
    • 0040869074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • POS, §41, AT, 11:359-60, CSM, 1:343.
    • AT , vol.11 , pp. 359-360
  • 224
    • 0039090855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • POS, §41, AT, 11:359-60, CSM, 1:343.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 343
  • 225
    • 84968908931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 4:314, CSM, 3:272.
    • AT , vol.4 , pp. 314
  • 226
    • 0039090857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 4:314, CSM, 3:272.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 272
  • 227
    • 0040869107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:83-8, CSM, 2:58-61.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 83-88
  • 228
    • 0040869069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:83-8, CSM, 2:58-61.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 58-61
  • 229
    • 0039090854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 8B:359, CSM, 1:304. In the optics one finds: "Instead we must hold that it is the movements composing this picture which, acting directly upon our soul in so far as it is united with our body, are ordained by nature to make it have such sensations"; AT, 6:130, CSM, 1:167. We believe that the doctrine of innate ideas suggests that the mind is structured in such a way that there are natural patterns of thought. While the will might be the motive force that begins a chain of thought, affirms and denies propositions, and pushes the process of analysis onward, innate ideas as dispositions to form occurent ideas with a certain content are lawfully organized. For example, if one begins with and idea of God as a magnified idea of oneself and inquires into the adequacy of that idea, this will lead to an idea of God as being that is infinite, omnipotent, omniscient, and so forth, and ultimately to an idea of a supremely perfect being. See Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Descartes' Factitious Ideas of God," Modern Schoolman 66 (1989): 197-208; and Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Innate Ideas and Cartesian Dispositions," International Studies in Philosophy 24 (1992): 65-80. If we are correct, this explains Descartes' confidence that anyone following his method will reach the same conclusions he reached.
    • AT , vol.8 B , pp. 359
  • 230
    • 84921838531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 8B:359, CSM, 1:304. In the optics one finds: "Instead we must hold that it is the movements composing this picture which, acting directly upon our soul in so far as it is united with our body, are ordained by nature to make it have such sensations"; AT, 6:130, CSM, 1:167. We believe that the doctrine of innate ideas suggests that the mind is structured in such a way that there are natural patterns of thought. While the will might be the motive force that begins a chain of thought, affirms and denies propositions, and pushes the process of analysis onward, innate ideas as dispositions to form occurent ideas with a certain content are lawfully organized. For example, if one begins with and idea of God as a magnified idea of oneself and inquires into the adequacy of that idea, this will lead to an idea of God as being that is infinite, omnipotent, omniscient, and so forth, and ultimately to an idea of a supremely perfect being. See Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Descartes' Factitious Ideas of God," Modern Schoolman 66 (1989): 197-208; and Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Innate Ideas and Cartesian Dispositions," International Studies in Philosophy 24 (1992): 65-80. If we are correct, this explains Descartes' confidence that anyone following his method will reach the same conclusions he reached.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 304
  • 231
    • 0040274821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 8B:359, CSM, 1:304. In the optics one finds: "Instead we must hold that it is the movements composing this picture which, acting directly upon our soul in so far as it is united with our body, are ordained by nature to make it have such sensations"; AT, 6:130, CSM, 1:167. We believe that the doctrine of innate ideas suggests that the mind is structured in such a way that there are natural patterns of thought. While the will might be the motive force that begins a chain of thought, affirms and denies propositions, and pushes the process of analysis onward, innate ideas as dispositions to form occurent ideas with a certain content are lawfully organized. For example, if one begins with and idea of God as a magnified idea of oneself and inquires into the adequacy of that idea, this will lead to an idea of God as being that is infinite, omnipotent, omniscient, and so forth, and ultimately to an idea of a supremely perfect being. See Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Descartes' Factitious Ideas of God," Modern Schoolman 66 (1989): 197-208; and Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Innate Ideas and Cartesian Dispositions," International Studies in Philosophy 24 (1992): 65-80. If we are correct, this explains Descartes' confidence that anyone following his method will reach the same conclusions he reached.
    • AT , vol.6 , pp. 130
  • 232
    • 0040869070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 8B:359, CSM, 1:304. In the optics one finds: "Instead we must hold that it is the movements composing this picture which, acting directly upon our soul in so far as it is united with our body, are ordained by nature to make it have such sensations"; AT, 6:130, CSM, 1:167. We believe that the doctrine of innate ideas suggests that the mind is structured in such a way that there are natural patterns of thought. While the will might be the motive force that begins a chain of thought, affirms and denies propositions, and pushes the process of analysis onward, innate ideas as dispositions to form occurent ideas with a certain content are lawfully organized. For example, if one begins with and idea of God as a magnified idea of oneself and inquires into the adequacy of that idea, this will lead to an idea of God as being that is infinite, omnipotent, omniscient, and so forth, and ultimately to an idea of a supremely perfect being. See Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Descartes' Factitious Ideas of God," Modern Schoolman 66 (1989): 197-208; and Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Innate Ideas and Cartesian Dispositions," International Studies in Philosophy 24 (1992): 65-80. If we are correct, this explains Descartes' confidence that anyone following his method will reach the same conclusions he reached.
    • CSM , vol.1 , pp. 167
  • 233
    • 0039683032 scopus 로고
    • Descartes' factitious ideas of god
    • AT, 8B:359, CSM, 1:304. In the optics one finds: "Instead we must hold that it is the movements composing this picture which, acting directly upon our soul in so far as it is united with our body, are ordained by nature to make it have such sensations"; AT, 6:130, CSM, 1:167. We believe that the doctrine of innate ideas suggests that the mind is structured in such a way that there are natural patterns of thought. While the will might be the motive force that begins a chain of thought, affirms and denies propositions, and pushes the process of analysis onward, innate ideas as dispositions to form occurent ideas with a certain content are lawfully organized. For example, if one begins with and idea of God as a magnified idea of oneself and inquires into the adequacy of that idea, this will lead to an idea of God as being that is infinite, omnipotent, omniscient, and so forth, and ultimately to an idea of a supremely perfect being. See Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Descartes' Factitious Ideas of God," Modern Schoolman 66 (1989): 197-208; and Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Innate Ideas and Cartesian Dispositions," International Studies in Philosophy 24 (1992): 65-80. If we are correct, this explains Descartes' confidence that anyone following his method will reach the same conclusions he reached.
    • (1989) Modern Schoolman , vol.66 , pp. 197-208
    • Flage, D.E.1    Bonnen, C.A.2
  • 234
    • 0039683040 scopus 로고
    • Innate ideas and cartesian dispositions
    • AT, 8B:359, CSM, 1:304. In the optics one finds: "Instead we must hold that it is the movements composing this picture which, acting directly upon our soul in so far as it is united with our body, are ordained by nature to make it have such sensations"; AT, 6:130, CSM, 1:167. We believe that the doctrine of innate ideas suggests that the mind is structured in such a way that there are natural patterns of thought. While the will might be the motive force that begins a chain of thought, affirms and denies propositions, and pushes the process of analysis onward, innate ideas as dispositions to form occurent ideas with a certain content are lawfully organized. For example, if one begins with and idea of God as a magnified idea of oneself and inquires into the adequacy of that idea, this will lead to an idea of God as being that is infinite, omnipotent, omniscient, and so forth, and ultimately to an idea of a supremely perfect being. See Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Descartes' Factitious Ideas of God," Modern Schoolman 66 (1989): 197-208; and Daniel E. Flage and Clarence A. Bonnen, "Innate Ideas and Cartesian Dispositions," International Studies in Philosophy 24 (1992): 65-80. If we are correct, this explains Descartes' confidence that anyone following his method will reach the same conclusions he reached.
    • (1992) International Studies in Philosophy , vol.24 , pp. 65-80
    • Flage, D.E.1    Bonnen, C.A.2
  • 236
    • 0040274810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:665, CSM, 3:218.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 665
  • 237
    • 0040274812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:665, CSM, 3:218.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 218
  • 238
    • 0040274810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:665, CSM, 3:218; see also AT, 3:690-1; CSM, 3:226.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 665
  • 239
    • 0040274812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:665, CSM, 3:218; see also AT, 3:690-1; CSM, 3:226.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 218
  • 240
    • 0040274814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:665, CSM, 3:218; see also AT, 3:690-1; CSM, 3:226.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 690-691
  • 241
    • 0040274817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:665, CSM, 3:218; see also AT, 3:690-1; CSM, 3:226.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 226
  • 242
    • 0039090814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:665-6, CSM, 2:218, emphasis added.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 665-666
  • 243
    • 0040869065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis added
    • AT, 7:665-6, CSM, 2:218, emphasis added.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 218
  • 244
    • 0040274815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:666-7, CSM, 2:219.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 666-667
  • 245
    • 0039683051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:666-7, CSM, 2:219.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 219
  • 246
    • 0039090812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles, 1:48.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 48
  • 247
    • 0039683053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:667-8, CSM, 3:218-19; see also AT, 3:693-4, 7:441-2; CSM, 3:227-8, 2:297-8.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 667-668
  • 248
    • 0040869063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:667-8, CSM, 3:218-19; see also AT, 3:693-4, 7:441-2; CSM, 3:227-8, 2:297-8.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 218-219
  • 249
    • 0040274816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:667-8, CSM, 3:218-19; see also AT, 3:693-4, 7:441-2; CSM, 3:227-8, 2:297-8.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 693-694
  • 250
    • 0040869064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:667-8, CSM, 3:218-19; see also AT, 3:693-4, 7:441-2; CSM, 3:227-8, 2:297-8.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 441-442
  • 251
    • 0039683050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:667-8, CSM, 3:218-19; see also AT, 3:693-4, 7:441-2; CSM, 3:227-8, 2:297-8.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 227-228
  • 252
    • 0039090813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:667-8, CSM, 3:218-19; see also AT, 3:693-4, 7:441-2; CSM, 3:227-8, 2:297-8.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 297-298
  • 253
    • 0003576582 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Daniel Garber presents an extended account of Descartes' views on substantial forms in his Descartes' Metaphysical Physics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 95-103.
    • (1992) Descartes' Metaphysical Physics , pp. 95-103
    • Garber, D.1
  • 254
    • 0040869045 scopus 로고
    • The unity of descartes' man
    • In "The Unity of Descartes' Man," Philosophical Review 95 (1986): 339-70, Paul Hoffman argues that the union between mind and body is substantial. In "Descartes: The End of Anthropology," in Reason, Will and Sensation: Studies in Descartes's Metaphysics, ed. J. Cottingham (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), 273-306, Stephen Voss argues that Descartes did not have a settled view on the nature of human beings. While the Descartes of the Meditations might have held that there is a substantial unity between the human soul and the human body, the Descartes of the Principles and later did not clearly hold that the notion of a human being is significant, at least in any sense in which the mind and body ontologically constitute one entity.
    • (1986) Philosophical Review , vol.95 , pp. 339-370
  • 255
    • 84856630484 scopus 로고
    • Descartes: The end of anthropology
    • ed. J. Cottingham Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • In "The Unity of Descartes' Man," Philosophical Review 95 (1986): 339-70, Paul Hoffman argues that the union between mind and body is substantial. In "Descartes: The End of Anthropology," in Reason, Will and Sensation: Studies in Descartes's Metaphysics, ed. J. Cottingham (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), 273-306, Stephen Voss argues that Descartes did not have a settled view on the nature of human beings. While the Descartes of the Meditations might have held that there is a substantial unity between the human soul and the human body, the Descartes of the Principles and later did not
    • (1994) Reason, Will and Sensation: Studies in Descartes's Metaphysics , pp. 273-306
    • Hoffman, P.1
  • 256
    • 0040274807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:14, CSM, 2:10.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 14
  • 257
    • 0040869059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:14, CSM, 2:10.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 10
  • 258
    • 0039683042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:64, CSM, 2:44-5.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 64
  • 259
    • 0040869058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:64, CSM, 2:44-5.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 44-45
  • 260
    • 0040274810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:665, CSM, 3:218.
    • AT , vol.3 , pp. 665
  • 261
    • 0040274812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 3:665, CSM, 3:218.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 218
  • 262
    • 0039683044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:219, CSM, 2:115, emphasis added.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 219
  • 263
    • 0039683041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis added
    • AT, 7:219, CSM, 2:115, emphasis added.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 115
  • 265
    • 0040869051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:444-5, CSM, 2:299.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 444-445
  • 266
    • 0042142444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See AT, 7:444-5, CSM, 2:299.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 299
  • 267
    • 0040869049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:222, CSM, 2:157.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 222
  • 268
    • 0040869048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AT, 7:222, CSM, 2:157.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 157
  • 269
    • 0040274805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 49
  • 270
    • 0040869050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 33
  • 271
    • 0039090800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Descartes and occasionalism
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • Descartes' Metaphysical Physics , pp. 299-305
    • Garber1
  • 272
    • 0040274792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • AT , vol.5 , pp. 347
  • 273
    • 0039683031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • CSM , vol.3 , pp. 375
  • 274
    • 0039683036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • AT , vol.9 A , pp. 213
  • 275
    • 0039090799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 275-276
  • 276
    • 0040274784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • AT , vol.7 , pp. 165-166
  • 277
    • 0042643373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • CSM , vol.2 , pp. 117
  • 278
    • 0040869037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some will argue that even if we have shown that one can read Descartes' discussions of mind-body interaction in terms of formal causes, we have not solved the problem of mind-body or even body-body interaction in Descartes, since the problem of interaction presupposes the notion of efficient causality. Insofar as Descartes claimed that there is only a conceptual distinction between creation and preservation (AT, 7:49, 109, 110; CSM, 2:33, 79), we must at least explain how God continually recreates these laws, that is, how God acts in such a way that the relations between created entities appear to be lawful. Does not our account, we would be asked, follow Garber's views (Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, 299-305, "Descartes and Occasionalism") and turn Descartes into at least a quasi-occasionalist? No. First, if one takes seriously Descartes' claim that the best model we have for divine will is human will (AT, 5:347, CSM, 3:375), and if one recognizes Cartesian beliefs are subject to the will, then a belief is the result of an act of the will, and any given belief will be retained until such a time as it is rescinded by some other act. If one applies this will-it-and-forget-it-forever theory of belief in the divine case, there is no reason to assume that God is continually acting behind the scenes to make sure all the laws are followed. This also fits nicely with the notion that God is immutable. Second, the question, "What is God doing?" is properly a theological question, and Descartes regularly indicates that theological questions, properly so called, are beyond the scope of his investigations. Third, Descartes claims he did not explain the nature of the unity between body and soul. Notice what he wrote to Clerselier: "These questions [how can the soul move the body if it is in no way material, and how can it receive the forms (espèces) of corporeal objects?] presuppose amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body, which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other. Yet those who admit of real accidents like heat, weight and so on, have no doubt that these accidents act on the body; but there is much more of a difference between them and it, i.e., between accidents and a substance, than there is between two substances"; AT, 9A:213, CSM, 2:275-6. Finally, occasionalism seems to be inconsistent with Descartes' theory of substance. Insofar as he draws a distinction between infinite substance, finite substance, and modes on the basis of independence (AT, 7:165-6, CSM, 2:117, Principles, 1:51), to suggest that God literally recreates the world at every moment would seem to collapse the distinction between finite substance and mode. If both a finite substance and the modes that clothe it depend solely on a God that recreates them every moment, neither is more independent than the other the substance-mode complex is reduced to a series of temporal slices and a finite substance, as such, would be nothing more than an abstraction from such a series of temporal slices. On such a view, the temporal slices, as such, would possess a greater degree of independence (reality) than the finite substances abstracted from them. Of course Descartes' official ontology provides no slot for a temporal slice as such. For these reasons, while granting that we have little understanding of the Cartesian God as an efficient cause, we would reject occasionalism as a plausible option.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 51


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.