메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 107, Issue 2, 1997, Pages 250-285

Nietzsche and the morality critics

(1)  Leiter, Brian a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0040428383     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233720     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (46)

References (145)
  • 1
    • 0004023594 scopus 로고
    • New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, esp. chaps. 5 and 6
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1979) Allegories of Reading
    • De Man, P.1
  • 2
    • 33749602257 scopus 로고
    • New York: Delta
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1977) The New Nietzsche
    • Allison, D.1
  • 3
    • 0003804733 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1985) Nietzsche: Life As Literature
    • Nehamas, A.1
  • 4
    • 0040378670 scopus 로고
    • Nietzsche and aestheticism
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1992) Journal of the History of Philosophy , vol.30 , pp. 275-290
    • Nietzsche1
  • 5
    • 0005524140 scopus 로고
    • Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of morals
    • ed. R. Schacht Berkeley: University of California Press
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1994) Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality
  • 6
    • 0004212168 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chaps.
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1990) Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy , pp. 1-4
    • Clark, M.1
  • 7
    • 0040379938 scopus 로고
    • The ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1900) Ethics , vol.11 , pp. 82-105
    • Adams, M.1
  • 8
    • 0039195340 scopus 로고
    • The morals of an immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1908) Ethics , vol.19 , pp. 1-23
    • Benn, A.W.1
  • 9
    • 0039787680 scopus 로고
    • Nietzsche and democracy
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1912) Philosophical Review , vol.21 , pp. 32-50
    • Rogers, A.K.1
  • 10
    • 0039787678 scopus 로고
    • Nietzsche's moral aim
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1915) Ethics , vol.25 , pp. 226-251
    • Salter, W.M.1
  • 11
    • 0040974204 scopus 로고
    • The metaphysics of Nietzsche's immoralism
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1915) Philosophical Review , vol.24 , pp. 386-418
    • Laing, B.1
  • 12
    • 0039787677 scopus 로고
    • Some criticisms on the Nietzsche revival
    • A very different Nietzsche has engaged thinkers elsewhere, notably on the European continent and in literature departments in the United States. There the key themes have been perspectivism, the primacy of interpretation (and, at the same time, its indeterminacy), and the impossibility of truth. This Nietzsche is well represented by Paul de Man, in Allegories of Reading (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979), esp. chaps. 5 and 6, and by many of the essays in D. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Delta, 1977); it has received its most sophisticated articulation, however, in Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985) , a book which, accordingly, gives only cursory attention to Nietzsche's moral philosophy. The problems with this reading of Nietzsche - which are, I think, many - are discussed in my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism," Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 275-90, and my "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals," in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, ed. R. Schacht (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994). Compare Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), chaps. 1-4. Interestingly, the last explosion of Anglo-American philosophical interest in Nietzsche - roughly, from 1900 until the end of World War I - was also driven by an interest in his ethics (and esp. its connection to evolutionary theory and positivism). See, e.g., Maurice Adams, "The Ethics of Tolstoy and Nietzsche," Ethics 11 (1900): 82-105; Alfred W. Benn, "The Morals of an Immoralist - Friedrich Nietzsche," Ethics 19 (1908-9): 1-23, 192-211; A. K. Rogers, "Nietzsche and Democracy," Philosophical Review 21 (1912): 32-50; William M. Salter, "Nietzsche's Moral Aim," Ethics 25 (1915): 226-51, 372-403; Bertram Laing, "The Metaphysics of Nietzsche's Immoralism," Philosophical Review 24 (1915): 386-418. One may hope that no philosopher today would write, as one dissenter from the Nietzsche revival did then, that "nothing . . . quite so worthless as 'Thus Spoke Zarathustra' or 'Beyond Good and Evil' has ever attracted so much attention from serious students of the philosophy of morals" (Herbert Stewart, "Some Criticisms on the Nietzsche Revival," Ethics 19 [1909]: 427-28).
    • (1909) Ethics , vol.19 , pp. 427-428
    • Stewart, H.1
  • 13
    • 0004123406 scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, esp.
    • Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), esp. pp. 107-11.
    • (1981) After Virtue , pp. 107-111
    • Macintyre, A.1
  • 14
    • 33747657396 scopus 로고
    • Theory and reflective practices
    • London: Methuen
    • Annette Baier, "Theory and Reflective Practices," in Postures of the Mind (London: Methuen, 1985), pp. 207-27, p. 224.
    • (1985) Postures of the Mind , pp. 207-227
    • Baier, A.1
  • 15
    • 0000146063 scopus 로고
    • Moral saints
    • Susan Wolf, "Moral Saints," Journal of Philosophy 79 (1982): 419-39, p. 433.
    • (1982) Journal of Philosophy , vol.79 , pp. 419-439
    • Wolf, S.1
  • 16
    • 0007075876 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon
    • See, e.g., Michael Slote, Goods and Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon, 1983), p. 79; Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 196; Philippa Foot, "Nietzsche: The Revaluation of Values," in Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. R. Solomon (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1973), esp. p. 163; see also her "Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives?" reprinted in her Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978).
    • (1983) Goods and Virtues , pp. 79
    • Slote, M.1
  • 17
    • 0004207980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • See, e.g., Michael Slote, Goods and Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon, 1983), p. 79; Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 196; Philippa Foot, "Nietzsche: The Revaluation of Values," in Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. R. Solomon (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1973), esp. p. 163; see also her "Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives?" reprinted in her Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978).
    • (1986) The View from Nowhere , pp. 196
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 18
    • 0040007028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nietzsche: The revaluation of values
    • ed. R. Solomon Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, esp.
    • See, e.g., Michael Slote, Goods and Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon, 1983), p. 79; Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 196; Philippa Foot, "Nietzsche: The Revaluation of Values," in Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. R. Solomon (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1973), esp. p. 163; see also her "Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives?" reprinted in her Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978).
    • (1973) Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays , pp. 163
    • Foot, P.1
  • 19
    • 24944581028 scopus 로고
    • Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives?
    • reprinted in her Berkeley: University of California Press
    • See, e.g., Michael Slote, Goods and Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon, 1983), p. 79; Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 196; Philippa Foot, "Nietzsche: The Revaluation of Values," in Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. R. Solomon (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1973), esp. p. 163; see also her "Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives?" reprinted in her Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978).
    • (1978) Virtues and Vices
  • 20
    • 84928507688 scopus 로고
    • Can we be too moral?
    • Robert Louden, "Can We Be Too Moral?" Ethics 98 (1988): 361-80, p. 361. Louden begins his essay by quoting Nietzsche's call for "a critique of moral values, the value of these values themselves must first be called in question" (GM, pref.). A note on citations: I cite Nietzsche's texts using the standard English-language acronyms: The Birth of Tragedy (BT), Untimely Meditations (U), Dawn (D), The Gay Science (GS), Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Z), Beyond Good and Evil (BGE), On the Genealogy of Morality (GM), Twilight of the Idols (TI), The Antichrist (A), Ecce Homo (EH), Nietzsche Contra Wagner (NCW), and The Will to Power (WP). Roman numerals refer to major divisions or chapters; arabic numerals refer to sections, not pages. Translations, with occasional minor emendations, are by Walter Kaufmann and/or R. J. Hollingdale; for purposes of making emendations, I rely upon the Sämtliche Werke in 15 Bänden, ed. G. Colli and M. Mottinari (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1980).
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.98 , pp. 361-380
    • Louden, R.1
  • 21
    • 85033113677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GM, pref.
    • Robert Louden, "Can We Be Too Moral?" Ethics 98 (1988): 361-80, p. 361. Louden begins his essay by quoting Nietzsche's call for "a critique of moral values, the value of these values themselves must first be called in question" (GM, pref.). A note on citations: I cite Nietzsche's texts using the standard English-language acronyms: The Birth of Tragedy (BT), Untimely Meditations (U), Dawn (D), The Gay Science (GS), Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Z), Beyond Good and Evil (BGE), On the Genealogy of Morality (GM), Twilight of the Idols (TI), The Antichrist (A), Ecce Homo (EH), Nietzsche Contra Wagner (NCW), and The Will to Power (WP). Roman numerals refer to major divisions or chapters; arabic numerals refer to sections, not pages. Translations, with occasional minor emendations, are by Walter Kaufmann and/or R. J. Hollingdale; for purposes of making emendations, I rely upon the Sämtliche Werke in 15 Bänden, ed. G. Colli and M. Mottinari (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1980).
    • A Critique of Moral Values, the Value of These Values Themselves Must First Be Called in Question
    • Nietzsche1
  • 23
    • 85033116914 scopus 로고
    • ed. G. Colli and M. Mottinari Berlin: de Gruyter
    • Robert Louden, "Can We Be Too Moral?" Ethics 98 (1988): 361-80, p. 361. Louden begins his essay by quoting Nietzsche's call for "a critique of moral values, the value of these values themselves must first be called in question" (GM, pref.). A note on citations: I cite Nietzsche's texts using the standard English-language acronyms: The Birth of Tragedy (BT), Untimely Meditations (U), Dawn (D), The Gay Science (GS), Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Z), Beyond Good and Evil (BGE), On the Genealogy of Morality (GM), Twilight of the Idols (TI), The Antichrist (A), Ecce Homo (EH), Nietzsche Contra Wagner (NCW), and The Will to Power (WP). Roman numerals refer to major divisions or chapters; arabic numerals refer to sections, not pages. Translations, with occasional minor emendations, are by Walter Kaufmann and/or R. J. Hollingdale; for purposes of making emendations, I rely upon the Sämtliche Werke in 15 Bänden, ed. G. Colli and M. Mottinari (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1980).
    • (1980) Sämtliche Werke in 15 Bänden
    • Kaufmann, W.1    Hollingdale, R.J.2
  • 25
    • 0002037012 scopus 로고
    • Toward fin de siecle ethics: Some trends
    • See Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton, "Toward Fin de siecle Ethics: Some Trends," Philosophical Review 101 (1992): 115-89, p. 181. This forms the subject matter of normative theory, which these authors, following Baier, identify as the primary target of those I am calling the Theory Critics.
    • (1992) Philosophical Review , vol.101 , pp. 115-189
    • Darwall, S.1    Gibbard, A.2    Railton, P.3
  • 26
    • 0007190918 scopus 로고
    • Ethical particularism and morally relevant properties
    • See Jonathan Dancy, "Ethical Particularism and Morally Relevant Properties," Mind 92 (1983): 530-47.
    • (1983) Mind , vol.92 , pp. 530-547
    • Dancy, J.1
  • 27
    • 0004195469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 16-17, cited hereafter in the text as ELP; Thomas Nagel, "The Fragmentation of Value," reprinted in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 131-32; Charles Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 138; Charles Taylor, "The Diversity of Goods," reprinted in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). Elsewhere in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Williams worries about a different kind of reductionism, i.e., the attempt to reduce all practical reasoning and all obligation to moral reasoning and moral obligation. See esp. chap. 10.
    • (1985) Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy , pp. 16-17
    • Williams, B.1
  • 28
    • 0001942520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fragmentation of value
    • reprinted Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 16-17, cited hereafter in the text as ELP; Thomas Nagel, "The Fragmentation of Value," reprinted in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 131-32; Charles Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 138; Charles Taylor, "The Diversity of Goods," reprinted in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). Elsewhere in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Williams worries about a different kind of reductionism, i.e., the attempt to reduce all practical reasoning and all obligation to moral reasoning and moral obligation. See esp. chap. 10.
    • (1979) Mortal Questions , pp. 131-132
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 29
    • 0004284007 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 16-17, cited hereafter in the text as ELP; Thomas Nagel, "The Fragmentation of Value," reprinted in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 131-32; Charles Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 138; Charles Taylor, "The Diversity of Goods," reprinted in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). Elsewhere in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Williams worries about a different kind of reductionism, i.e., the attempt to reduce all practical reasoning and all obligation to moral reasoning and moral obligation. See esp. chap. 10.
    • (1987) Patterns of Moral Complexity , pp. 138
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 30
    • 0009958086 scopus 로고
    • The diversity of goods
    • reprinted in Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 16-17, cited hereafter in the text as ELP; Thomas Nagel, "The Fragmentation of Value," reprinted in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 131-32; Charles Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 138; Charles Taylor, "The Diversity of Goods," reprinted in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). Elsewhere in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Williams worries about a different kind of reductionism, i.e., the attempt to reduce all practical reasoning and all obligation to moral reasoning and moral obligation. See esp. chap. 10.
    • (1985) Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers , vol.2
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 31
    • 0004195469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp. chap. 10
    • Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 16-17, cited hereafter in the text as ELP; Thomas Nagel, "The Fragmentation of Value," reprinted in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 131-32; Charles Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 138; Charles Taylor, "The Diversity of Goods," reprinted in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). Elsewhere in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Williams worries about a different kind of reductionism, i.e., the attempt to reduce all practical reasoning and all obligation to moral reasoning and moral obligation. See esp. chap. 10.
    • Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
    • Williams1
  • 32
    • 0039786329 scopus 로고
    • Preface
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Bernard Williams, "Preface," in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. x; Larmore, p. ix, chap. 1; Taylor. Something similar seems to be Annette Baier's target in "Theory and Reflective Practices," and "Doing without Moral Theory?" (reprinted in Postures of the Mind, pp. 228-45), esp. in her talk of the theorist's hierarchical ordering of more principles "in which the less general are derived from the more general" ("Doing without Moral Theory?" p. 232) on the model of a legal system ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 214) (where the latter is thought of, in a pre-Legal Realist sense, as involving the deduction of particular decisions from general rules).
    • (1981) Moral Luck
    • Williams, B.1
  • 33
    • 85033111882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 1
    • Bernard Williams, "Preface," in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. x; Larmore, p. ix, chap. 1; Taylor. Something similar seems to be Annette Baier's target in "Theory and Reflective Practices," and "Doing without Moral Theory?" (reprinted in Postures of the Mind, pp. 228-45), esp. in her talk of the theorist's hierarchical ordering of more principles "in which the less general are derived from the more general" ("Doing without Moral Theory?" p. 232) on the model of a legal system ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 214) (where the latter is thought of, in a pre-Legal Realist sense, as involving the deduction of particular decisions from general rules).
    • Larmore1
  • 34
    • 0009437770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theory and reflective practices," and "doing without moral theory?
    • reprinted esp.
    • Bernard Williams, "Preface," in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. x; Larmore, p. ix, chap. 1; Taylor. Something similar seems to be Annette Baier's target in "Theory and Reflective Practices," and "Doing without Moral Theory?" (reprinted in Postures of the Mind, pp. 228-45), esp. in her talk of the theorist's hierarchical ordering of more principles "in which the less general are derived from the more general" ("Doing without Moral Theory?" p. 232) on the model of a legal system ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 214) (where the latter is thought of, in a pre-Legal Realist sense, as involving the deduction of particular decisions from general rules).
    • Postures of the Mind , pp. 228-245
    • Baier, A.1
  • 35
    • 85033116703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bernard Williams, "Preface," in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. x; Larmore, p. ix, chap. 1; Taylor. Something similar seems to be Annette Baier's target in "Theory and Reflective Practices," and "Doing without Moral Theory?" (reprinted in Postures of the Mind, pp. 228-45), esp. in her talk of the theorist's hierarchical ordering of more principles "in which the less general are derived from the more general" ("Doing without Moral Theory?" p. 232) on the model of a legal system ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 214) (where the latter is thought of, in a pre-Legal Realist sense, as involving the deduction of particular decisions from general rules).
    • Doing Without Moral Theory? , pp. 232
  • 36
    • 85033115122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bernard Williams, "Preface," in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. x; Larmore, p. ix, chap. 1; Taylor. Something similar seems to be Annette Baier's target in "Theory and Reflective Practices," and "Doing without Moral Theory?" (reprinted in Postures of the Mind, pp. 228-45), esp. in her talk of the theorist's hierarchical ordering of more principles "in which the less general are derived from the more general" ("Doing without Moral Theory?" p. 232) on the model of a legal system ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 214) (where the latter is thought of, in a pre-Legal Realist sense, as involving the deduction of particular decisions from general rules).
    • Theory and Reflective Practices , pp. 214
  • 37
    • 85033107059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taylor aptly calls this the ambition for a "single-consideration procedure," a label which suggests the unity of Reduction and Mechanical Decision, and objects that such a procedure cannot do justice to "the real diversity of goods that we recognize" (pp. 245, 247).
    • The Real Diversity of Goods That We Recognize , pp. 245
    • Taylor1
  • 38
    • 85033113854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theory and reflective practices
    • See Baier, "Theory and Reflective Practices" and "Doing without Moral Theory?"; and Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 115-17, 127, 202.
    • Doing Without Moral Theory?
    • Baier1
  • 39
    • 0004195469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp.
    • See Baier, "Theory and Reflective Practices" and "Doing without Moral Theory?"; and Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 115-17, 127, 202.
    • Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy , pp. 115-117
    • Williams1
  • 40
    • 0040974201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Baier argues for ethical reflection without "normative theory in the Kantian sense" while noting that "reflectiveness about our practices requires at the very least noting whether they are counterproductive to their expressed aims" ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 226). Williams wonders throughout Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy "why reflection should be taken to require theory" (p. 112) and claims that "philosophy in the modern world cannot make any special claim to reflectiveness" (p. 3). Taylor goes further and concedes that even if there are a plurality of goods, "people . . . are faced with the job of somehow making them compatible in their lives" (p. 236) and that, as a result, "the demand for a unified theory" is a "demand we cannot totally repudiate" (p. 245).
    • Theory and Reflective Practices , pp. 226
    • Baier1
  • 41
    • 0004195469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Baier argues for ethical reflection without "normative theory in the Kantian sense" while noting that "reflectiveness about our practices requires at the very least noting whether they are counterproductive to their expressed aims" ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 226). Williams wonders throughout Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy "why reflection should be taken to require theory" (p. 112) and claims that "philosophy in the modern world cannot make any special claim to reflectiveness" (p. 3). Taylor goes further and concedes that even if there are a plurality of goods, "people . . . are faced with the job of somehow making them compatible in their lives" (p. 236) and that, as a result, "the demand for a unified theory" is a "demand we cannot totally repudiate" (p. 245).
    • Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy , pp. 112
    • Williams1
  • 42
    • 85033113671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Baier argues for ethical reflection without "normative theory in the Kantian sense" while noting that "reflectiveness about our practices requires at the very least noting whether they are counterproductive to their expressed aims" ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 226). Williams wonders throughout Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy "why reflection should be taken to require theory" (p. 112) and claims that "philosophy in the modern world cannot make any special claim to reflectiveness" (p. 3). Taylor goes further and concedes that even if there are a plurality of goods, "people . . . are faced with the job of somehow making them compatible in their lives" (p. 236) and that, as a result, "the demand for a unified theory" is a "demand we cannot totally repudiate" (p. 245).
    • Philosophy in the Modern World Cannot Make Any Special Claim to Reflectiveness , pp. 3
  • 43
    • 85033098898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Baier argues for ethical reflection without "normative theory in the Kantian sense" while noting that "reflectiveness about our practices requires at the very least noting whether they are counterproductive to their expressed aims" ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 226). Williams wonders throughout Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy "why reflection should be taken to require theory" (p. 112) and claims that "philosophy in the modern world cannot make any special claim to reflectiveness" (p. 3). Taylor goes further and concedes that even if there are a plurality of goods, "people . . . are faced with the job of somehow making them compatible in their lives" (p. 236) and that, as a result, "the demand for a unified theory" is a "demand we cannot totally repudiate" (p. 245).
    • People . . . Are Faced with the Job of Somehow Making Them Compatible in Their Lives , pp. 236
    • Taylor1
  • 44
    • 85033123038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Baier argues for ethical reflection without "normative theory in the Kantian sense" while noting that "reflectiveness about our practices requires at the very least noting whether they are counterproductive to their expressed aims" ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 226). Williams wonders throughout Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy "why reflection should be taken to require theory" (p. 112) and claims that "philosophy in the modern world cannot make any special claim to reflectiveness" (p. 3). Taylor goes further and concedes that even if there are a plurality of goods, "people . . . are faced with the job of somehow making them compatible in their lives" (p. 236) and that, as a result, "the demand for a unified theory" is a "demand we cannot totally repudiate" (p. 245).
    • The Demand for a Unified Theory , pp. 245
  • 45
    • 0001942520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is clearest in the case of writers like Nagel and Larmore, who explicitly affirm both the tenability of moral theory and the indispensable role of something like Aristotle's practical wisdom or judgment in our moral life. See Nagel, "The Fragmentation of Value," pp. 135-37; and Larmore, chap. 1, p. 151 ("My intention . . . has not been to deny the possibilities or importance of moral theory. I do not believe that the complexity of morality is so great, so boundless, that it baffles any attempt at systematization.").
    • The Fragmentation of Value , pp. 135-137
    • Nagel1
  • 46
    • 85033108853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 1
    • This is clearest in the case of writers like Nagel and Larmore, who explicitly affirm both the tenability of moral theory and the indispensable role of something like Aristotle's practical wisdom or judgment in our moral life. See Nagel, "The Fragmentation of Value," pp. 135-37; and Larmore, chap. 1, p. 151 ("My intention . . . has not been to deny the possibilities or importance of moral theory. I do not believe that the complexity of morality is so great, so boundless, that it baffles any attempt at systematization.").
    • Larmore1
  • 47
    • 85033104488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I take the preceding sentence to be a more obviously apt characterization of some of Williams's earlier work in ethics.
  • 48
    • 85033126078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See the further discussion in Sec. V.
  • 49
    • 0000685612 scopus 로고
    • The Schizophrenia of modern ethical theories
    • Michael Stocker, "The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories," Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976): 453-66, cited in this section by page number.
    • (1976) Journal of Philosophy , vol.73 , pp. 453-466
    • Stocker, M.1
  • 50
    • 85033113992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See esp. the concluding pages of Stocker's piece. Susan Wolf presents a slightly different case than other Morality Critics in this regard; see "Moral Saints," pp. 435-37; and my discussion in n. 26.
    • Moral Saints , pp. 435-437
    • Stocker1
  • 51
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, esp.
    • For example, of the former type, John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), esp. pp. 26-27; of the latter type, Samuel Scheffler, "Agent-Centered Restrictions, Rationality, and the Virtues," Mind 94 (1985): 409-19, esp. p. 409.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 26-27
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 52
    • 0039194058 scopus 로고
    • Agent-centered restrictions, rationality, and the virtues
    • esp.
    • For example, of the former type, John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), esp. pp. 26-27; of the latter type, Samuel Scheffler, "Agent-Centered Restrictions, Rationality, and the Virtues," Mind 94 (1985): 409-19, esp. p. 409.
    • (1985) Mind , vol.94 , pp. 409-419
    • Scheffler, S.1
  • 53
    • 0002233285 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarian morality and the personal point of view
    • A third difficulty is that some writers construe demands of, e.g., partiality and integrity to be essentially moral demands, apart from their role in deontological and consequentialist theories. See David Brink, "Utilitarian Morality and the Personal Point of View," Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 417-38, pp. 418-19; Larmore, pp. 132-33. This construal is not, I think, suggested by the writings of most Morality Critics themselves and, in any event, can be dealt with in the way suggested in the text.
    • (1986) Journal of Philosophy , vol.83 , pp. 417-438
    • Brink, D.1
  • 54
    • 85033115329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A third difficulty is that some writers construe demands of, e.g., partiality and integrity to be essentially moral demands, apart from their role in deontological and consequentialist theories. See David Brink, "Utilitarian Morality and the Personal Point of View," Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 417-38, pp. 418-19; Larmore, pp. 132-33. This construal is not, I think, suggested by the writings of most Morality Critics themselves and, in any event, can be dealt with in the way suggested in the text.
    • Larmore1
  • 55
    • 85033101294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A serious threat to the kind of personal life that many of us take to be desirable
    • Nagel speaks of morality posing "a serious threat to the kind of personal life that many of us take to be desirable" (View from Nowhere, p. 190). Wolf claims that the "moral saint" cannot realize "a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Bernard Williams argues that both Kantian and utilitarian theories will sometimes require us to abandon our "ground projects," those projects "which propel [a person] in the future, and give him (in a sense) a reason for living" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," in The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976], pp. 209-10). See Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 77-150, esp. pp. 115-17, and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 181-82 (worrying that a Kantian notion of obligation can "come to dominate life altogether"). Slote argues that a commitment to morality would require us to "deplore and disavow" (p. 85) certain otherwise admirable traits like "single-minded devotion to aesthetic goals or ideals" (p. 80) - because of their essential tendency also to produce immoral behavior. Michael Stocker is probably an exception to the characterization offered in the text. While most Morality Critics view the nonmoral goods and considerations as largely prudential in character, Stocker is concerned with phenomena like "love" and "friendship" whose value is probably not prudential. See "The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories."
    • View from Nowhere , pp. 190
    • Nagel1
  • 56
    • 85033124261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral saint
    • Nagel speaks of morality posing "a serious threat to the kind of personal life that many of us take to be desirable" (View from Nowhere, p. 190). Wolf claims that the "moral saint" cannot realize "a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Bernard Williams argues that both Kantian and utilitarian theories will sometimes require us to abandon our "ground projects," those projects "which propel [a person] in the future, and give him (in a sense) a reason for living" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," in The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976], pp. 209-10). See Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 77-150, esp. pp. 115-17, and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 181-82 (worrying that a Kantian notion of obligation can "come to dominate life altogether"). Slote argues that a commitment to morality would require us to "deplore and disavow" (p. 85) certain otherwise admirable traits like "single-minded devotion to aesthetic goals or ideals" (p. 80) - because of their essential tendency also to produce immoral behavior. Michael Stocker is probably an exception to the characterization offered in the text. While most Morality Critics view the nonmoral goods and considerations as largely prudential in character, Stocker is concerned with phenomena like "love" and "friendship" whose value is probably not prudential. See "The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories."
    • A Great Variety of Forms of Personal Excellence , pp. 426
    • Wolf1
  • 57
    • 0002775463 scopus 로고
    • Persons, character, and morality
    • ed. A. Rorty Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Nagel speaks of morality posing "a serious threat to the kind of personal life that many of us take to be desirable" (View from Nowhere, p. 190). Wolf claims that the "moral saint" cannot realize "a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Bernard Williams argues that both Kantian and utilitarian theories will sometimes require us to abandon our "ground projects," those projects "which propel [a person] in the future, and give him (in a sense) a reason for living" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," in The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976], pp. 209-10). See Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 77-150, esp. pp. 115-17, and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 181-82 (worrying that a Kantian notion of obligation can "come to dominate life altogether"). Slote argues that a commitment to morality would require us to "deplore and disavow" (p. 85) certain otherwise admirable traits like "single-minded devotion to aesthetic goals or ideals" (p. 80) - because of their essential tendency also to produce immoral behavior. Michael Stocker is probably an exception to the characterization offered in the text. While most Morality Critics view the nonmoral goods and considerations as largely prudential in character, Stocker is concerned with phenomena like "love" and "friendship" whose value is probably not prudential. See "The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories."
    • (1976) The Identities of Persons , pp. 209-210
    • Williams, B.1
  • 58
    • 0001895023 scopus 로고
    • A critique of utilitarianism
    • J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, esp.
    • Nagel speaks of morality posing "a serious threat to the kind of personal life that many of us take to be desirable" (View from Nowhere, p. 190). Wolf claims that the "moral saint" cannot realize "a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Bernard Williams argues that both Kantian and utilitarian theories will sometimes require us to abandon our "ground projects," those projects "which propel [a person] in the future, and give him (in a sense) a reason for living" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," in The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976], pp. 209-10). See Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 77-150, esp. pp. 115-17, and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 181-82 (worrying that a Kantian notion of obligation can "come to dominate life altogether"). Slote argues that a commitment to morality would require us to "deplore and disavow" (p. 85) certain otherwise admirable traits like "single-minded devotion to aesthetic goals or ideals" (p. 80) - because of their essential tendency also to produce immoral behavior. Michael Stocker is probably an exception to the characterization offered in the text. While most Morality Critics view the nonmoral goods and considerations as largely prudential in character, Stocker is concerned with phenomena like "love" and "friendship" whose value is probably not prudential. See "The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories."
    • (1973) Utilitarianism: For and Against , pp. 77-150
    • Williams, B.1
  • 59
    • 84955292794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp.
    • Nagel speaks of morality posing "a serious threat to the kind of personal life that many of us take to be desirable" (View from Nowhere, p. 190). Wolf claims that the "moral saint" cannot realize "a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Bernard Williams argues that both Kantian and utilitarian theories will sometimes require us to abandon our "ground projects," those projects "which propel [a person] in the future, and give him (in a sense) a reason for living" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," in The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976], pp. 209-10). See Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 77-150, esp. pp. 115-17, and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 181-82 (worrying that a Kantian notion of obligation can "come to dominate life altogether"). Slote argues that a commitment to morality would require us to "deplore and disavow" (p. 85) certain otherwise admirable traits like "single-minded devotion to aesthetic goals or ideals" (p. 80) - because of their essential tendency also to produce immoral behavior. Michael Stocker is probably an exception to the
    • Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy , pp. 181-182
  • 60
    • 85033119998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nagel speaks of morality posing "a serious threat to the kind of personal life that many of us take to be desirable" (View from Nowhere, p. 190). Wolf claims that the "moral saint" cannot realize "a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Bernard Williams argues that both Kantian and utilitarian theories will sometimes require us to abandon our "ground projects," those projects "which propel [a person] in the future, and give him (in a sense) a reason for living" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," in The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976], pp. 209-10). See Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 77-150, esp. pp. 115-17, and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 181-82 (worrying that a Kantian notion of obligation can "come to dominate life altogether"). Slote argues that a commitment to morality would require us to "deplore and disavow" (p. 85) certain otherwise admirable traits like "single-minded devotion to aesthetic goals or ideals" (p. 80) - because of their essential tendency also to produce immoral behavior. Michael Stocker is probably an exception to the characterization offered in the text. While most Morality Critics view the nonmoral goods and considerations as largely prudential in character, Stocker is concerned with phenomena like "love" and "friendship" whose value is probably not prudential. See "The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories."
    • Deplore and Disavow , pp. 85
    • Slote1
  • 61
    • 85033102048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nagel speaks of morality posing "a serious threat to the kind of personal life that many of us take to be desirable" (View from Nowhere, p. 190). Wolf claims that the "moral saint" cannot realize "a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Bernard Williams argues that both Kantian and utilitarian theories will sometimes require us to abandon our "ground projects," those projects "which propel [a person] in the future, and give him (in a sense) a reason for living" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," in The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976], pp. 209-10). See Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 77-150, esp. pp. 115-17, and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 181-82 (worrying that a Kantian notion of obligation can "come to dominate life altogether"). Slote argues that a commitment to morality would require us to "deplore and disavow" (p. 85) certain otherwise admirable traits like "single-minded devotion to aesthetic goals or ideals" (p. 80) - because of their essential tendency also to produce immoral behavior. Michael Stocker is probably an exception to the characterization offered in the text. While most Morality Critics view the nonmoral goods and considerations as largely prudential in character, Stocker is concerned with phenomena like "love" and "friendship" whose value is probably not prudential. See "The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories."
    • Single-minded Devotion to Aesthetic Goals or Ideals , pp. 80
  • 62
    • 0007630868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nagel speaks of morality posing "a serious threat to the kind of personal life that many of us take to be desirable" (View from Nowhere, p. 190). Wolf claims that the "moral saint" cannot realize "a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Bernard Williams argues that both Kantian and utilitarian theories will sometimes require us to abandon our "ground projects," those projects "which propel [a person] in the future, and give him (in a sense) a reason for living" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," in The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976], pp. 209-10). See Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 77-150, esp. pp. 115-17, and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, esp. pp. 181-82 (worrying that a Kantian notion of obligation can "come to dominate life altogether"). Slote argues that a commitment to morality would require us to "deplore and disavow" (p. 85) certain otherwise admirable traits like "single-minded devotion to aesthetic goals or ideals" (p. 80) - because of their essential tendency also to produce immoral behavior. Michael Stocker is probably an exception to the characterization offered in the text. While most Morality Critics view the nonmoral goods and considerations as largely prudential in character, Stocker is concerned with phenomena like "love" and "friendship" whose value is probably not prudential. See "The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories."
    • The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories
    • Stocker, M.1
  • 63
    • 85033121199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Wolf: "The admiration of and striving toward achieving any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence are character traits it is valuable and desirable for people to have. . . . In thinking that it is good for a person to strive for [this] ideal . . . , we implicitly acknowledge the goodness of ideals incompatible with that of the moral saint" (p. 426). The truth of IT is defended in slightly different ways by the Critics, depending on whether they are taking consequentialism or Kantianism as the target. (For consequentialism, and specifically Utilitarianism, see Wolf, pp. 427-30; Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," pp. 93-118, "Persons, Character, and Morality," pp. 199-200, 210; for Kantianism, see Wolf, pp. 430-33; Williams, "Persons, Character, and Morality," and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, chap. 10.) However, as a number of writers have noted, there is a common element in both deontological and consequentialist theories that is supposed to generate IT, i.e., their commitment to an impersonal point of view and impartial value. Because of this commitment, these theories cannot (according to the Critics) do real justice to the importance of our various personal and partial attachments and projects: such projects and attachments can always be sacrificed when impersonal and impartial considerations demand it. Our most important personal project is, after all, just one among many from the moral point of view, which is precisely why (according to the Critics) morality cannot do justice to its significance and value. See Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 189-91.
    • The Admiration of and Striving Toward Achieving Any of a Great Variety of Forms of Personal Excellence Are Character Traits It Is Valuable and Desirable for People to Have. . . . In Thinking That It Is Good for a Person to Strive for [this] Ideal . . . , We Implicitly Acknowledge the Goodness of Ideals Incompatible with That of the Moral Saint , pp. 426
    • Wolf1
  • 64
    • 85033104684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Wolf: "The admiration of and striving toward achieving any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence are character traits it is valuable and desirable for people to have. . . . In thinking that it is good for a person to strive for [this] ideal . . . , we implicitly acknowledge the goodness of ideals incompatible with that of the moral saint" (p. 426). The truth of IT is defended in slightly different ways by the Critics, depending on whether they are taking consequentialism or Kantianism as the target. (For consequentialism, and specifically Utilitarianism, see Wolf, pp. 427-30; Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," pp. 93-118, "Persons, Character, and Morality," pp. 199-200, 210; for Kantianism, see Wolf, pp. 430-33; Williams, "Persons, Character, and Morality," and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, chap. 10.) However, as a number of writers have noted, there is a common element in both deontological and consequentialist theories that is supposed to generate IT, i.e., their commitment to an impersonal point of view and impartial value. Because of this commitment, these theories cannot (according to the Critics) do real justice to the importance of our various personal and partial attachments and projects: such projects and attachments can always be sacrificed when impersonal and impartial considerations demand it. Our most important personal project is, after all, just one among many from the moral point of view, which is precisely why (according to the Critics) morality cannot do justice to its significance and value. See Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 189-91.
    • Wolf1
  • 65
    • 0040379930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Wolf: "The admiration of and striving toward achieving any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence are character traits it is valuable and desirable for people to have. . . . In thinking that it is good for a person to strive for [this] ideal . . . , we implicitly acknowledge the goodness of ideals incompatible with that of the moral saint" (p. 426). The truth of IT is defended in slightly different ways by the Critics, depending on whether they are taking consequentialism or Kantianism as the target. (For consequentialism, and specifically Utilitarianism, see Wolf, pp. 427-30; Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," pp. 93-118, "Persons, Character, and Morality," pp. 199-200, 210; for Kantianism, see Wolf, pp. 430-33; Williams, "Persons, Character, and Morality," and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, chap. 10.) However, as a number of writers have noted, there is a common element in both deontological and consequentialist theories that is supposed to generate IT, i.e., their commitment to an impersonal point of view and impartial value. Because of this commitment, these theories cannot (according to the Critics) do real justice to the importance of our various personal and partial attachments and projects: such projects and attachments can always be sacrificed when impersonal and impartial considerations demand it. Our most important personal project is, after all, just one among many from the moral point of view, which is precisely why (according to the Critics) morality cannot do justice to its significance and value. See Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 189-91.
    • A Critique of Utilitarianism , pp. 93-118
    • Williams1
  • 66
    • 0002166163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Wolf: "The admiration of and striving toward achieving any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence are character traits it is valuable and desirable for people to have. . . . In thinking that it is good for a person to strive for [this] ideal . . . , we implicitly acknowledge the goodness of ideals incompatible with that of the moral saint" (p. 426). The truth of IT is defended in slightly different ways by the Critics, depending on whether they are taking consequentialism or Kantianism as the target. (For consequentialism, and specifically Utilitarianism, see Wolf, pp. 427-30; Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," pp. 93-118, "Persons, Character, and Morality," pp. 199-200, 210; for Kantianism, see Wolf, pp. 430-33; Williams, "Persons, Character, and Morality," and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, chap. 10.) However, as a number of writers have noted, there is a common element in both deontological and consequentialist theories that is supposed to generate IT, i.e., their commitment to an impersonal point of view and impartial value. Because of this commitment, these theories cannot (according to the Critics) do real justice to the importance of our various personal and partial attachments and projects: such projects and attachments can always be sacrificed when impersonal and impartial considerations demand it. Our most important personal project is, after all, just one among many from the moral point of view, which is precisely why (according to the Critics) morality cannot do justice to its significance and value. See Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 189-91.
    • Persons, Character, and Morality , pp. 199-200
  • 67
    • 85033101462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Wolf: "The admiration of and striving toward achieving any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence are character traits it is valuable and desirable for people to have. . . . In thinking that it is good for a person to strive for [this] ideal . . . , we implicitly acknowledge the goodness of ideals incompatible with that of the moral saint" (p. 426). The truth of IT is defended in slightly different ways by the Critics, depending on whether they are taking consequentialism or Kantianism as the target. (For consequentialism, and specifically Utilitarianism, see Wolf, pp. 427-30; Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," pp. 93-118, "Persons, Character, and Morality," pp. 199-200, 210; for Kantianism, see Wolf, pp. 430-33; Williams, "Persons, Character, and Morality," and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, chap. 10.) However, as a number of writers have noted, there is a common element in both deontological and consequentialist theories that is supposed to generate IT, i.e., their commitment to an impersonal point of view and impartial value. Because of this commitment, these theories cannot (according to the Critics) do real justice to the importance of our various personal and partial attachments and projects: such projects and attachments can always be sacrificed when impersonal and impartial considerations demand it. Our most important personal project is, after all, just one among many from the moral point of view, which is precisely why (according to the Critics) morality cannot do justice to its significance and value. See Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 189-91.
    • Wolf1
  • 68
    • 85033122832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Persons, character, and morality
    • chap. 10.
    • For example, Wolf: "The admiration of and striving toward achieving any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence are character traits it is valuable and desirable for people to have. . . . In thinking that it is good for a person to strive for [this] ideal . . . , we implicitly acknowledge the goodness of ideals incompatible with that of the moral saint" (p. 426). The truth of IT is defended in slightly different ways by the Critics, depending on whether they are taking consequentialism or Kantianism as the target. (For consequentialism, and specifically Utilitarianism, see Wolf, pp. 427-30; Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," pp. 93-118, "Persons, Character, and Morality," pp. 199-200, 210; for Kantianism, see Wolf, pp. 430-33; Williams, "Persons, Character, and Morality," and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, chap. 10.) However, as a number of writers have noted, there is a common element in both deontological and consequentialist theories that is supposed to generate IT, i.e., their commitment to an impersonal point of view and impartial value. Because of this commitment, these theories cannot (according to the Critics) do real justice to the importance of our various personal and partial attachments and projects: such projects and attachments can always be sacrificed when impersonal and impartial considerations demand it. Our most important personal project is, after all, just one among many from the moral point of view, which is precisely why (according to the Critics) morality cannot do justice to its significance and value. See Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 189-91.
    • Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
    • Williams1
  • 69
    • 0004207980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Wolf: "The admiration of and striving toward achieving any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence are character traits it is valuable and desirable for people to have. . . . In thinking that it is good for a person to strive for [this] ideal . . . , we implicitly acknowledge the goodness of ideals incompatible with that of the moral saint" (p. 426). The truth of IT is defended in slightly different ways by the Critics, depending on whether they are taking consequentialism or Kantianism as the target. (For consequentialism, and specifically Utilitarianism, see Wolf, pp. 427-30; Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," pp. 93-118, "Persons, Character, and Morality," pp. 199-200, 210; for Kantianism, see Wolf, pp. 430-33; Williams, "Persons, Character, and Morality," and Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, chap. 10.) However, as a number of writers have noted, there is a common element in both deontological and consequentialist theories that is supposed to generate IT, i.e., their commitment to an impersonal point of view and impartial value. Because of this commitment, these theories cannot (according to the Critics) do real justice to the importance of our various personal and partial attachments and projects: such projects and attachments can always be sacrificed when impersonal and impartial considerations demand it. Our most important personal project is, after all, just one among many from the moral point of view, which is precisely why (according to the Critics) morality cannot do justice to its significance and value. See Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 189-91.
    • View from Nowhere , pp. 189-191
    • Nagel1
  • 70
    • 85033118984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wolf challenges "the assumption that it is always better to be morally better" and concludes that "our values cannot be fully comprehended on the model of a hierarchical system with morality at the top" (p. 438). Slote claims that the possibility of admirable immorality should "[loosen]. . . our attachment to the 'overridingness' thesis" (p. 107). Williams concludes, "Life has to have substance if anything is to have sense, including adherence to the impartial [moral] system; but if it has substance, then it cannot grant supreme importance to the impartial system" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," p. 215). Owen Flanagan identifies "this assumption of the sovereignty of the moral good" as the target of critics like Wolf, Williams, and Slote (Owen Flanagan, "Admirable Immorality and Admirable Imperfection," Journal of Philosophy 83 [1986]: 41-60, p. 41). Note that for at least Williams, morality already does its damage - in the form of "alienation" - once it asks us to view our personal projects as up for grabs in moral deliberation (whether or not morality ultimately requires us to abandon them).
    • Wolf1
  • 71
    • 85033109992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wolf challenges "the assumption that it is always better to be morally better" and concludes that "our values cannot be fully comprehended on the model of a hierarchical system with morality at the top" (p. 438). Slote claims that the possibility of admirable immorality should "[loosen]. . . our attachment to the 'overridingness' thesis" (p. 107). Williams concludes, "Life has to have substance if anything is to have sense, including adherence to the impartial [moral] system; but if it has substance, then it cannot grant supreme importance to the impartial system" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," p. 215). Owen Flanagan identifies "this assumption of the sovereignty of the moral good" as the target of critics like Wolf, Williams, and Slote (Owen Flanagan, "Admirable Immorality and Admirable Imperfection," Journal of Philosophy 83 [1986]: 41-60, p. 41). Note that for at least Williams, morality already does its damage - in the form of "alienation" - once it asks us to view our personal projects as up for grabs in moral deliberation (whether or not morality ultimately requires us to abandon them).
    • Slote1
  • 72
    • 85033113392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Life has to have substance if anything is to have sense, including adherence to the impartial [moral] system; but if it has substance, then it cannot grant supreme importance to the impartial system
    • Wolf challenges "the assumption that it is always better to be morally better" and concludes that "our values cannot be fully comprehended on the model of a hierarchical system with morality at the top" (p. 438). Slote claims that the possibility of admirable immorality should "[loosen]. . . our attachment to the 'overridingness' thesis" (p. 107). Williams concludes, "Life has to have substance if anything is to have sense, including adherence to the impartial [moral] system; but if it has substance, then it cannot grant supreme importance to the impartial system" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," p. 215). Owen Flanagan identifies "this assumption of the sovereignty of the moral good" as the target of critics like Wolf, Williams, and Slote (Owen Flanagan, "Admirable Immorality and Admirable Imperfection," Journal of Philosophy 83 [1986]: 41-60, p. 41). Note that for at least Williams, morality already does its damage - in the form of "alienation" - once it asks us to view our personal projects as up for grabs in moral deliberation (whether or not morality ultimately requires us to abandon them).
    • Persons, Character, and Morality , pp. 215
    • Williams1
  • 73
    • 0003259494 scopus 로고
    • Admirable immorality and admirable imperfection
    • Wolf challenges "the assumption that it is always better to be morally better" and concludes that "our values cannot be fully comprehended on the model of a hierarchical system with morality at the top" (p. 438). Slote claims that the possibility of admirable immorality should "[loosen]. . . our attachment to the 'overridingness' thesis" (p. 107). Williams concludes, "Life has to have substance if anything is to have sense, including adherence to the impartial [moral] system; but if it has substance, then it cannot grant supreme importance to the impartial system" ("Persons, Character, and Morality," p. 215). Owen Flanagan identifies "this assumption of the sovereignty of the moral good" as the target of critics like Wolf, Williams, and Slote (Owen Flanagan, "Admirable Immorality and Admirable Imperfection," Journal of Philosophy 83 [1986]: 41-60, p. 41). Note that for at least Williams, morality already does its damage - in the form of "alienation" - once it asks us to view our personal projects as up for grabs in moral deliberation (whether or not morality ultimately requires us to abandon them).
    • (1986) Journal of Philosophy , vol.83 , pp. 41-60
    • Flanagan, O.1
  • 74
    • 0040269757 scopus 로고
    • Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality
    • reprinted ed. S. Scheffler Oxford: Oxford University Press, esp.
    • On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialism and Its Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp. 113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983): 298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese 72 (1987): 71-89, esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed does not permit "unconditional attachment" to personal projects irrespective of their morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further that such unconditional attachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity (Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p. 308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solipsism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96 (1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues in n. 51, below.
    • (1988) Consequentialism and Its Critics , pp. 93-133
    • Railton, P.1
  • 75
    • 0039786333 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism and integrity
    • esp.
    • On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialism and Its Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp. 113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983): 298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese 72 (1987): 71-89, esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed does not permit "unconditional attachment" to personal projects irrespective of their morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further that such unconditional attachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity (Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p. 308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solipsism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96 (1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues in n. 51, below.
    • (1983) Monist , vol.66 , pp. 298-311
    • Conly, S.1
  • 76
    • 0004255852 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Hackett, bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3
    • On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialism and Its Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp. 113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983): 298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese 72 (1987): 71-89, esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed does not permit "unconditional attachment" to personal projects irrespective of their morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further that such unconditional attachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity (Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p. 308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solipsism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96 (1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues in n. 51, below.
    • (1981) The Methods of Ethics, 7th Ed.
    • Sidgwick, H.1
  • 77
    • 0008992964 scopus 로고
    • Act-utilitarianism: Account of right-making characteristics or decision-making procedure?
    • On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialism and Its Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp. 113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983): 298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese 72 (1987): 71-89, esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed does not permit "unconditional attachment" to personal projects irrespective of their morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further that such unconditional attachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity (Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p. 308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solipsism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96 (1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues in n. 51, below.
    • (1971) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.8 , pp. 257-265
    • Bales, R.E.1
  • 78
    • 85033106179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the "supererogation"
    • response: see, e.g., Nagel
    • On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialism and Its Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp. 113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983): 298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese 72 (1987): 71-89, esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed does not permit "unconditional attachment" to personal projects irrespective of their morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further that such unconditional attachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity (Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p. 308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solipsism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96 (1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues in n. 51, below.
    • View from Nowhere , pp. 203-204
    • Brink1
  • 79
    • 0039787648 scopus 로고
    • Abolishing morality
    • esp.
    • On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialism and Its Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp. 113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983): 298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese 72 (1987): 71-89, esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed does not permit "unconditional attachment" to personal projects irrespective of their morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further that such unconditional attachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity (Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p. 308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solipsism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96 (1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues in n. 51, below.
    • (1987) Synthese , vol.72 , pp. 71-89
    • Darwall, S.1
  • 80
    • 11544330876 scopus 로고
    • Integrity and impartiality
    • On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialism and Its Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp. 113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983): 298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese 72 (1987): 71-89, esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed does not permit "unconditional attachment" to personal projects irrespective of their morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further that such unconditional attachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity (Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p. 308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solipsism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96 (1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues in n. 51, below.
    • (1983) Monist , vol.66 , pp. 233-250
    • Herman, B.1
  • 81
    • 85033119670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialism and Its Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp. 113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983): 298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese 72 (1987): 71-89, esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed does not permit "unconditional attachment" to personal projects irrespective of their morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further that such unconditional attachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity (Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p. 308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solipsism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96 (1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues in n. 51, below.
    • Conly1
  • 82
    • 60950727167 scopus 로고
    • On admirable immorality
    • esp.
    • On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialism and Its Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp. 113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983): 298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1, sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese 72 (1987): 71-89, esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed does not permit "unconditional attachment" to personal projects irrespective of their morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further that such unconditional attachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity (Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p. 308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solipsism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96 (1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues in n. 51, below.
    • (1986) Ethics , vol.96 , pp. 557-566
    • Baron, M.1
  • 84
    • 85033118493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As a freestanding complaint, this could be made by a Theory Critic as well as a Morality Critic: for the former, it would come in the context of an attack on the reductionist aims of Theory based on the real "diversity of goods"; for the latter, it would serve to show that the reason the ("perfect master's") Moral Life is incompatible with the Good Life is that it privileges some type of moral value at the expense of other, nonmoral values. Quite generally, it is easy to see how, e.g., objections to the reductionist aims of Theory based on the plurality of values can quickly start to sound like objections to Morality for wrongly overriding other distinct sources of value. The difference here may only be a matter of emphasis, though it is a difference that is real enough: the Theory Critic invokes the plurality of values to emphasize the inadequacy of a theoretical framework which excludes so much, while the Morality Critic invokes the plurality of values in order to emphasize the costs of morality's OT and to argue against it. The ease with which we might move from one sort of criticism to the other should not obscure the fact, however, that many writers lodge themselves firmly in one camp rather than the other - in fact, only Williams and Foot seem to take both sorts of critical positions. Wolf, e.g., is explicit in distancing herself from any critique of theory per se: "The flaws of a perfect master of a moral theory need not reflect flaws in the intramoral content of the theory itself" (p. 435). Rather, for
    • The Flaws of a Perfect Master of a Moral Theory Need Not Reflect Flaws in the Intramoral Content of the Theory Itself , pp. 435
    • Williams1    Foot2    Wolf3
  • 86
    • 0004047249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon, 1990, esp.
    • A different question is whether he offers an ethical theory more akin to ancient ones - say, a type of virtue ethics, as some recent writers have suggested. See, e.g., John Casey, Pagan Virtue: An Essay in Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1990), esp. pp. 79-83; Lester Hunt, Nietzsche and the Origin of Virtue (London: Routledge, 1991). The difficulties with Hunt's account will serve to highlight the problems confronting this interpretation of Nietzsche. According to Hunt, Nietzsche's theory of virtue is "procedural": "it specifies which traits are virtues by indicating a certain process and declaring that any trait that arises from this process is virtuous" (p. 145). The relevant process is given by Nietzsche's "experimentalism," which requires us to experiment with different goals until we find those which bring about "a complete integration of the psyche" (p. 141), such that "one part of the self imposes order on other, potentially chaotic parts by successfully orienting the subordinate parts towards its own purposes" (p. 128). The traits that are conducive to the integrating goals are, says Hunt, virtues for Nietzsche. There is certainly something broadly right about this picture, though its vagueness is only one of its several problems. First, the theory seems not so much procedural as substantive, since it employs a substantive criterion (integration of the self) for identifying which goal-oriented activities involve virtues. Second, it seems to stretch Nietzsche's ambitions considerably to attribute to him something called a "procedural theory of virtue." Third, Hunt gives almost none of the detail about particular virtues that interest most contemporary writers (including, e.g., Casey), even relegating Nietzsche's own specific virtue lists to an endnote (p. 187, n. 4). While Hunt has a multitude of interesting things to say about Nietzsche, it is not clear that his account makes Nietzsche a virtue theorist of much practical or philosophical help.
    • Pagan Virtue: An Essay in Ethics , pp. 79-83
    • Casey, J.1
  • 87
    • 0040974181 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • A different question is whether he offers an ethical theory more akin to ancient ones - say, a type of virtue ethics, as some recent writers have suggested. See, e.g., John Casey, Pagan Virtue: An Essay in Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1990), esp. pp. 79-83; Lester Hunt, Nietzsche and the Origin of Virtue (London: Routledge, 1991). The difficulties with Hunt's account will serve to highlight the problems confronting this interpretation of Nietzsche. According to Hunt, Nietzsche's theory of virtue is "procedural": "it specifies which traits are virtues by indicating a certain process and declaring that any trait that arises from this process is virtuous" (p. 145). The relevant process is given by Nietzsche's "experimentalism," which requires us to experiment with different goals until we find those which bring about "a complete integration of the psyche" (p. 141), such that "one part of the self imposes order on other, potentially chaotic parts by successfully orienting the subordinate parts towards its own purposes" (p. 128). The traits that are conducive to the integrating goals are, says Hunt, virtues for Nietzsche. There is certainly something broadly right about this picture, though its vagueness is only one of its several problems. First, the theory seems not so much procedural as substantive, since it employs a substantive criterion (integration of the self) for identifying which goal-oriented activities involve virtues. Second, it seems to stretch Nietzsche's ambitions considerably to attribute to him something called a "procedural theory of virtue." Third, Hunt gives almost none of the detail about particular virtues that interest most contemporary writers (including, e.g., Casey), even relegating Nietzsche's own specific virtue lists to an endnote (p. 187, n. 4). While Hunt has a multitude of interesting things to say about Nietzsche, it is not clear that his account makes Nietzsche a virtue theorist of much practical or philosophical help.
    • (1991) Nietzsche and the Origin of Virtue , pp. 145
    • Hunt, L.1
  • 88
    • 85033102985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Experimentalism
    • A different question is whether he offers an ethical theory more akin to ancient ones - say, a type of virtue ethics, as some recent writers have suggested. See, e.g., John Casey, Pagan Virtue: An Essay in Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1990), esp. pp. 79-83; Lester Hunt, Nietzsche and the Origin of Virtue (London: Routledge, 1991). The difficulties with Hunt's account will serve to highlight the problems confronting this interpretation of Nietzsche. According to Hunt, Nietzsche's theory of virtue is "procedural": "it specifies which traits are virtues by indicating a certain process and declaring that any trait that arises from this process is virtuous" (p. 145). The relevant process is given by Nietzsche's "experimentalism," which requires us to experiment with different goals until we find those which bring about "a complete integration of the psyche" (p. 141), such that "one part of the self imposes order on other, potentially chaotic parts by successfully orienting the subordinate parts towards its own purposes" (p. 128). The traits that are conducive to the integrating goals are, says Hunt, virtues for Nietzsche. There is certainly something broadly right about this picture, though its vagueness is only one of its several problems. First, the theory seems not so much procedural as substantive, since it employs a substantive criterion (integration of the self) for identifying which goal-oriented activities involve virtues. Second, it seems to stretch Nietzsche's ambitions considerably to attribute to him something called a "procedural theory of virtue." Third, Hunt gives almost none of the detail about particular virtues that interest most contemporary writers (including, e.g., Casey), even relegating Nietzsche's own specific virtue lists to an endnote (p. 187, n. 4). While Hunt has a multitude of interesting things to say about Nietzsche, it is not clear that his account makes Nietzsche a virtue theorist of much practical or philosophical help.
    • A Complete Integration of the Psyche , pp. 141
    • Nietzsche1
  • 89
    • 85033110365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A different question is whether he offers an ethical theory more akin to ancient ones - say, a type of virtue ethics, as some recent writers have suggested. See, e.g., John Casey, Pagan Virtue: An Essay in Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1990), esp. pp. 79-83; Lester Hunt, Nietzsche and the Origin of Virtue (London: Routledge, 1991). The difficulties with Hunt's account will serve to highlight the problems confronting this interpretation of Nietzsche. According to Hunt, Nietzsche's theory of virtue is "procedural": "it specifies which traits are virtues by indicating a certain process and declaring that any trait that arises from this process is virtuous" (p. 145). The relevant process is given by Nietzsche's "experimentalism," which requires us to experiment with different goals until we find those which bring about "a complete integration of the psyche" (p. 141), such that "one part of the self imposes order on other, potentially chaotic parts by successfully orienting the subordinate parts towards its own purposes" (p. 128). The traits that are conducive to the integrating goals are, says Hunt, virtues for Nietzsche. There is certainly something broadly right about this picture, though its vagueness is only one of its several problems. First, the theory seems not so much procedural as substantive, since it employs a substantive criterion (integration of the self) for identifying which goal-oriented activities involve virtues. Second, it seems to stretch Nietzsche's ambitions considerably to attribute to him something called a "procedural theory of virtue." Third, Hunt gives almost none of the detail about particular virtues that interest most contemporary writers (including, e.g., Casey), even relegating Nietzsche's own specific virtue lists to an endnote (p. 187, n. 4). While Hunt has a multitude of interesting things to say about Nietzsche, it is not clear that his account makes Nietzsche a virtue theorist of much practical or philosophical help.
    • One Part of the Self Imposes Order on Other, Potentially Chaotic Parts by Successfully Orienting the Subordinate Parts Towards Its Own Purposes , pp. 128
  • 90
    • 85033104380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procedural theory of virtue
    • including, e.g., Casey, even relegating Nietzsche's own specific virtue lists to an endnote
    • A different question is whether he offers an ethical theory more akin to ancient ones - say, a type of virtue ethics, as some recent writers have suggested. See, e.g., John Casey, Pagan Virtue: An Essay in Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1990), esp. pp. 79-83; Lester Hunt, Nietzsche and the Origin of Virtue (London: Routledge, 1991). The difficulties with Hunt's account will serve to highlight the problems confronting this interpretation of Nietzsche. According to Hunt, Nietzsche's theory of virtue is "procedural": "it specifies which traits are virtues by indicating a certain process and declaring that any trait that arises from this process is virtuous" (p. 145). The relevant process is given by Nietzsche's "experimentalism," which requires us to experiment with different goals until we find those which bring about "a complete integration of the psyche" (p. 141), such that "one part of the self imposes order on other, potentially chaotic parts by successfully orienting the subordinate parts towards its own purposes" (p. 128). The traits that are conducive to the integrating goals are, says Hunt, virtues for Nietzsche. There is certainly something broadly right about this picture, though its vagueness is only one of its several problems. First, the theory seems not so much procedural as substantive, since it employs a substantive criterion (integration of the self) for identifying which goal-oriented activities involve virtues. Second, it seems to stretch Nietzsche's ambitions considerably to attribute to him something called a "procedural theory of virtue." Third, Hunt gives almost none of the detail about particular virtues that interest most contemporary writers (including, e.g., Casey), even relegating Nietzsche's own specific virtue lists to an endnote (p. 187, n. 4). While Hunt has a multitude of interesting things to say about Nietzsche, it is not clear that his account makes Nietzsche a virtue theorist of much practical or philosophical help.
    • Third, Hunt Gives Almost None of the Detail about Particular Virtues That Interest Most Contemporary Writers , pp. 187
    • Nietzsche1
  • 91
    • 0040866607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The paradox of fatalism and self-creation in Nietzsche
    • ed. C. Janaway (Oxford: Oxford University Press, in press)
    • For a more substantial discussion of these oft-neglected themes in Nietzsche's work, see Brian Leiter, "The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche," in Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche's Educator, ed. C. Janaway (Oxford: Oxford University Press, in press).
    • Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer As Nietzsche's Educator
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 93
    • 0040378667 scopus 로고
    • Morality in the pejorative sense: On the logic of nietzsche's critique of morality
    • See esp. Brian Leiter, "Morality in the Pejorative Sense: On the Logic of Nietzsche's Critique of Morality," British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3 (1995): 113-45, and also Leiter, "Beyond Good and Evil," History of Philosophy Quarterly 10 (1993): 261-70. The former sets out the affinities and differences my account has with those common in the secondary literature.
    • (1995) British Journal for the History of Philosophy , vol.3 , pp. 113-145
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 94
    • 0040378667 scopus 로고
    • Beyond good and evil
    • See esp. Brian Leiter, "Morality in the Pejorative Sense: On the Logic of Nietzsche's Critique of Morality," British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3 (1995): 113-45, and also Leiter, "Beyond Good and Evil," History of Philosophy Quarterly 10 (1993): 261-70. The former sets out the affinities and differences my account has with those common in the secondary literature.
    • (1993) History of Philosophy Quarterly , vol.10 , pp. 261-270
    • Leiter1
  • 95
    • 84875345997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For some nonpejorative uses of the word 'morality', see, e.g., TI, IV, sec. 4 (where he speaks of the possibility of a "healthy morality" [gesunde Moral]), and BGE, 202 ("higher moralities" [Morale]). On the nature and content of such a morality, see my "Beyond Good and Evil."
    • Beyond Good and Evil
  • 96
    • 0040972960 scopus 로고
    • 'ought,' 'can,' free will and responsibility
    • London: Routledge
    • Smart's Utilitarianism is a good example of an MPS that embodies a normative agenda that is objectionable on Nietzschean grounds, while involving no commitment to an untenable metaphysics of agency. See esp. J. J. C. Smart, "'Ought,' 'Can,' Free Will and Responsibility," in Ethics, Persuasion and Truth (London: Routledge, 1984). Bernard Williams has gone so far as to suggest that because blaming can be justified on utilitarian grounds alone (and regardless of whether agents have free will), Utilitarianism is, at best, a "marginal member of the morality system" - where Williams takes Kantian morality to be the paradigmatic member (Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, p. 178).
    • (1984) Ethics, Persuasion and Truth
    • Smart, J.J.C.1
  • 97
    • 85033117760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marginal member of the morality system
    • Smart's Utilitarianism is a good example of an MPS that embodies a normative agenda that is objectionable on Nietzschean grounds, while involving no commitment to an untenable metaphysics of agency. See esp. J. J. C. Smart, "'Ought,' 'Can,' Free Will and Responsibility," in Ethics, Persuasion and Truth (London: Routledge, 1984). Bernard Williams has gone so far as to suggest that because blaming can be justified on utilitarian grounds alone (and regardless of whether agents have free will), Utilitarianism is, at best, a "marginal member of the morality system" - where Williams takes Kantian morality to be the paradigmatic member (Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, p. 178).
    • Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy , pp. 178
    • Williams, B.1
  • 99
    • 85033125730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Nehamas, pp. 209, 214, 223.
    • Nehamas1
  • 100
    • 85033101680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See D, 163; BGE, 62, 212; GM, III, sec. 14; A, 5, 24; EH, IV, sec. 4; WP, 274, 345, 400, 870, 879, 957. For example, in a work of 1880 he writes, "Our weak, unmanly, social concepts of good and evil and their tremendous ascendancy over body and soul have finally weakened all bodies and souls and snapped the self-reliant, independent, unprejudiced men, the pillars of a strong civilization" (D, 163). While in a posthumously published note of 1885 he remarks that "men of great creativity, the really great men according to my understanding, will be sought in vain today" because "nothing stands more malignantly in the way of their rise and evolution . . . than what in Europe today is called simply 'morality'" (WP, 957). Similarly, in a late note of 1888, he observes (in a passage plainly echoing the preface of GM),
  • 101
    • 85033111415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I should not be construed here as endorsing the idiosyncratic view defended in the last chapter of Nehamas. According to Nehamas, Nietzsche does not describe his ideal person - his "higher man" - but rather "exemplifies" such a person in the form of the "character" that is constituted by and exemplified in his literary corpus. Nietzsche, however, describes at great length and in many places (see D, 201; GS, 55; BGE, 287; WP, 943) the types of persons he admires, and he also describes himself as such a person (see EH, I, sec. 2). For further criticism of Nehamas on this and other points, see my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism."
  • 102
    • 85033112216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This type of simplifying move, however, does not obviously help us get a fix on who "lower men" are supposed to be. Yet not saying more about "lower men" is not necessarily problematic for my project here of characterizing Nietzsche's conception of MPS. For the heart of Nietzsche's complaint is simply that MPS has a deleterious effect on higher types (i.e., those who manifest human excellence). It is true that Nietzsche also seems to think that MPS is in the interests of other persons - "lower men" - but this by itself is not objectionable; recall that Nietzsche says, "The ideas of the herd should rule in the herd - but not reach out beyond it" (WP, 287). It is this "reaching out beyond," then, that is at issue because it is this that harms "higher men." If there were a social order in which MPS existed - and in which it served the interests of "lower" types - without having any effects on potentially "higher men," then one would imagine that Nietzsche should have no objections. In that case, one could leave the issue of who "lower men" are pleasantly vague without any cost to the analytical task of getting clear about Nietzsche's critique of morality.
  • 103
    • 85033115560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • So an agent who says, colloquially speaking, "I would gladly lead my life again, except for the time in my thirties when I was ill and depressed," would not affirm life in the requisite sense.
  • 104
    • 85033120350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For example, EH, III, Z-1: "The idea of the eternal recurrence, this highest formulation of affirmation that is at all attainable" (cf. BGE, 56).
  • 105
    • 0040974176 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • Some writers (e.g., Richard Schacht, Nietische [London: Routledge, 1983]) have argued that Nietzsche objects to MPS centrally because it is harmful to "life." The main difficulty with this approach, even as it is typically developed, is its vagueness: as Mark Platts remarks, "Morality versus life is not the best defined of battle lines" (Moral Realities [London: Routledge, 1991], p. 220). I argue elsewhere that when Nietzsche speaks of morality being harmful to "life," he really means harmful to "higher men"; see my "Morality in the Pejorative Sense," pp. 132-34. Other writers (including Schacht again) have suggested that Nietzsche criticizes morality by reference to his preferred standard of "value" as "will to power." I ignore this possibility here, because it seems to make the notion of "will to power" more central to Nietzsche's mature thought than recent scholarship would suggest is warranted. See Mazzino Montinari, "Nietzsches Nachlass von 1885 bis 1888 oder Textkritik und Wille zur Macht," in his Nietzsche Lesen (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1982); Clark, pp. 212-27. Textual worries aside, I doubt whether a good argument can even be made out that "will to power" provides Nietzsche with his standard of value. I make this case in an unpublished manuscript, "Nietzsche's Metaethics."
    • (1983) Nietische
    • Schacht, R.1
  • 106
    • 0039786328 scopus 로고
    • Morality versus life is not the best defined of battle lines
    • London: Routledge
    • Some writers (e.g., Richard Schacht, Nietische [London: Routledge, 1983]) have argued that Nietzsche objects to MPS centrally because it is harmful to "life." The main difficulty with this approach, even as it is typically developed, is its vagueness: as Mark Platts remarks, "Morality versus life is not the best defined of battle lines" (Moral Realities [London: Routledge, 1991], p. 220). I argue elsewhere that when Nietzsche speaks of morality being harmful to "life," he really means harmful to "higher men"; see my "Morality in the Pejorative Sense," pp. 132-34. Other writers (including Schacht again) have suggested that Nietzsche criticizes morality by reference to his preferred standard of "value" as "will to power." I ignore this possibility here, because it seems to make the notion of "will to power" more central to Nietzsche's mature thought than recent scholarship would suggest is warranted. See Mazzino Montinari, "Nietzsches Nachlass von 1885 bis 1888 oder Textkritik und Wille zur Macht," in his Nietzsche Lesen (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1982); Clark, pp. 212-27. Textual worries aside, I doubt whether a good argument can even be made out that "will to power" provides Nietzsche with his standard of value. I make this case in an unpublished manuscript, "Nietzsche's Metaethics."
    • (1991) Moral Realities , pp. 220
    • Platts, M.1
  • 107
    • 85033104993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some writers (e.g., Richard Schacht, Nietische [London: Routledge, 1983]) have argued that Nietzsche objects to MPS centrally because it is harmful to "life." The main difficulty with this approach, even as it is typically developed, is its vagueness: as Mark Platts remarks, "Morality versus life is not the best defined of battle lines" (Moral Realities [London: Routledge, 1991], p. 220). I argue elsewhere that when Nietzsche speaks of morality being harmful to "life," he really means harmful to "higher men"; see my "Morality in the Pejorative Sense," pp. 132-34. Other writers (including Schacht again) have suggested that Nietzsche criticizes morality by reference to his preferred standard of "value" as "will to power." I ignore this possibility here, because it seems to make the notion of "will to power" more central to Nietzsche's mature thought than recent scholarship would suggest is warranted. See Mazzino Montinari, "Nietzsches Nachlass von 1885 bis 1888 oder Textkritik und Wille zur Macht," in his Nietzsche Lesen (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1982); Clark, pp. 212-27. Textual worries aside, I doubt whether a good argument can even be made out that "will to power" provides Nietzsche with his standard of value. I make this case in an unpublished manuscript, "Nietzsche's Metaethics."
    • Morality in the Pejorative Sense , pp. 132-134
  • 108
    • 0039787654 scopus 로고
    • Nietzsches nachlass von 1885 bis 1888 oder textkritik und wille zur macht
    • Berlin: de Gruyter
    • Some writers (e.g., Richard Schacht, Nietische [London: Routledge, 1983]) have argued that Nietzsche objects to MPS centrally because it is harmful to "life." The main difficulty with this approach, even as it is typically developed, is its vagueness: as Mark Platts remarks, "Morality versus life is not the best defined of battle lines" (Moral Realities [London: Routledge, 1991], p. 220). I argue elsewhere that when Nietzsche speaks of morality being harmful to "life," he really means harmful to "higher men"; see my "Morality in the Pejorative Sense," pp. 132-34. Other writers (including Schacht again) have suggested that Nietzsche criticizes morality by reference to his preferred standard of "value" as "will to power." I ignore this possibility here, because it seems to make the notion of "will to power" more central to Nietzsche's mature thought than recent scholarship would suggest is warranted. See Mazzino Montinari, "Nietzsches Nachlass von 1885 bis 1888 oder Textkritik und Wille zur Macht," in his Nietzsche Lesen (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1982); Clark, pp. 212-27. Textual worries aside, I doubt whether a good argument can even be made out that "will to power" provides Nietzsche with his standard of value. I make this case in an unpublished manuscript, "Nietzsche's Metaethics."
    • (1982) Nietzsche Lesen
    • Montinari, M.1
  • 109
    • 85033121446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some writers (e.g., Richard Schacht, Nietische [London: Routledge, 1983]) have argued that Nietzsche objects to MPS centrally because it is harmful to "life." The main difficulty with this approach, even as it is typically developed, is its vagueness: as Mark Platts remarks, "Morality versus life is not the best defined of battle lines" (Moral Realities [London: Routledge, 1991], p. 220). I argue elsewhere that when Nietzsche speaks of morality being harmful to "life," he really means harmful to "higher men"; see my "Morality in the Pejorative Sense," pp. 132-34. Other writers (including Schacht again) have suggested that Nietzsche criticizes morality by reference to his preferred standard of "value" as "will to power." I ignore this possibility here, because it seems to make the notion of "will to power" more central to Nietzsche's mature thought than recent scholarship would suggest is warranted. See Mazzino Montinari, "Nietzsches Nachlass von 1885 bis 1888 oder Textkritik und Wille zur Macht," in his Nietzsche Lesen (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1982); Clark, pp. 212-27. Textual worries aside, I doubt whether a good argument can even be made out that "will to power" provides Nietzsche with his standard of value. I make this case in an unpublished manuscript, "Nietzsche's Metaethics."
    • Clark1
  • 110
    • 85033120425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some writers (e.g., Richard Schacht, Nietische [London: Routledge, 1983]) have argued that Nietzsche objects to MPS centrally because it is harmful to "life." The main difficulty with this approach, even as it is typically developed, is its vagueness: as Mark Platts remarks, "Morality versus life is not the best defined of battle lines" (Moral Realities [London: Routledge, 1991], p. 220). I argue elsewhere that when Nietzsche speaks of morality being harmful to "life," he really means harmful to "higher men"; see my "Morality in the Pejorative Sense," pp. 132-34. Other writers (including Schacht again) have suggested that Nietzsche criticizes morality by reference to his preferred standard of "value" as "will to power." I ignore this possibility here, because it seems to make the notion of "will to power" more central to Nietzsche's mature thought than recent scholarship would suggest is warranted. See Mazzino Montinari, "Nietzsches Nachlass von 1885 bis 1888 oder Textkritik und Wille zur Macht," in his Nietzsche Lesen (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1982); Clark, pp. 212-27. Textual worries aside, I doubt whether a good argument can even be made out that "will to power" provides Nietzsche with his standard of value. I make this case in an unpublished manuscript, "Nietzsche's Metaethics."
    • Nietzsche's Metaethics
  • 112
    • 85033102320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Nietzsche only advocates "severe" self-love, i.e., highly critical concern with the self, as the only self-love conducive to the full flourishing of the strong and healthy individual. See EH, IV, sec. 7, and the further discussion below.
  • 113
    • 85033121124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One problem with this view is that its endpoint - the abolition of suffering and the reign of happiness - is an impossibility because Nietzsche holds that "happiness and unhappiness are sisters" (GS, 338), that we must have both in order to have either. Although the unity of apparent opposites is a recurring theme in Nietzsche, it is not central to his objection to this aspect of MPS. A useful discussion of this theme can be found in Nehamas, pp. 209-11.
    • Nehamas , pp. 209-211
  • 114
    • 85033119825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Nietzsche no doubt construes the doctrine thus uncharitably because he thinks that the "British utilitarians . . . walk clumsily and honorably in Bentham's footsteps" and that they have "not a new idea, no trace of a subtler version or twist of an old idea" (BGE, 228). Mill, of course, was at pains to develop a subtler hedonistic doctrine than Bentham's, though it is an open question whether in the process he does not pour all the content out of the notion of "pleasure." In any event, Nietzsche drew no distinction between Bentham and Mill - referring to the latter (in an especially intemperate spirit) as "the flathead John Stuart Mill" (WP, 30).
  • 115
    • 85033109973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Compare GS, pref. 3: "Only great pain is the ultimate liberator of the spirit. . . . I doubt that such pain makes us 'better'; but I know that it makes us more profound."
  • 117
    • 0039195315 scopus 로고
    • Compare this letter of January 1880, quoted ibid., p. 219: "My existence is a fearful burden. I would have thrown it off long ago if I had not been making the most instructive tests and experiments on mental and moral questions in precisely this condition of suffering and almost complete renunciation."
    • (1880) Nietzsche: A Critical Life , pp. 219
  • 118
    • 85033119896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Nietzsche, in fact, reverses the MPS valuation, commenting, "Never have I felt happier with myself than in the sickest and most painful periods of my life" (EH, III, HAH-4).
  • 119
    • 0013090814 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Richard Miller, Moral Differences (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1992), p. 309.
    • (1992) Moral Differences , pp. 309
    • Miller, R.1
  • 120
    • 85033119403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, even among Morality Critics we sometimes hear echoes of the specifically Nietzschean worry, e.g., in the famous Gauguin case, where it is supposed that the Moral Life would undermine "great creativity," or in Wolf's worry that the moral saint cannot achieve "any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Moreover, we have already noted that there is clearly an element of extremism running through Nietzsche's critical position; e.g., we can be sure that Nietzsche would not agree with Wolf that a critique of morality does not show "that moral value should not be an important, even the most important, kind of value we attend to in evaluating and improving ourselves and our world" (p. 438). Yet we can live (probably happily) with these differences of degree and still think that Nietzsche joins cause with the Morality Critics, quite broadly, in accepting the truth of IT and rejecting OT.
    • Any of a Great Variety of Forms of Personal Excellence , pp. 426
    • Wolf1
  • 121
    • 85033105276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, even among Morality Critics we sometimes hear echoes of the specifically Nietzschean worry, e.g., in the famous Gauguin case, where it is supposed that the Moral Life would undermine "great creativity," or in Wolf's worry that the moral saint cannot achieve "any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426). Moreover, we have already noted that there is clearly an element of extremism running through Nietzsche's critical position; e.g., we can be sure that Nietzsche would not agree with Wolf that a critique of morality does not show "that moral value should not be an important, even the most important, kind of value we attend to in evaluating and improving ourselves and our world" (p. 438). Yet we can live (probably happily) with these differences of degree and still think that Nietzsche joins cause with the Morality Critics, quite broadly, in accepting the truth of IT and rejecting OT.
    • Wolf1
  • 122
    • 85033112375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the literature cited above in n. 25. As we saw earlier, there are really two strands in the responses to the Morality Critics: what we might call "Bullet Biters" and "Accommodationists." Bullet Biters like Conly, Herman, and Baron simply "bite the bullet" on the challenge of the Morality Critics: yes, these writers concede, morality is incompatible with a certain sort of commitment to personal projects - but so much the better, the Bullet Biters claim. For the sort of ability of personal projects to override morality that the Critics envision is not appealing, admirable, or central to a person's character or integrity. By contrast, Accommodationists like Railton, Nagel, and Darwall accept the force of the Critics' challenge but claim that morality can, contrary to IT, accommodate the sorts of personal projects that the Morality Critics care about. It is the response of the Accommodationists that is analogous to the challenge posed by the Harm Puzzle. (Needless to say, the line between the two types of theory defenders is not hard and fast. See Railton's account of why "alienation is not always a bad thing," pp. 106-8, and compare with the position of the Bullet Biters.)
    • Alienation Is Not Always a Bad Thing , pp. 106-108
    • Railton1
  • 123
    • 85033113267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For doubts that this is, in fact, an adequate response, see Wolf, p. 428. For related discussion of the important political dimension of these issues, see Railton, pp. 122-23; and Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 206-7. For a very different perspective on this debate, however, see the scathing critique of the: Morality Critics (including Wolf) in Catherine Wilson, "On Some Alleged Limitations to Moral Endeavor," Journal of Philosophy 90 (1993): 275-89.
    • Wolf1
  • 124
    • 85033109836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For doubts that this is, in fact, an adequate response, see Wolf, p. 428. For related discussion of the important political dimension of these issues, see Railton, pp. 122-23; and Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 206-7. For a very different perspective on this debate, however, see the scathing critique of the: Morality Critics (including Wolf) in Catherine Wilson, "On Some Alleged Limitations to Moral Endeavor," Journal of Philosophy 90 (1993): 275-89.
    • Railton1
  • 125
    • 0004207980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For doubts that this is, in fact, an adequate response, see Wolf, p. 428. For related discussion of the important political dimension of these issues, see Railton, pp. 122-23; and Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 206-7. For a very different perspective on this debate, however, see the scathing critique of the: Morality Critics (including Wolf) in Catherine Wilson, "On Some Alleged Limitations to Moral Endeavor," Journal of Philosophy 90 (1993): 275-89.
    • View from Nowhere , pp. 206-207
    • Nagel1
  • 126
    • 0040972959 scopus 로고
    • On some alleged limitations to moral endeavor
    • For doubts that this is, in fact, an adequate response, see Wolf, p. 428. For related discussion of the important political dimension of these issues, see Railton, pp. 122-23; and Nagel, View from Nowhere, pp. 206-7. For a very different perspective on this debate, however, see the scathing critique of the: Morality Critics (including Wolf) in Catherine Wilson, "On Some Alleged Limitations to Moral Endeavor," Journal of Philosophy 90 (1993): 275-89.
    • (1993) Journal of Philosophy , vol.90 , pp. 275-289
    • Wilson, C.1
  • 127
    • 85033107648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, the theorist might object that, even if Nietzsche were right, all this would show is that our cultural practices need correction by a suitable moral theory, one that will permit nascent Nietzsches to suffer and the like. I shall postpone this worry for now and consider it, and several other objections to Nietzsche's position, in the final section of this paper.
  • 128
    • 84928439578 scopus 로고
    • Impartiality and ethical theory
    • Compare Lawrence Becker's observation that defenders of morality's commitment to impartiality try to show that the "purported inadequacies [of impartiality] . . . are not really attributable to a proper theoretical commitment to impartiality" ("Impartiality and Ethical Theory," Ethics 101 [1991]: 698-700, p. 700, emphasis added). See also Stocker: "[The phenomenon of] admirable immorality . . . show[s] how immorality and defect can and must be allowed for in ethical theory" (Michael Stocker, Plural and Conflicting Values [Oxford: Clarendon, 1990], p. 50).
    • (1991) Ethics , vol.101 , pp. 698-700
    • Becker, L.1
  • 129
    • 0003945976 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon
    • Compare Lawrence Becker's observation that defenders of morality's commitment to impartiality try to show that the "purported inadequacies [of impartiality] . . . are not really attributable to a proper theoretical commitment to impartiality" ("Impartiality and Ethical Theory," Ethics 101 [1991]: 698-700, p. 700, emphasis added). See also Stocker: "[The phenomenon of] admirable immorality . . . show[s] how immorality and defect can and must be allowed for in ethical theory" (Michael Stocker, Plural and Conflicting Values [Oxford: Clarendon, 1990], p. 50).
    • (1990) Plural and Conflicting Values , pp. 50
    • Stocker, M.1
  • 130
    • 85033119557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, one might pick out various points where the Morality Critics seem to echo Nietzsche. Compare Wolf: "A moral saint will have to be very, very nice. It is important that he not be offensive. The worry is that, as a result, he will have to be dull-witted or humorless or bland" (p. 422); cf. BGE, 260: "the good human being [according to slave morality] has to be undangerous . . . : he is good-natured, easy to deceive, a little stupid perhaps, un bonhomme. Wherever slave morality becomes preponderant, language tends to bring the words 'good' and 'stupid' closer together."
    • Wolf1
  • 131
    • 85033109945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The reader may wonder in what sense Nietzsche's claims are empirical, since they are hardly the upshot of systematic investigation into, say, the psychology and etiology of genius. They are empirical, however, in the sense that Nietzsche seems to have reached these conclusions from certain sorts of observation: first, and most important, of himself and his own development (note that the theme only appears in his work in the very late 1870s, when he is about thirty-five and has already been ill for several years); second, of various historical figures and cultures with which he was acquainted through his studies and reading. As I note at the end, though, the case for his critique really requires a more sustained empirical examination.
  • 132
    • 85033121182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Construction of private fantasy moral worlds
    • Compare Annette Baier's complaints about the irrelevance of moral theory, of its "construction of private fantasy moral worlds" ("Doing without Moral Theory?" p. 235; cf. p. 234).
    • Doing Without Moral Theory? , pp. 235
    • Baier, A.1
  • 133
    • 85033106978 scopus 로고
    • Our modern scholasticism
    • trans. H. Tomlinson New York: Columbia University Press
    • Gilles Deleuze aptly calls phenomenology "our modern scholasticism" in Nietische and Philosophy, trans. H. Tomlinson (New York: Columbia University Press, 1983), p. 195.
    • (1983) Nietische and Philosophy , pp. 195
    • Deleuze, G.1
  • 135
    • 85033099270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One might worry, though, that such a complaint will backfire against Nietzsche, for isn't he a "theorist" of sorts, hoping to affect cultural practice? The answer, I think, is that Nietzsche is an esoteric moralist, hoping to reach only a few select readers, those "predisposed and predestined for" his insights (BGE, 30); thus he aims not to reform culture but to enlighten a select few to the dangers of the dominant moral culture. This is why, contrary to a large amount of recent literature, Nietzsche does not have any political theory or any real politics. I hope to address these issues, however, elsewhere.
    • Political Theory or Any Real Politics
    • Nietzsche1
  • 136
    • 85033122068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nehamas, pp. 202-3; Philippa Foot, "Nietzsche's Immoralism," New York Review of Books 38 (June 13, 1991), p. 19, reprinted in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality.
    • Nehamas1
  • 137
    • 0039786332 scopus 로고
    • Nietzsche's immoralism
    • June 13
    • See Nehamas, pp. 202-3; Philippa Foot, "Nietzsche's Immoralism," New York Review of Books 38 (June 13, 1991), p. 19, reprinted in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality.
    • (1991) New York Review of Books , vol.38 , pp. 19
    • Foot, P.1
  • 138
    • 85033106608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted
    • See Nehamas, pp. 202-3; Philippa Foot, "Nietzsche's Immoralism," New York Review of Books 38 (June 13, 1991), p. 19, reprinted in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality.
    • Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality
  • 139
    • 85033102702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nietzsche's polemic against Christianity in The Antichrist is framed in the starkest Calliclean terms, with Nietzsche describing "the cross as the mark of recognition for the most subterranean conspiracy that ever existed - against health, beauty, whatever has turned out well, courage, spirit, graciousness of the soul, against life itself" (A, 62); see also WP, 400: "In the history of morality a will to power finds expression, through which now the slaves and oppressed, now the ill-constituted and those who suffer from themselves, now the mediocre attempt to make those value judgments prevail that are favorable to them."
    • The Antichrist , Issue.62 A
    • Nietzsche1
  • 140
    • 85033105759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Nietzsche also often blames "Christianity," but we must remember that for Nietzsche Christianity was simply "the most prodigal elaboration of the moral theme to which humanity has ever been subjected" (BT, pref. 5).
  • 142
    • 85033107940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To say that they take the demands of MPS "seriously" is not to say that they understand them in the way a philosophical theory would; it is only to say that they are more likely to take these unsystematic and inchoate demands constitutive of morality as weighing seriously upon them.
  • 143
    • 85033119433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See the earlier quotations from Zarathustra's description of the last man.
  • 144
    • 85033120515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In his Calliclean moods, of course, Nietzsche believes that morality really aims to undermine the Extraordinary Life, but one might reject the Callicleanism and still think there is something to the underlying causal claim.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.