-
1
-
-
0031507203
-
The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of Law
-
June develops the game-theoretic basis for a rational choice model along these lines. Although my argument here focuses on social practices and values rather than on rational choice, it is compatible with Weingast's model. I received very helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper delivered at New York University, the University of California at Santa Cruz, Stanford University, and Princeton University's Center for Human Values. Special thanks to Barry Strauss and Phillip Mitsis, for discussions that led to the writing of this paper, and to Emily Mackil for editorial assistance and substantive comments
-
Barry R. Weingast, "The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of Law," American Political Science Review 91, no. 2 (June 1997): 245-63, develops the game-theoretic basis for a rational choice model along these lines. Although my argument here focuses on social practices and values rather than on rational choice, it is compatible with Weingast's model. I received very helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper delivered at New York University, the University of California at Santa Cruz, Stanford University, and Princeton University's Center for Human Values. Special thanks to Barry Strauss and Phillip Mitsis, for discussions that led to the writing of this paper, and to Emily Mackil for editorial assistance and substantive comments.
-
(1997)
American Political Science Review
, vol.91
, Issue.2
, pp. 245-263
-
-
Weingast, B.R.1
-
2
-
-
0004616144
-
The Rise of Illiberal Democracy
-
November/ December
-
Fareed Zakaria, "The Rise of Illiberal Democracy," Foreign Affairs 76, no. 6 (November/ December 1997): 23-43. For a good discussion of the traditional conflict between the liberal "rights of the moderns" (religious liberty; liberty of conscience, thought, and expression; rights of person and property) and the democratic "rights of the ancients" (freedom of political speech, and participation rights), and an argument that these can be conjoined within a conception of deliberative democracy based on reasonable plurality, see Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 94-119.
-
(1997)
Foreign Affairs
, vol.76
, Issue.6
, pp. 23-43
-
-
Zakaria, F.1
-
3
-
-
0004616144
-
Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy
-
ed. Seyla Benhabib Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
Fareed Zakaria, "The Rise of Illiberal Democracy," Foreign Affairs 76, no. 6 (November/ December 1997): 23-43. For a good discussion of the traditional conflict between the liberal "rights of the moderns" (religious liberty; liberty of conscience, thought, and expression; rights of person and property) and the democratic "rights of the ancients" (freedom of political speech, and participation rights), and an argument that these can be conjoined within a conception of deliberative democracy based on reasonable plurality, see Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 94-119.
-
(1996)
Democracy and Difference
, pp. 94-119
-
-
Cohen, J.1
-
4
-
-
0343267056
-
-
Zakaria, "Rise of Illiberal Democracy," 28. Zakaria's examples of constitutional liberalism leading to democracy include nineteenth-century Britain, Hong Kong, and contemporary "semi-democratic" East Asian regimes. His examples of democracy failing to bring about constitutional liberalism include sub-Saharan Africa, Haiti, Central Asia, and "the Islamic world" (ibid., 26-29).
-
Rise of Illiberal Democracy
, pp. 28
-
-
Zakaria1
-
5
-
-
0343267056
-
-
Zakaria, "Rise of Illiberal Democracy," 28. Zakaria's examples of constitutional liberalism leading to democracy include nineteenth-century Britain, Hong Kong, and contemporary "semi-democratic" East Asian regimes. His examples of democracy failing to bring about constitutional liberalism include sub-Saharan Africa, Haiti, Central Asia, and "the Islamic world" (ibid., 26-29).
-
Rise of Illiberal Democracy
, pp. 26-29
-
-
-
7
-
-
0003275369
-
The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with that of the Moderns
-
Benjamin Constant, ed. and trans. Biancamaria Fontana Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Benjamin Constant, "The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with That of the Moderns," in Benjamin Constant, Political Writings, ed. and trans. Biancamaria Fontana (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 307-28; Isaiah Berlin, "Two Concepts of Liberty," in Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 163ff., esp. 164f. On Berlin's conception of negative liberty and his debt to Constant, see John Gray, Isaiah Berlin (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 5-37, esp. 20. The Berlin quotes in this paragraph are drawn from "Two Concepts of Liberty," 14, 56, cited by Quentin Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 115.
-
(1988)
Political Writings
, pp. 307-328
-
-
Constant, B.1
-
8
-
-
0002068898
-
Two Concepts of Liberty
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Benjamin Constant, "The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with That of the Moderns," in Benjamin Constant, Political Writings, ed. and trans. Biancamaria Fontana (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 307-28; Isaiah Berlin, "Two Concepts of Liberty," in Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 163ff., esp. 164f. On Berlin's conception of negative liberty and his debt to Constant, see John Gray, Isaiah Berlin (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 5-37, esp. 20. The Berlin quotes in this paragraph are drawn from "Two Concepts of Liberty," 14, 56, cited by Quentin Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 115.
-
(1969)
Four Essays on Liberty
-
-
Berlin, I.1
-
9
-
-
0004199332
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press, esp. 20
-
Benjamin Constant, "The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with That of the Moderns," in Benjamin Constant, Political Writings, ed. and trans. Biancamaria Fontana (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 307-28; Isaiah Berlin, "Two Concepts of Liberty," in Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 163ff., esp. 164f. On Berlin's conception of negative liberty and his debt to Constant, see John Gray, Isaiah Berlin (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 5-37, esp. 20. The Berlin quotes in this paragraph are drawn from "Two Concepts of Liberty," 14, 56, cited by Quentin Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 115.
-
(1996)
Isaiah Berlin
, pp. 5-37
-
-
Gray, J.1
-
10
-
-
0004178539
-
-
Benjamin Constant, "The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with That of the Moderns," in Benjamin Constant, Political Writings, ed. and trans. Biancamaria Fontana (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 307-28; Isaiah Berlin, "Two Concepts of Liberty," in Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 163ff., esp. 164f. On Berlin's conception of negative liberty and his debt to Constant, see John Gray, Isaiah Berlin (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 5-37, esp. 20. The Berlin quotes in this paragraph are drawn from "Two Concepts of Liberty," 14, 56, cited by Quentin Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 115.
-
Two Concepts of Liberty
, pp. 14
-
-
-
11
-
-
0004260025
-
-
Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press
-
Benjamin Constant, "The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with That of the Moderns," in Benjamin Constant, Political Writings, ed. and trans. Biancamaria Fontana (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 307-28; Isaiah Berlin, "Two Concepts of Liberty," in Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 163ff., esp. 164f. On Berlin's conception of negative liberty and his debt to Constant, see John Gray, Isaiah Berlin (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 5-37, esp. 20. The Berlin quotes in this paragraph are drawn from "Two Concepts of Liberty," 14, 56, cited by Quentin Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 115.
-
(1998)
Liberty before Liberalism
, pp. 115
-
-
Skinner, Q.1
-
13
-
-
0039318012
-
Equalities and Inequalities in Athenian Democracy
-
ed. Josiah Ober and Charles Hedrick Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
For a general discussion of Athenian democratic equality, see Kurt A. Raaflaub, "Equalities and Inequalities in Athenian Democracy," in Demokratia: A Conversation on Democracies, Ancient and Modern, ed. Josiah Ober and Charles Hedrick (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 139-74.
-
(1996)
Demokratia: A Conversation on Democracies, Ancient and Modern
, pp. 139-174
-
-
Raaflaub, K.A.1
-
15
-
-
0010198406
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press esp. ch. 6
-
The story of how the dêmos came to be defined in terms of "non-leisured" Athenians (or, conversely all native adult males) rather than in terms of the elite is important and interesting but is not my main focus here: cf. Josiah Ober, The Athenian Revolution: Essays on Ancient Greek Democracy and Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1996), esp. ch. 6; Victor D. Hanson, "Hoplites into Democrats: The Changing Ideology of Athenian Infantry," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 289-312; Barry S. Strauss, "The Athenian Trireme School of Democracy," in ibid., 313-26; and my exchange with Kurt Raaflaub in Democracy 2500? Questions and Challenges, ed. K. Raaflaub and I. Morris, Archaeological Institute of America, Colloquia and Conference Papers 2 (Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 1998), 67-85.
-
(1996)
The Athenian Revolution: Essays on Ancient Greek Democracy and Political Theory
-
-
Ober, J.1
-
16
-
-
60950549399
-
Hoplites into Democrats: The Changing Ideology of Athenian Infantry
-
ed. Ober and Hedrick
-
The story of how the dêmos came to be defined in terms of "non-leisured" Athenians (or, conversely all native adult males) rather than in terms of the elite is important and interesting but is not my main focus here: cf. Josiah Ober, The Athenian Revolution: Essays on Ancient Greek Democracy and Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1996), esp. ch. 6; Victor D. Hanson, "Hoplites into Democrats: The Changing Ideology of Athenian Infantry," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 289-312; Barry S. Strauss, "The Athenian Trireme School of Democracy," in ibid., 313-26; and my exchange with Kurt Raaflaub in Democracy 2500? Questions and Challenges, ed. K. Raaflaub and I. Morris, Archaeological Institute of America, Colloquia and Conference Papers 2 (Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 1998), 67-85.
-
Demokratia
, pp. 289-312
-
-
Hanson, V.D.1
-
17
-
-
78049378548
-
The Athenian Trireme School of Democracy
-
The story of how the dêmos came to be defined in terms of "non-leisured" Athenians (or, conversely all native adult males) rather than in terms of the elite is important and interesting but is not my main focus here: cf. Josiah Ober, The Athenian Revolution: Essays on Ancient Greek Democracy and Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1996), esp. ch. 6; Victor D. Hanson, "Hoplites into Democrats: The Changing Ideology of Athenian Infantry," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 289-312; Barry S. Strauss, "The Athenian Trireme School of Democracy," in ibid., 313-26; and my exchange with Kurt Raaflaub in Democracy 2500? Questions and Challenges, ed. K. Raaflaub and I. Morris, Archaeological Institute of America, Colloquia and Conference Papers 2 (Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 1998), 67-85.
-
Demokratia
, pp. 313-326
-
-
Strauss, B.S.1
-
18
-
-
0039318013
-
-
ed. K. Raaflaub and I. Morris, Archaeological Institute of America, Colloquia and Conference Papers 2 Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt
-
The story of how the dêmos came to be defined in terms of "non-leisured" Athenians (or, conversely all native adult males) rather than in terms of the elite is important and interesting but is not my main focus here: cf. Josiah Ober, The Athenian Revolution: Essays on Ancient Greek Democracy and Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1996), esp. ch. 6; Victor D. Hanson, "Hoplites into Democrats: The Changing Ideology of Athenian Infantry," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 289-312; Barry S. Strauss, "The Athenian Trireme School of Democracy," in ibid., 313-26; and my exchange with Kurt Raaflaub in Democracy 2500? Questions and Challenges, ed. K. Raaflaub and I. Morris, Archaeological Institute of America, Colloquia and Conference Papers 2 (Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 1998), 67-85.
-
(1998)
Democracy 2500? Questions and Challenges
, pp. 67-85
-
-
Raaflaub, K.1
-
19
-
-
0039910372
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
See Virginia J. Hunter, Policing Athens: Social Control in the Attic Lawsuits, 420-320 B.C. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994); and David Cohen, Law, Sexuality, and Society: The Enforcement of Morals in Classical Athens (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
-
(1994)
Policing Athens: Social Control in the Attic Lawsuits, 420-320 B.C.
-
-
Hunter, V.J.1
-
20
-
-
0040503305
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See Virginia J. Hunter, Policing Athens: Social Control in the Attic Lawsuits, 420-320 B.C. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994); and David Cohen, Law, Sexuality, and Society: The Enforcement of Morals in Classical Athens (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
-
(1991)
Law, Sexuality, and Society: The Enforcement of Morals in Classical Athens
-
-
Cohen, D.1
-
21
-
-
0004319381
-
-
ed. and trans. Benjamin Jowett Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, ed. and trans. Benjamin Jowett (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1881), with revisions of Simon Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991), 2.37.2.
-
(1881)
The Peloponnesian War
-
-
Thucydides1
-
22
-
-
0009134666
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, ed. and trans. Benjamin Jowett (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1881), with revisions of Simon Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991), 2.37.2.
-
(1991)
A Commentary on Thucydides
, pp. 2372
-
-
Hornblower, S.1
-
23
-
-
0039318009
-
-
Herning, Denmark: Systime, The number of foreign residents and slaves was large, but cannot be accurately estimated. In any event, citizens cannot have been more than about one-fifth of the total population at any time during the democracy
-
On Athenian demographics, see Mogens H. Hansen, Demography and Democracy: The Number of Athenian Citizens in the Fourth Century B.C. (Herning, Denmark: Systime, 1985). The number of foreign residents and slaves was large, but cannot be accurately estimated. In any event, citizens cannot have been more than about one-fifth of the total population at any time during the democracy.
-
(1985)
Demography and Democracy: The Number of Athenian Citizens in the Fourth Century B.C.
-
-
Hansen, M.H.1
-
24
-
-
0038617524
-
-
ch. 11, and the literature cited therein
-
On this distinction, see Ober, Athenian Revolution, ch. 11, and the literature cited therein.
-
Athenian Revolution
-
-
Ober1
-
25
-
-
0038622731
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
On the bipolarity of Athenians and others, see Paul Cartledge, The Greeks: A Portrait of Self and Others (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993); on the link between this bipolarity and democracy, see Jennifer Tolbert Roberts, "Athenian Equality: A Constant Surrounded by Flux," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 187-202; on racism and misogyny, see Ian Morris, Archaeology as Cultural History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming).
-
(1993)
The Greeks: A Portrait of Self and Others
-
-
Cartledge, P.1
-
26
-
-
84883911155
-
Athenian Equality: A Constant Surrounded by Flux
-
ed. Ober and Hedrick
-
On the bipolarity of Athenians and others, see Paul Cartledge, The Greeks: A Portrait of Self and Others (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993); on the link between this bipolarity and democracy, see Jennifer Tolbert Roberts, "Athenian Equality: A Constant Surrounded by Flux," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 187-202; on racism and misogyny, see Ian Morris, Archaeology as Cultural History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming).
-
Demokratia
, pp. 187-202
-
-
Roberts, J.T.1
-
27
-
-
0040503304
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming
-
On the bipolarity of Athenians and others, see Paul Cartledge, The Greeks: A Portrait of Self and Others (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993); on the link between this bipolarity and democracy, see Jennifer Tolbert Roberts, "Athenian Equality: A Constant Surrounded by Flux," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 187-202; on racism and misogyny, see Ian Morris, Archaeology as Cultural History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming).
-
Archaeology As Cultural History
-
-
Morris, I.1
-
29
-
-
0039318010
-
-
note
-
The distinctions between what people say and what they do, and between what people say in official circumstances and what they say among intimates, is relevant here, but hard to specify.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
0038617524
-
-
ch. 5, on the inevitability of criticism
-
See, for example, Ober, Athenian Revolution, ch. 5, on the inevitability of criticism.
-
Athenian Revolution
-
-
Ober1
-
31
-
-
84919454060
-
-
New York: Routledge
-
Judith Butler, Excitable Speech: A Politics of the Performative (New York: Routledge, 1997), offers one account of the relationship between performance and culture; my thanks to Susan Lape for clarifying for me how Butler's work can be applied to Athens. My own understanding of how dominant ideologies are challenged by alternative performances is sketched in Athenian Revolution, 148-54.
-
(1997)
Excitable Speech: A Politics of the Performative
-
-
Butler, J.1
-
32
-
-
0038617524
-
-
Judith Butler, Excitable Speech: A Politics of the Performative (New York: Routledge, 1997), offers one account of the relationship between performance and culture; my thanks to Susan Lape for clarifying for me how Butler's work can be applied to Athens. My own understanding of how dominant ideologies are challenged by alternative performances is sketched in Athenian Revolution, 148-54.
-
Athenian Revolution
, pp. 148-154
-
-
-
34
-
-
0040503304
-
-
ch. 4. In my own work, I have tended to use the term "ideology" to cover aspects of both thought and practice, and it is important to keep in mind that there is no practical way to segregate "mentality" from "ideology" in the thought of any given person at any given time
-
Ibid., ch. 4. In my own work, I have tended to use the term "ideology" to cover aspects of both thought and practice, and it is important to keep in mind that there is no practical way to segregate "mentality" from "ideology" in the thought of any given person at any given time.
-
Archaeology As Cultural History
-
-
-
35
-
-
0041097392
-
-
note
-
Chattel slaves, either Greek prisoners of war or (more often) non-Greeks imported specifically to serve as slaves, could be bought and sold as ordinary property. Helots and other unfree "serfs" were tied to the land; they could not be bought or sold, but otherwise lacked liberties and immunities.
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
0039317965
-
The Strong Principle of Equality and the Archaic Origins of Greek Democracy
-
ed. Ober and Hedrick
-
See Ian Morris, "The Strong Principle of Equality and the Archaic Origins of Greek Democracy," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 19-48; Leslie Kurke, "The Politics of Habrosunê in Archaic Greece," Classical Antiquity 11 (1992): 91-120; and (believing the metrios ideal to be a reality rather than an ideology) Hanson, "Hoplites into Democrats."
-
Demokratia
, pp. 19-48
-
-
Morris, I.1
-
37
-
-
84968136042
-
The Politics of Habrosunê in Archaic Greece
-
See Ian Morris, "The Strong Principle of Equality and the Archaic Origins of Greek Democracy," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 19-48; Leslie Kurke, "The Politics of Habrosunê in Archaic Greece," Classical Antiquity 11 (1992): 91-120; and (believing the metrios ideal to be a reality rather than an ideology) Hanson, "Hoplites into Democrats."
-
(1992)
Classical Antiquity
, vol.11
, pp. 91-120
-
-
Kurke, L.1
-
38
-
-
60950549399
-
-
See Ian Morris, "The Strong Principle of Equality and the Archaic Origins of Greek Democracy," in Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick, 19-48; Leslie Kurke, "The Politics of Habrosunê in Archaic Greece," Classical Antiquity 11 (1992): 91-120; and (believing the metrios ideal to be a reality rather than an ideology) Hanson, "Hoplites into Democrats."
-
Hoplites into Democrats
-
-
Hanson1
-
41
-
-
0039910322
-
-
For the struggle between the habrosunê mentality and the metrios mentality, see Morris, "Strong Principle of Equality"; Kurke, "Politics of Habrosunê"; and Kurke, The Politics of Meaning in Archaic Greece: Coinage, Bodies, Games, and Gold (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000).
-
Strong Principle of Equality
-
-
Morris1
-
42
-
-
0039317963
-
-
For the struggle between the habrosunê mentality and the metrios mentality, see Morris, "Strong Principle of Equality"; Kurke, "Politics of Habrosunê"; and Kurke, The Politics of Meaning in Archaic Greece: Coinage, Bodies, Games, and Gold (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000).
-
Politics of Habrosunê
-
-
Kurke1
-
43
-
-
0040503272
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
For the struggle between the habrosunê mentality and the metrios mentality, see Morris, "Strong Principle of Equality"; Kurke, "Politics of Habrosunê"; and Kurke, The Politics of Meaning in Archaic Greece: Coinage, Bodies, Games, and Gold (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000).
-
(2000)
The Politics of Meaning in Archaic Greece: Coinage, Bodies, Games, and Gold
-
-
Kurke1
-
44
-
-
4243862944
-
-
ed. and trans. David Ames Curtis Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press
-
On the centrality of politics, see Pierre Lèvêque and Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Cleisthenes the Athenian: An Essay on the Representation of Space and Time in Greek Political Thought from the End of the Sixth Century to the Death of Plato, ed. and trans. David Ames Curtis (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1996); Christian Meier, The Greek Discovery of Politics, trans. David McLintock (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990); and Jean-Pierre Vernant, The Origins of Greek Thought (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1982). My argument does not embrace extreme claims about the "primacy of politics" in Greek culture (see, e.g., Paul A. Rahe, Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution [Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1992]), but it likewise rejects the attempt to read Athens as primarily family- and cult-centered (see, e.g., Cynthia Patterson, The Family in Greek History [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998]).
-
(1996)
Cleisthenes the Athenian: An Essay on the Representation of Space and Time in Greek Political Thought from the End of the Sixth Century to the Death of Plato
-
-
Lèvêque, P.1
Vidal-Naquet, P.2
-
45
-
-
0011804115
-
-
trans. David McLintock Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
On the centrality of politics, see Pierre Lèvêque and Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Cleisthenes the Athenian: An Essay on the Representation of Space and Time in Greek Political Thought from the End of the Sixth Century to the Death of Plato, ed. and trans. David Ames Curtis (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1996); Christian Meier, The Greek Discovery of Politics, trans. David McLintock (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990); and Jean-Pierre Vernant, The Origins of Greek Thought (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1982). My argument does not embrace extreme claims about the "primacy of politics" in Greek culture (see, e.g., Paul A. Rahe, Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution [Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1992]), but it likewise rejects the attempt to read Athens as primarily family- and cult-centered (see, e.g., Cynthia Patterson, The Family in Greek History [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998]).
-
(1990)
The Greek Discovery of Politics
-
-
Meier, C.1
-
46
-
-
0007378758
-
-
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
-
On the centrality of politics, see Pierre Lèvêque and Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Cleisthenes the Athenian: An Essay on the Representation of Space and Time in Greek Political Thought from the End of the Sixth Century to the Death of Plato, ed. and trans. David Ames Curtis (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1996); Christian Meier, The Greek Discovery of Politics, trans. David McLintock (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990); and Jean-Pierre Vernant, The Origins of Greek Thought (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1982). My argument does not embrace extreme claims about the "primacy of politics" in Greek culture (see, e.g., Paul A. Rahe, Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution [Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1992]), but it likewise rejects the attempt to read Athens as primarily family- and cult-centered (see, e.g., Cynthia Patterson, The Family in Greek History [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998]).
-
(1982)
The Origins of Greek Thought
-
-
Vernant, J.-P.1
-
47
-
-
0004178688
-
-
Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press
-
On the centrality of politics, see Pierre Lèvêque and Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Cleisthenes the Athenian: An Essay on the Representation of Space and Time in Greek Political Thought from the End of the Sixth Century to the Death of Plato, ed. and trans. David Ames Curtis (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1996); Christian Meier, The Greek Discovery of Politics, trans. David McLintock (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990); and Jean-Pierre Vernant, The Origins of Greek Thought (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1982). My argument does not embrace extreme claims about the "primacy of politics" in Greek culture (see, e.g., Paul A. Rahe, Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution [Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1992]), but it likewise rejects the attempt to read Athens as primarily family- and cult-centered (see, e.g., Cynthia Patterson, The Family in Greek History [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998]).
-
(1992)
Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution
-
-
Rahe, P.A.1
-
48
-
-
0005593796
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
On the centrality of politics, see Pierre Lèvêque and Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Cleisthenes the Athenian: An Essay on the Representation of Space and Time in Greek Political Thought from the End of the Sixth Century to the Death of Plato, ed. and trans. David Ames Curtis (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1996); Christian Meier, The Greek Discovery of Politics, trans. David McLintock (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990); and Jean-Pierre Vernant, The Origins of Greek Thought (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1982). My argument does not embrace extreme claims about the "primacy of politics" in Greek culture (see, e.g., Paul A. Rahe, Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution [Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1992]), but it likewise rejects the attempt to read Athens as primarily family- and cult-centered (see, e.g., Cynthia Patterson, The Family in Greek History [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998]).
-
(1998)
The Family in Greek History
-
-
Patterson, C.1
-
49
-
-
0003669724
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
See Josiah Ober, Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989); and Ober, Athenian Revolution.
-
(1989)
Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens
-
-
Ober, J.1
-
50
-
-
0038617524
-
-
See Josiah Ober, Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989); and Ober, Athenian Revolution.
-
Athenian Revolution
-
-
Ober1
-
51
-
-
0039624990
-
Cardinal Virtues: The Language of Public Approbation in Democratic Athens
-
On inscriptions, see David Whitehead, "Cardinal Virtues: The Language of Public Approbation in Democratic Athens," Classica et Mediaevalia 34 (1983): 55-74. On speeches, see Ober, Mass and Elite.
-
(1983)
Classica et Mediaevalia
, vol.34
, pp. 55-74
-
-
Whitehead, D.1
-
52
-
-
0004350834
-
-
On inscriptions, see David Whitehead, "Cardinal Virtues: The Language of Public Approbation in Democratic Athens," Classica et Mediaevalia 34 (1983): 55-74. On speeches, see Ober, Mass and Elite.
-
Mass and Elite
-
-
Ober1
-
53
-
-
0039910318
-
-
note
-
The contrast, among republics, is with societies like that of ancient Rome, in which religious, social, economic, and political power were concentrated in the hands of an aristocratic oligarchy. I know much less about monarchical societies (e.g., classical China), but I suppose that they might manifest an even more fully developed isomorphism between various sorts of power, and consequently fewer obvious contradictions or opportunities for ideological confusion.
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
0041097373
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, On the ways in which post-classical Athenian political culture may have resorted to essentializing ideological tactics, see Susan Lape, "Community and Politics in Menander," Ph.D. dissertation, Princeton University
-
On democracy in post-classical Athens, see Christian Habicht, Athens from Alexander to Antony (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997). On the ways in which post-classical Athenian political culture may have resorted to essentializing ideological tactics, see Susan Lape, "Community and Politics in Menander," Ph.D. dissertation, Princeton University, 1998.
-
(1997)
Athens from Alexander to Antony
-
-
Habicht, C.1
-
55
-
-
84902630834
-
-
ed. G. W. Bowersock Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Pseudo-Xenophon, Constitution of the Athenians, ed. G. W. Bowersock (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971).
-
(1971)
Constitution of the Athenians
-
-
Pseudo-Xenophon1
-
56
-
-
0039910317
-
-
On this passage of Pseudo-Xenophon, cf. Arnold W. Gomme, "The Old Oligarch," in Gomme, More Essays in Greek History and Literature, ed. David A. Campbell (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1962), 61-62, 67-68; originally published in Athenian Studies Presented to W. S. Ferguson: Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, supplementary vol. 1 (1940), 211-45. The association of revolutionary change in the politeia with a change in the dominant element in the citizen body (politeuma) is a key issue for Aristotle in the Politics; see below.
-
The Old Oligarch
-
-
Gomme, A.W.1
-
57
-
-
0039910316
-
-
ed. David A. Campbell Oxford: Basil Blackwell
-
On this passage of Pseudo-Xenophon, cf. Arnold W. Gomme, "The Old Oligarch," in Gomme, More Essays in Greek History and Literature, ed. David A. Campbell (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1962), 61-62, 67-68; originally published in Athenian Studies Presented to W. S. Ferguson: Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, supplementary vol. 1 (1940), 211-45. The association of revolutionary change in the politeia with a change in the dominant element in the citizen body (politeuma) is a key issue for Aristotle in the Politics; see below.
-
(1962)
More Essays in Greek History and Literature
, pp. 61-62
-
-
Gomme1
-
58
-
-
84923789617
-
-
The association of revolutionary change in the politeia with a change in the dominant element in the citizen body (politeuma) is a key issue for Aristotle in the Politics; see below
-
On this passage of Pseudo-Xenophon, cf. Arnold W. Gomme, "The Old Oligarch," in Gomme, More Essays in Greek History and Literature, ed. David A. Campbell (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1962), 61-62, 67-68; originally published in Athenian Studies Presented to W. S. Ferguson: Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, supplementary vol. 1 (1940), 211-45. The association of revolutionary change in the politeia with a change in the dominant element in the citizen body (politeuma) is a key issue for Aristotle in the Politics; see below.
-
(1940)
Athenian Studies Presented to W. S. Ferguson: Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, supplementary
, vol.1 SUPPLEMENTARY VOL.
, pp. 211-245
-
-
-
60
-
-
0004080299
-
-
For Aristotle's doctrine of natural slavery, see Aristotle, Politics 1252a24-1256b40, and the discussion of Peter Garnsey, Ideas of Slavery from Aristotle to Augustine (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), and the literature cited therein.
-
Politics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
61
-
-
0003892849
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, and the literature cited therein
-
For Aristotle's doctrine of natural slavery, see Aristotle, Politics 1252a24-1256b40, and the discussion of Peter Garnsey, Ideas of Slavery from Aristotle to Augustine (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), and the literature cited therein.
-
(1996)
Ideas of Slavery from Aristotle to Augustine
-
-
Garnsey, P.1
-
62
-
-
0040503255
-
A Note on Pseudo-Xenophon, The Constitution of the Athenians 1.11
-
where Bechtle discusses the difficulties and offers a sensible solution. The point, for Pseudo-Xenophon, is that because the Athenians enter into legally binding financial agreements with their slaves, under the terms of which the slaves are eventually able to manumit themselves, the free Athenians are not able to do whatever they wish with respect to slaves and are therefore "slaves to slaves."
-
The Greek text is partially corrupt here; see Gerald Bechtle, "A Note on Pseudo-Xenophon, The Constitution of the Athenians 1.11," Classical Quarterly 46, no. 2 (1996): 564-66, where Bechtle discusses the difficulties and offers a sensible solution. The point, for Pseudo-Xenophon, is that because the Athenians enter into legally binding financial agreements with their slaves, under the terms of which the slaves are eventually able to manumit themselves, the free Athenians are not able to do whatever they wish with respect to slaves and are therefore "slaves to slaves."
-
(1996)
Classical Quarterly
, vol.46
, Issue.2
, pp. 564-566
-
-
Bechtle, G.1
-
64
-
-
0038617524
-
-
ch. 7
-
See note 38 for a modern edition of Demosthenes' speech. I offer a detailed analysis of the speech in Athenian Revolution, ch. 7.
-
Athenian Revolution
-
-
-
66
-
-
0041097379
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge Philological Society
-
On enktêsis and isoteleia, see David Whitehead, The Ideology of the Athenian Metic (Cambridge: Cambridge Philological Society, 1977). On wealthy metics and slaves, see Edward E. Cohen, Athenian Nation (Princeton: Princeton University Press, forthcoming).
-
(1977)
The Ideology of the Athenian Metic
-
-
Whitehead, D.1
-
67
-
-
84923816065
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press, forthcoming
-
On enktêsis and isoteleia, see David Whitehead, The Ideology of the Athenian Metic (Cambridge: Cambridge Philological Society, 1977). On wealthy metics and slaves, see Edward E. Cohen, Athenian Nation (Princeton: Princeton University Press, forthcoming).
-
Athenian Nation
-
-
Cohen, E.E.1
-
68
-
-
85011760857
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
See Edward E. Cohen, Ancient Athenian Maritime Courts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973); and Cohen, Athenian Nation.
-
(1973)
Ancient Athenian Maritime Courts
-
-
Cohen, E.E.1
-
69
-
-
84923816065
-
-
See Edward E. Cohen, Ancient Athenian Maritime Courts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973); and Cohen, Athenian Nation.
-
Athenian Nation
-
-
Cohen1
-
70
-
-
0037946530
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
On the question of religious freedom and the law against impiety, see Robert Parker, Athenian Religion: A History (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 207-11, 214-15. On metics and slaves in Athenian religious life, see Cohen, Athenian Nation. The Eleusinian Mysteries were celebrated each year with a grand procession from Athens to the deme of Eleusis, where initiates were shown and told secret things that led them to have hopes for the afterlife.
-
(1996)
Athenian Religion: A History
, pp. 207-211
-
-
Parker, R.1
-
71
-
-
84923816065
-
-
The Eleusinian Mysteries were celebrated each year with a grand procession from Athens to the deme of Eleusis, where initiates were shown and told secret things that led them to have hopes for the afterlife
-
On the question of religious freedom and the law against impiety, see Robert Parker, Athenian Religion: A History (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 207-11, 214-15. On metics and slaves in Athenian religious life, see Cohen, Athenian Nation. The Eleusinian Mysteries were celebrated each year with a grand procession from Athens to the deme of Eleusis, where initiates were shown and told secret things that led them to have hopes for the afterlife.
-
Athenian Nation
-
-
Cohen1
-
72
-
-
0005624152
-
Perikles' Citizenship Law of 451/0 B.C
-
ed. Alan L. Boegehold and Adele C. Scafuro Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press
-
On Periclean citizenship law, see Alan L. Boegehold, "Perikles' Citizenship Law of 451/0 B.C.," in Athenian Identity and Civic Ideology, ed. Alan L. Boegehold and Adele C. Scafuro (Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994), 57-66, and the literature cited therein. On the move from autochthony to patriotism, see Ober, Mass and Elite, 261-66. In Athenian Nation, Cohen discusses the evidence for naturalization in detail. He also argues that the citizenship law potentially allows any individual to be legally accepted as a citizen so long as he was born of two long-term noncitizen residents of Attica, but I do not believe that the evidence he cites supports the sharp legal distinction between the terms astos and politês upon which his argument depends.
-
(1994)
Athenian Identity and Civic Ideology
, pp. 57-66
-
-
Boegehold, A.L.1
-
73
-
-
0004350834
-
-
On Periclean citizenship law, see Alan L. Boegehold, "Perikles' Citizenship Law of 451/0 B.C.," in Athenian Identity and Civic Ideology, ed. Alan L. Boegehold and Adele C. Scafuro (Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994), 57-66, and the literature cited therein. On the move from autochthony to patriotism, see Ober, Mass and Elite, 261-66. In Athenian Nation, Cohen discusses the evidence for naturalization in detail. He also argues that the citizenship law potentially allows any individual to be legally accepted as a citizen so long as he was born of two long-term noncitizen residents of Attica, but I do not believe that the evidence he cites supports the sharp legal distinction between the terms astos and politês upon which his argument depends.
-
Mass and Elite
, pp. 261-266
-
-
Ober1
-
74
-
-
84923816065
-
-
discusses the evidence for naturalization in detail. He also argues that the citizenship law potentially allows any individual to be legally accepted as a citizen so long as he was born of two long-term noncitizen residents of Attica, but I do not believe that the evidence he cites supports the sharp legal distinction between the terms astos and politês upon which his argument depends
-
On Periclean citizenship law, see Alan L. Boegehold, "Perikles' Citizenship Law of 451/0 B.C.," in Athenian Identity and Civic Ideology, ed. Alan L. Boegehold and Adele C. Scafuro (Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994), 57-66, and the literature cited therein. On the move from autochthony to patriotism, see Ober, Mass and Elite, 261-66. In Athenian Nation, Cohen discusses the evidence for naturalization in detail. He also argues that the citizenship law potentially allows any individual to be legally accepted as a citizen so long as he was born of two long-term noncitizen residents of Attica, but I do not believe that the evidence he cites supports the sharp legal distinction between the terms astos and politês upon which his argument depends.
-
Athenian Nation
-
-
Cohen1
-
75
-
-
0039910307
-
-
Brussels: AWLSK, Klasse der Lettern, Jaargang 43, Nr. 98
-
On the procedure for enfranchisement and its relative rarity, see M. J. Osborne, Naturalization in Athens (Brussels: AWLSK, Klasse der Lettern, Jaargang 43, Nr. 98, 1981). On the house of Pasion and Apollodorus, see Ober, Mass and Elite, 212-14. See also Jeremy Trevett, Apollodoros the Son of Pasion (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992).
-
(1981)
Naturalization in Athens
-
-
Osborne, M.J.1
-
76
-
-
0004350834
-
-
On the procedure for enfranchisement and its relative rarity, see M. J. Osborne, Naturalization in Athens (Brussels: AWLSK, Klasse der Lettern, Jaargang 43, Nr. 98, 1981). On the house of Pasion and Apollodorus, see Ober, Mass and Elite, 212-14. See also Jeremy Trevett, Apollodoros the Son of Pasion (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992).
-
Mass and Elite
, pp. 212-214
-
-
Ober1
-
77
-
-
0040503260
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
On the procedure for enfranchisement and its relative rarity, see M. J. Osborne, Naturalization in Athens (Brussels: AWLSK, Klasse der Lettern, Jaargang 43, Nr. 98, 1981). On the house of Pasion and Apollodorus, see Ober, Mass and Elite, 212-14. See also Jeremy Trevett, Apollodoros the Son of Pasion (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992).
-
(1992)
Apollodoros the Son of Pasion
-
-
Trevett, J.1
-
78
-
-
0041097379
-
-
On metic service in Athenian armed forces, see Whitehead, Ideology of the Athenian Metic, 82-86. On slaves in military service, see Peter Hunt, Slaves, Warfare, and Ideology in the Greek Historians (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
-
Ideology of the Athenian Metic
, pp. 82-86
-
-
Whitehead1
-
79
-
-
0037946571
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
On metic service in Athenian armed forces, see Whitehead, Ideology of the Athenian Metic, 82-86. On slaves in military service, see Peter Hunt, Slaves, Warfare, and Ideology in the Greek Historians (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
-
(1998)
Slaves, Warfare, and Ideology in the Greek Historians
-
-
Hunt, P.1
-
80
-
-
84923816065
-
-
discusses the evidence in detail
-
Cohen, in Athenian Nation, discusses the evidence in detail.
-
Athenian Nation
-
-
Cohen1
-
81
-
-
84883911155
-
-
For the claim that women in democratic Athens were actually less free than in aristo-cratic poleis, couched in negative terms, see Roberts, "Athenian Equality."
-
Athenian Equality
-
-
Roberts1
-
84
-
-
0039910303
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Cf. Thucydides 2.45.2: "If I may speak also about the women who will now be widows, I shall define it all in a brief admonition. For great is the glory for you not to be worse than your existing nature, and not to be talked about for good or evil among men" (trans. J. S. Rusten, Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, Book II [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989], with adaptations suggested by Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides).
-
(1989)
Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, Book II
-
-
Rusten, J.S.1
-
85
-
-
0009134666
-
-
Cf. Thucydides 2.45.2: "If I may speak also about the women who will now be widows, I shall define it all in a brief admonition. For great is the glory for you not to be worse than your existing nature, and not to be talked about for good or evil among men" (trans. J. S. Rusten, Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, Book II [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989], with adaptations suggested by Hornblower, A Commentary on Thucydides).
-
A Commentary on Thucydides
-
-
Hornblower1
-
87
-
-
84874543915
-
How to Criticize Democracy in Late Fifth- and Fourth-Century Athens
-
The argument here is made in more detail in Ober, "How to Criticize Democracy in Late Fifth- and Fourth-Century Athens," in Athenian Revolution.
-
Athenian Revolution
-
-
Ober1
-
88
-
-
0041097372
-
-
note
-
Although Aristotle's concept of aristocracy is a complicated philosophical contrivance, the fact that some nondemocratic poleis did indeed have "controllers of women" allows us to use the term "aristocracy" rather more broadly than Aristotle (sometimes) did. Some scholars have supposed (although it is not provable) that the hubris law was enacted by Solon, to whom are also attributed laws restricting the behavior of Athenian women at funerals (Plutarch, Solon 21.5). But the point here concerns what laws are enforced under the democratic regime.
-
-
-
-
89
-
-
0041012919
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
On Plato's Crito, see Richard Kraut, Socrates and the State (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984).
-
(1984)
Socrates and the State
-
-
Kraut, R.1
-
90
-
-
0041097369
-
-
note
-
This would be a problematic procedure if the primary concern was the intention of the original lawmaker, but since that is unknowable and undatable (per note 51 above), I am concerned here with the way the law was used and understood in fourth-century practice.
-
-
-
-
91
-
-
0007146358
-
-
On the phrase kataluein ton dêmon (or similar phrases) and its association with hubris, see Aristophanes, Ecclesiazusae 453; and Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War 3.81.4 (civil war on Corcyra).
-
Ecclesiazusae
, pp. 453
-
-
Aristophanes1
-
92
-
-
0041097368
-
-
civil war on Corcyra
-
On the phrase kataluein ton dêmon (or similar phrases) and its association with hubris, see Aristophanes, Ecclesiazusae 453; and Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War 3.81.4 (civil war on Corcyra).
-
The Peloponnesian War 3.81.4
-
-
Thucydides1
-
93
-
-
0039317870
-
-
note
-
Demosthenes' description of the various bad things done to him in private life by Meidias and his cronies illustrates the potential harms that could arise from challenging the powerful, even in Athens.
-
-
-
-
94
-
-
0004032769
-
-
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, But the work of magistrates was subordinate to the popular Assemblies and lawcourts, and did not include moral policing
-
The Athenians annually appointed many magistrates (by election or, more often, by lot) to undertake various aspects of public business; see Mogens H. Hansen, The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991), 225-45. But the work of magistrates was subordinate to the popular Assemblies and lawcourts, and did not include moral policing.
-
(1991)
The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes
, pp. 225-245
-
-
Hansen, M.H.1
-
96
-
-
0040503254
-
-
and the bibliographies of both books point to more
-
A good deal of recent work is summed up in Peter Euben, Corrupting Youth: Political Education, Democratic Culture, and Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997); and Demokratia, ed. Ober and Hedrick; and the bibliographies of both books point to more.
-
Demokratia
-
-
Ober1
Hedrick2
|