메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 61, Issue 2, 2000, Pages 223-240

The "survival of the fittest" and the origins of social Darwinism

(1)  Claeys, Gregory a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0040001176     PISSN: 00225037     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3654026     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (117)

References (147)
  • 1
    • 0003418142 scopus 로고
    • 3 vols.: London
    • Francis Darwin (ed.), The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin (3 vols.: London, 1888), I, 83. The passage was picked up by contemporaries, e.g., Benjamin Kidd, Social Evolution (London, 1894), 32 .
    • (1888) The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin
    • Darwin, F.1
  • 2
    • 0012615553 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Francis Darwin (ed.), The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin (3 vols.: London, 1888), I, 83. The passage was picked up by contemporaries, e.g., Benjamin Kidd, Social Evolution (London, 1894), 32 .
    • (1894) Social Evolution , pp. 32
    • Kidd, B.1
  • 3
    • 0003809032 scopus 로고
    • London, ch. 3
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1859) Origin of Species
    • Darwin, C.1
  • 4
    • 0042334999 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1899) From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance , pp. 63
    • Mackintosh, R.1
  • 5
    • 0011572486 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1901) Darwinism and Politics , pp. 1-6
    • Ritchie, D.1
  • 6
    • 0017004967 scopus 로고
    • Malthus, Darwin, and the concept of struggle
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1976) JHI , vol.37 , pp. 631-650
    • Bowler, P.1
  • 7
    • 0041333254 scopus 로고
    • Natural selection before the 'origin of species'
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1941) Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society , vol.84 , pp. 71-123
    • Zirkle, C.1
  • 8
    • 85034519271 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1959) Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution
    • Himmelfarb, G.1
  • 9
    • 0004181897 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1966) Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory
    • Burrow, J.1
  • 10
    • 0042835889 scopus 로고
    • Darwin, Malthus, and the theory of natural selection
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1969) JHI , vol.30 , pp. 527-542
    • Vorzimmer, P.1
  • 11
    • 0005878897 scopus 로고
    • Malthus and the evolutionists: The common context of biological and social theory
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1969) Past and Present , vol.43
    • Young, R.1
  • 12
    • 0015029748 scopus 로고
    • Darwin, Malthus and selection
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1971) Journal of the History of Biology , vol.4 , pp. 209-217
    • Herbert, S.1
  • 13
    • 0016133189 scopus 로고
    • The evolutionary theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1974) Current Anthropology , vol.15 , pp. 211-221
    • Freeman, D.1
  • 14
    • 0017530263 scopus 로고
    • The origin of the origin revisited
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1977) Journal of the History of Biology , vol.10 , pp. 229-316
    • Schweber, S.1
  • 15
    • 1542282498 scopus 로고
    • Darwin and social Darwinism: Purity and history
    • Shapin and Barnes, Los Angeles
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1977) Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture , pp. 125-142
    • Shapin, S.1    Barnes, B.2
  • 16
    • 0011669943 scopus 로고
    • Social darwinism: Two sources
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1980) Albion , vol.12 , pp. 23-36
    • Ruse, M.1
  • 17
    • 0042835887 scopus 로고
    • The origins of Darwin's ideas on evolution and natural selection
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1962) Proceedings of the Royal Society of London , vol.155 , Issue.B , pp. 321-338
    • De Beer, G.1
  • 18
    • 0004327513 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1961) Darwin's Century , pp. 181-182
    • Eiseley, L.1
  • 19
    • 0042835889 scopus 로고
    • Darwin, Malthus, and the theory of natural selection
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1969) JHI , vol.30 , pp. 527-542
    • Vorzimmer, P.1
  • 20
    • 0003967363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boston
    • Charles Darwin, Origin of Species (London, 1859), ch. 3; the phrase "survival of the fittest" Darwin only introduced in the fifth, 1872 edition of the Origin and meant by it only that those who produced the most offspring were likely to pass their characteristics onwards. See Robert Mackintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd: The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), 63; David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), 1-6. The most concise treatment of the subject is Peter Bowler. "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50; Conway Zirkle, "Natural Selection before the 'Origin of Species,'" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 84 (1941), 71-123; Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution (London, 1959), John Burrow, Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory (Cambridge, 1966): Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42: Robert Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: the Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 43 (1969): Sandra Herbert, "Darwin, Malthus and Selection," Journal of the History of Biology, 4 (1971), 209-17; Derek Freeman, "The Evolutionary Theories of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer," Current Anthropology, 15 (1974), 211-21; Silvan Schweber, "The Origin of the Origin Revisited," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 229-316; Steven Shapin and Barry Barnes, "Darwin and Social Darwinism: Purity and History," in Shapin and Barnes, Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture (Los Angeles, 1977), 125-42; Michael Ruse, "Social Darwinism: Two Sources," Albion, 12 (1980), 23-36 ; also Gavin de Beer, "The Origins of Darwin's Ideas on Evolution and Natural Selection," Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, 155, B (1962), 321-38: Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century (New York, 1961), 181-82; Peter Vorzimmer, "Darwin, Malthus, and the Theory of Natural Selection," JHI, 30 (1969), 527-42; and Richard Hofstadter. Social Darwinism in American Thought (Boston, 1955).
    • (1955) Social Darwinism in American Thought
    • Hofstadter, R.1
  • 23
    • 0004112069 scopus 로고
    • London
    • "Then it suddenly flashed upon me that this self-acting process would necessarily improve the race, because in every generation the inferior would inevitably be killed off and the superior would remain - that is, the fittest would survive." Alfred Russel Wallace, My Life: A Record of Events and Opinions (London, 1908), 190.
    • (1908) My Life: A Record of Events and Opinions , pp. 190
    • Wallace, A.R.1
  • 24
    • 84892756514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wallace, My Life, 232-35, had in fact read Malthus some twenty years earlier, in 1844-5, but only recognised the implications for evolutionary theory later.
    • My Life , pp. 232-235
    • Wallace1
  • 25
    • 0003717996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The standard account of evolutionary theories in this period remains J. W. Burrow, Evolution and Society, which, however, excludes Social Darwinism.
    • Evolution and Society
    • Burrow, J.W.1
  • 26
    • 0039963396 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • The Darwin industry has of course made much of this association, which is also widely recognised by other historians, e.g., Donald Winch, Malthus (Oxford, 1987), 7; D. P. Crook, Darwinism, War and History (Cambridge, 1994), 17-21. On Darwin's "metaphor," see David N. Livingstone, Darwin's Forgotten Defenders (Edinburgh, 1987), ch. 2. Some contemporaries also regarded Social Darwinism and Malthusianism as essentially identical. See H. M. Hyndman (The Historical Basis of Socialism in England [London, 1883], 38.): "The attempt made to apply Darwin's theories on the struggle for life among animals to man is quite beside the point. Man is the only animal who deliberately modifies nature on a large scale, and increases the amount of his own food. To my mind, the Malthusian theory in the present condition of population on the planet, and of human civilization among the progressive races, is utterly misleading and foolish."
    • (1987) Malthus , pp. 7
    • Winch, D.1
  • 27
    • 0004066639 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • The Darwin industry has of course made much of this association, which is also widely recognised by other historians, e.g., Donald Winch, Malthus (Oxford, 1987), 7; D. P. Crook, Darwinism, War and History (Cambridge, 1994), 17-21. On Darwin's "metaphor," see David N. Livingstone, Darwin's Forgotten Defenders (Edinburgh, 1987), ch. 2. Some contemporaries also regarded Social Darwinism and Malthusianism as essentially identical. See H. M. Hyndman (The Historical Basis of Socialism in England [London, 1883], 38.): "The attempt made to apply Darwin's theories on the struggle for life among animals to man is quite beside the point. Man is the only animal who deliberately modifies nature on a large scale, and increases the amount of his own food. To my mind, the Malthusian theory in the present condition of population on the planet, and of human civilization among the progressive races, is utterly misleading and foolish."
    • (1994) Darwinism, War and History , pp. 17-21
    • Crook, D.P.1
  • 28
    • 0007183869 scopus 로고
    • Edinburgh, ch. 2
    • The Darwin industry has of course made much of this association, which is also widely recognised by other historians, e.g., Donald Winch, Malthus (Oxford, 1987), 7; D. P. Crook, Darwinism, War and History (Cambridge, 1994), 17-21. On Darwin's "metaphor," see David N. Livingstone, Darwin's Forgotten Defenders (Edinburgh, 1987), ch. 2. Some contemporaries also regarded Social Darwinism and Malthusianism as essentially identical. See H. M. Hyndman (The Historical Basis of Socialism in England [London, 1883], 38.): "The attempt made to apply Darwin's theories on the struggle for life among animals to man is quite beside the point. Man is the only animal who deliberately modifies nature on a large scale, and increases the amount of his own food. To my mind, the Malthusian theory in the present condition of population on the planet, and of human civilization among the progressive races, is utterly misleading and foolish."
    • (1987) Darwin's Forgotten Defenders
    • Livingstone, D.N.1
  • 29
    • 0042334996 scopus 로고
    • London
    • The Darwin industry has of course made much of this association, which is also widely recognised by other historians, e.g., Donald Winch, Malthus (Oxford, 1987), 7; D. P. Crook, Darwinism, War and History (Cambridge, 1994), 17-21. On Darwin's "metaphor," see David N. Livingstone, Darwin's Forgotten Defenders (Edinburgh, 1987), ch. 2. Some contemporaries also regarded Social Darwinism and Malthusianism as essentially identical. See H. M. Hyndman (The Historical Basis of Socialism in England [London, 1883], 38.): "The attempt made to apply Darwin's theories on the struggle for life among animals to man is quite beside the point. Man is the only animal who deliberately modifies nature on a large scale, and increases the amount of his own food. To my mind, the Malthusian theory in the present condition of population on the planet, and of human civilization among the progressive races, is utterly misleading and foolish."
    • (1883) The Historical Basis of Socialism in England , pp. 38
    • Hyndman, H.M.1
  • 30
    • 0001478648 scopus 로고
    • Social Darwinism: A definition
    • See R. J. Halliday, "Social Darwinism: A Definition," Victorian Studies, 14 (1971), 389-405.
    • (1971) Victorian Studies , vol.14 , pp. 389-405
    • Halliday, R.J.1
  • 31
  • 32
    • 0004343491 scopus 로고
    • London
    • See Maine's praise for "the beneficent private war which makes one man strive to climb on the shoulders of another and remain there through the law of the survival of the fittest." Popular Government (London, 1885), 50.
    • (1885) Popular Government , pp. 50
  • 33
    • 0041833841 scopus 로고
    • London
    • J. Holland Rose (The Rise of Democracy [London, 1898], 166), contended that the influence of Darwin's theories had been "both to extend and complicate the issues which were prominent in the previous generation. Then controversy raged mostly on the question of natural rights, especially those of the individual to a share in the government. Now the contest is between those who would strengthen and those who would minimize the authority of the state in its dealings with the individual, especially in regard to private ownership, the claims of companies, and economic or social questions arising therefrom." Yet Dicey gave him relatively little credit for assisting this trend in Lectures on the Relation between Law and Public Opinion in the Nineteenth Century. A similar stress on the collectivist implications of the theory of natural selection is given by Benjamin Kidd (Principles of Western Civilisation [London, 1902], 51), who however emphasizes the post-Darwinian contribution. Greta Jones, Social Darwinism and English Thought (Brighton, 1980), 54-77.
    • (1898) The Rise of Democracy , pp. 166
    • Holland Rose, J.1
  • 34
    • 0013050866 scopus 로고
    • London
    • J. Holland Rose (The Rise of Democracy [London, 1898], 166), contended that the influence of Darwin's theories had been "both to extend and complicate the issues which were prominent in the previous generation. Then controversy raged mostly on the question of natural rights, especially those of the individual to a share in the government. Now the contest is between those who would strengthen and those who would minimize the authority of the state in its dealings with the individual, especially in regard to private ownership, the claims of companies, and economic or social questions arising therefrom." Yet Dicey gave him relatively little credit for assisting this trend in Lectures on the Relation between Law and Public Opinion in the Nineteenth Century. A similar stress on the collectivist implications of the theory of natural selection is given by Benjamin Kidd (Principles of Western Civilisation [London, 1902], 51), who however emphasizes the post-Darwinian contribution. Greta Jones, Social Darwinism and English Thought (Brighton, 1980), 54-77.
    • (1902) Principles of Western Civilisation , pp. 51
    • Kidd, B.1
  • 35
    • 0003720461 scopus 로고
    • Brighton
    • J. Holland Rose (The Rise of Democracy [London, 1898], 166), contended that the influence of Darwin's theories had been "both to extend and complicate the issues which were prominent in the previous generation. Then controversy raged mostly on the question of natural rights, especially those of the individual to a share in the government. Now the contest is between those who would strengthen and those who would minimize the authority of the state in its dealings with the individual, especially in regard to private ownership, the claims of companies, and economic or social questions arising therefrom." Yet Dicey gave him relatively little credit for assisting this trend in Lectures on the Relation between Law and Public Opinion in the Nineteenth Century. A similar stress on the collectivist implications of the theory of natural selection is given by Benjamin Kidd (Principles of Western Civilisation [London, 1902], 51), who however emphasizes the post-Darwinian contribution. Greta Jones, Social Darwinism and English Thought (Brighton, 1980), 54-77.
    • (1980) Social Darwinism and English Thought , pp. 54-77
    • Jones, G.1
  • 36
    • 0041333253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Benjamin Kidd (The Science of Power, 57, 59), "Nietzsche's teachings represented the interpretation of the popular Darwinism delivered with the fury and intensity of genius."
    • The Science of Power , pp. 57
    • Kidd, B.1
  • 37
    • 0042334995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 39. A typical stress on efficiency of this kind is given in W. H. Mallock, Aristocracy and Evolution (London, 1898), 92.
    • The Science of Power , pp. 39
  • 38
    • 34548277764 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Ibid., 39. A typical stress on efficiency of this kind is given in W. H. Mallock, Aristocracy and Evolution (London, 1898), 92.
    • (1898) Aristocracy and Evolution , pp. 92
    • Mallock, W.H.1
  • 39
    • 0039458380 scopus 로고
    • London
    • According to Leonard Hobhouse (Democracy and Reaction [London, 1904], 85), "those who have applied Darwin's theories to the science of society have not as a rule troubled themselves to understand Darwin any more than the science of society. What has filtered through into the social and political thought of the time has been the belief that the time-honoured doctrine 'Might is Right' has a scientific foundation in the laws of biology." Hobhouse thought Bagehot, who concentrates on "national character" in Physics and Politics, had first applied Darwinian notions to ideas of international rather than intra-national or species-centered struggle.
    • (1904) Democracy and Reaction , pp. 85
    • Hobhouse, L.1
  • 42
    • 0041333253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Benjamin Kidd, The Science of Power, 45: "Within half a century the Origin of Species had become the bible of the doctrine of the omnipotence of force."
    • The Science of Power , pp. 45
    • Kidd, B.1
  • 43
    • 0005878897 scopus 로고
    • Malthus and the evolutionists: The common context of biological and social theory
    • For previous examples of this line of enquiry, see in particular R. M. Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: The Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 93 (1969), 109-41; Kenneth Bock, "Darwin and Social Theory," Philosophy of Science, 22 (1955), 123-34; Thomas Cowles, "Malthus, Darwin, and Bagehot: A Study in the Transference of a Concept," Isis, 26 (1936), 341-48; and Barry Gale, "Darwin and the Concept of a Struggle for Existence: A Study in the Extrascientific Origins of Scientific Ideas," Isis, 63 (1972), 321-44.
    • (1969) Past and Present , vol.93 , pp. 109-141
    • Young, R.M.1
  • 44
    • 0005878897 scopus 로고
    • Darwin and social theory
    • For previous examples of this line of enquiry, see in particular R. M. Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: The Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 93 (1969), 109-41; Kenneth Bock, "Darwin and Social Theory," Philosophy of Science, 22 (1955), 123-34; Thomas Cowles, "Malthus, Darwin, and Bagehot: A Study in the Transference of a Concept," Isis, 26 (1936), 341-48; and Barry Gale, "Darwin and the Concept of a Struggle for Existence: A Study in the Extrascientific Origins of Scientific Ideas," Isis, 63 (1972), 321-44.
    • (1955) Philosophy of Science , vol.22 , pp. 123-134
    • Bock, K.1
  • 45
    • 0005878897 scopus 로고
    • Malthus, Darwin, and Bagehot: A study in the transference of a concept
    • For previous examples of this line of enquiry, see in particular R. M. Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: The Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 93 (1969), 109-41; Kenneth Bock, "Darwin and Social Theory," Philosophy of Science, 22 (1955), 123-34; Thomas Cowles, "Malthus, Darwin, and Bagehot: A Study in the Transference of a Concept," Isis, 26 (1936), 341-48; and Barry Gale, "Darwin and the Concept of a Struggle for Existence: A Study in the Extrascientific Origins of Scientific Ideas," Isis, 63 (1972), 321-44.
    • (1936) Isis , vol.26 , pp. 341-348
    • Cowles, T.1
  • 46
    • 0005878897 scopus 로고
    • Darwin and the concept of a struggle for existence: A study in the extrascientific origins of scientific ideas
    • For previous examples of this line of enquiry, see in particular R. M. Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists: The Common Context of Biological and Social Theory," Past and Present, 93 (1969), 109-41; Kenneth Bock, "Darwin and Social Theory," Philosophy of Science, 22 (1955), 123-34; Thomas Cowles, "Malthus, Darwin, and Bagehot: A Study in the Transference of a Concept," Isis, 26 (1936), 341-48; and Barry Gale, "Darwin and the Concept of a Struggle for Existence: A Study in the Extrascientific Origins of Scientific Ideas," Isis, 63 (1972), 321-44.
    • (1972) Isis , vol.63 , pp. 321-344
    • Gale, B.1
  • 47
    • 0003418142 scopus 로고
    • Darwin ( The Life and Letters of Charles Danwin [1888], III, 45-46), took up the term in 1866, writing to Wallace that "I fully agree with all that you say on the advantages of H. Spencer's excellent expression of 'the survival of the fittest.' This, however, had not occurred to me till reading your letter. It is, however, a great objection to this term that it cannot be used as a substantive governing a verb: and that this is a real objection I infer from H. Spencer continually using the words, natural selection. I formerly thought, probably in an exaggerated degree, that it was a great advantage to bring into connection natural and artificial selection; this indeed led me to use a term in common, and I still think it some advantage. I wish I had received your letter two months ago, for I would have worked in 'the survival, ©.,' often in the new edition of the 'Origin,' which is now almost printed off, and of which I will of course send you a copy. I will use the term in my next book on Domestic Animals, ©."
    • (1888) The Life and Letters of Charles Danwin
    • Darwin1
  • 49
  • 50
    • 0042638086 scopus 로고
    • A theory of population deduced from the general law of animal fertility
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography (London, 1904), I, 462; see generally "Progress: Its Law and Cause," Westminster Review, 67 (1857), 445-85. He would also acknowledge, however, that Darwin had forced him to modify his own views of evolution substantially. Ibid., II, 50. C. U. M. Smith, "Evolution and the Problem of Mind: Herbert Spencer," Journal of the History of Biology, 15 (1982), 55-88; D. R. Olroyd, Darwinian Impacts (New Brunswick, 1980), ch. 15; David Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer (Oxford, 1978), 192-224 ; and J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London, 1971), 131-65, which argues that "what was called 'Social Darwinism" was often derived largely from Spencer." Spencer's theory laid more stress on individual efforts than did Darwin's, and was more indebted to Lamarckian conceptions that habits could modify constitutions and in these in turn could be passed to future generations. The Malthusian source of Spencer's evolutionism is evident in his "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review (1852), which argued that an "inevitable redundancy of numbers . . . involves also a demand for skill, intelligence, and self-control" which resulted in social improvement (266).
    • (1852) Westminster Review , vol.1 , pp. 501
    • Spencer1
  • 51
    • 0004164487 scopus 로고
    • 2 vols.; London
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography (London, 1904), I, 462; see generally "Progress: Its Law and Cause," Westminster Review, 67 (1857), 445-85. He would also acknowledge, however, that Darwin had forced him to modify his own views of evolution substantially. Ibid., II, 50. C. U. M. Smith, "Evolution and the Problem of Mind: Herbert Spencer," Journal of the History of Biology, 15 (1982), 55-88; D. R. Olroyd, Darwinian Impacts (New Brunswick, 1980), ch. 15; David Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer (Oxford, 1978), 192-224 ; and J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London, 1971), 131-65, which argues that "what was called 'Social Darwinism" was often derived largely from Spencer." Spencer's theory laid more stress on individual efforts than did Darwin's, and was more indebted to Lamarckian conceptions that habits could modify constitutions and in these in turn could be passed to future generations. The Malthusian source of Spencer's evolutionism is evident in his "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review (1852), which argued that an "inevitable redundancy of numbers . . . involves also a demand for skill, intelligence, and self-control" which resulted in social improvement (266).
    • (1911) First Principles
    • Spencer, H.1
  • 52
    • 2442426019 scopus 로고
    • London
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography (London, 1904), I, 462; see generally "Progress: Its Law and Cause," Westminster Review, 67 (1857), 445-85. He would also acknowledge, however, that Darwin had forced him to modify his own views of evolution substantially. Ibid., II, 50. C. U. M. Smith, "Evolution and the Problem of Mind: Herbert Spencer," Journal of the History of Biology, 15 (1982), 55-88; D. R. Olroyd, Darwinian Impacts (New Brunswick, 1980), ch. 15; David Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer (Oxford, 1978), 192-224 ; and J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London, 1971), 131-65, which argues that "what was called 'Social Darwinism" was often derived largely from Spencer." Spencer's theory laid more stress on individual efforts than did Darwin's, and was more indebted to Lamarckian conceptions that habits could modify constitutions and in these in turn could be passed to future generations. The Malthusian source of Spencer's evolutionism is evident in his "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review (1852), which argued that an "inevitable redundancy of numbers . . . involves also a demand for skill, intelligence, and self-control" which resulted in social improvement (266).
    • (1904) Autobiography
  • 53
    • 0008061292 scopus 로고
    • Progress: Its law and cause
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography
    • (1857) Westminster Review , vol.67 , pp. 445-485
  • 54
    • 84906592625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography (London, 1904), I, 462; see generally "Progress: Its Law and Cause," Westminster Review, 67 (1857), 445-85. He would also acknowledge, however, that Darwin had forced him to modify his own views of evolution substantially. Ibid., II, 50. C. U. M. Smith, "Evolution and the Problem of Mind: Herbert Spencer," Journal of the History of Biology, 15 (1982), 55-88; D. R. Olroyd, Darwinian Impacts (New Brunswick, 1980), ch. 15; David Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer (Oxford, 1978), 192-224 ; and J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London, 1971), 131-65, which argues that "what was called 'Social Darwinism" was often derived largely from Spencer." Spencer's theory laid more stress on individual efforts than did Darwin's, and was more indebted to Lamarckian conceptions that habits could modify constitutions and in these in turn could be passed to future generations. The Malthusian source of Spencer's evolutionism is evident in his "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review (1852), which argued that an "inevitable redundancy of numbers . . . involves also a demand for skill, intelligence, and self-control" which resulted in social improvement (266).
    • Westminster Review
  • 55
    • 0020110392 scopus 로고
    • Evolution and the problem of mind: Herbert Spencer
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography (London, 1904), I, 462; see generally "Progress: Its Law and Cause," Westminster Review, 67 (1857), 445-85. He would also acknowledge, however, that Darwin had forced him to modify his own views of evolution substantially. Ibid., II, 50. C. U. M. Smith, "Evolution and the Problem of Mind: Herbert Spencer," Journal of the History of Biology, 15 (1982), 55-88; D. R. Olroyd, Darwinian Impacts (New Brunswick, 1980), ch. 15; David Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer (Oxford, 1978), 192-224 ; and J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London, 1971), 131-65, which argues that "what was called 'Social Darwinism" was often derived largely from Spencer." Spencer's theory laid more stress on individual efforts than did Darwin's, and was more indebted to Lamarckian conceptions that habits could modify constitutions and in these in turn could be passed to future generations. The Malthusian source of Spencer's evolutionism is evident in his "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review (1852), which argued that an "inevitable redundancy of numbers . . . involves also a demand for skill, intelligence, and self-control" which resulted in social improvement (266).
    • (1982) Journal of the History of Biology , vol.15 , pp. 55-88
    • Smith, C.U.M.1
  • 56
    • 0041833835 scopus 로고
    • New Brunswick, ch. 15
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography (London, 1904), I, 462; see generally "Progress: Its Law and Cause," Westminster Review, 67 (1857), 445-85. He would also acknowledge, however, that Darwin had forced him to modify his own views of evolution substantially. Ibid., II, 50. C. U. M. Smith, "Evolution and the Problem of Mind: Herbert Spencer," Journal of the History of Biology, 15 (1982), 55-88; D. R. Olroyd, Darwinian Impacts (New Brunswick, 1980), ch. 15; David Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer (Oxford, 1978), 192-224 ; and J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London, 1971), 131-65, which argues that "what was called 'Social Darwinism" was often derived largely from Spencer." Spencer's theory laid more stress on individual efforts than did Darwin's, and was more indebted to Lamarckian conceptions that habits could modify constitutions and in these in turn could be passed to future generations. The Malthusian source of Spencer's evolutionism is evident in his "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review (1852), which argued that an "inevitable redundancy of numbers . . . involves also a demand for skill, intelligence, and self-control" which resulted in social improvement (266).
    • (1980) Darwinian Impacts
    • Olroyd, D.R.1
  • 57
    • 0009363323 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography (London, 1904), I, 462; see generally "Progress: Its Law and Cause," Westminster Review, 67 (1857), 445-85. He would also acknowledge, however, that Darwin had forced him to modify his own views of evolution substantially. Ibid., II, 50. C. U. M. Smith, "Evolution and the Problem of Mind: Herbert Spencer," Journal of the History of Biology, 15 (1982), 55-88; D. R. Olroyd, Darwinian Impacts (New Brunswick, 1980), ch. 15; David Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer (Oxford, 1978), 192-224 ; and J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London, 1971), 131-65, which argues that "what was called 'Social Darwinism" was often derived largely from Spencer." Spencer's theory laid more stress on individual efforts than did Darwin's, and was more indebted to Lamarckian conceptions that habits could modify constitutions and in these in turn could be passed to future generations. The Malthusian source of Spencer's evolutionism is evident in his "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review (1852), which argued that an "inevitable redundancy of numbers . . . involves also a demand for skill, intelligence, and self-control" which resulted in social improvement (266).
    • (1978) The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer , pp. 192-224
    • Wiltshire, D.1
  • 58
    • 85048940982 scopus 로고
    • London
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography (London, 1904), I, 462; see generally "Progress: Its Law and Cause," Westminster Review, 67 (1857), 445-85. He would also acknowledge, however, that Darwin had forced him to modify his own views of evolution substantially. Ibid., II, 50. C. U. M. Smith, "Evolution and the Problem of Mind: Herbert Spencer," Journal of the History of Biology, 15 (1982), 55-88; D. R. Olroyd, Darwinian Impacts (New Brunswick, 1980), ch. 15; David Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer (Oxford, 1978), 192-224 ; and J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London, 1971), 131-65, which argues that "what was called 'Social Darwinism" was often derived largely from Spencer." Spencer's theory laid more stress on individual efforts than did Darwin's, and was more indebted to Lamarckian conceptions that habits could modify constitutions and in these in turn could be passed to future generations. The Malthusian source of Spencer's evolutionism is evident in his "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review (1852), which argued that an "inevitable redundancy of numbers . . . involves also a demand for skill, intelligence, and self-control" which resulted in social improvement (266).
    • (1971) Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist , pp. 131-165
    • Peel, J.D.Y.1
  • 59
    • 0042638086 scopus 로고
    • A theory of population, deduced from the general law of animal fertility
    • "From the beginning," Spencer wrote, "pressure of population has been the proximate cause of progress." "A Theory of Population Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns 1 (1852), 501. This "progress" derived from improvements of individual character or "type" (by a Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics) defined not by a teleologically-induced divine principle, but by movement from "an incoherent homogeneity to a coherent heterogeneity," or from simplicity to complexity. Herbert Spencer, First Principles (2 vols.; London, 1911), I, 291. Spencer would claim that his own "general doctrine of evolution" from homogeneity to heterogeneity, using Adam Smith's theory of increasing returns and the division of labour as a paradigm for differentiation in general, was fully formed by 1855. Autobiography (London, 1904), I, 462; see generally "Progress: Its Law and Cause," Westminster Review, 67 (1857), 445-85. He would also acknowledge, however, that Darwin had forced him to modify his own views of evolution substantially. Ibid., II, 50. C. U. M. Smith, "Evolution and the Problem of Mind: Herbert Spencer," Journal of the History of Biology, 15 (1982), 55-88; D. R. Olroyd, Darwinian Impacts (New Brunswick, 1980), ch. 15; David Wiltshire, The Social and Political Thought of Herbert Spencer (Oxford, 1978), 192-224 ; and J. D. Y. Peel, Herbert Spencer: The Evolution of a Sociologist (London, 1971), 131-65, which argues that "what was called 'Social Darwinism" was often derived largely from Spencer." Spencer's theory laid more stress on individual efforts than did Darwin's, and was more indebted to Lamarckian conceptions that habits could modify constitutions and in these in turn could be passed to future generations. The Malthusian source of Spencer's evolutionism is evident in his "A Theory of Population, Deduced from the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review (1852), which argued that an "inevitable redundancy of numbers . . . involves also a demand for skill, intelligence, and self-control" which resulted in social improvement (266).
    • (1852) Westminster Review
    • Spencer1
  • 60
    • 77952998183 scopus 로고
    • The development of Herbert Spencer's concept of evolution
    • Warsaw
    • On the influence of Malthus on Spencer, see R. M. Young, "The Development of Herbert Spencer's Concept of Evolution," Actes du XIe congrès internationale d'histoire des sciences (Warsaw, 1967), II, 273-79.
    • (1967) Actes du XIe Congrès Internationale d'Histoire des Sciences
    • Young, R.M.1
  • 61
    • 0012188689 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Their popularity was much indebted to the emergence of the social sciences in the late nineteenth century; to the growing distinction between individualist and collectivist political theories; of the popularity of jingoistic imperialism in the last third of the nineteenth century; and of increasing international tension and economic competition in the decades before 1914. which often produced the view that England had "now entered a new stage in the struggle for national life" (Arnold White, Efficiency and Empire [London, 1902], 112).
    • (1902) Efficiency and Empire , pp. 112
    • White, A.1
  • 62
    • 0041333243 scopus 로고
    • Non-survival of the fittest
    • London
    • See W. R. Greg. "Non-survival of the Fittest," in Enigmas of Life (London, 1872). Wallace summarizes his own views in "Evolution and Character," in Percy Parker (ed.), Character and Life (London, 1912), 3-50.
    • (1872) Enigmas of Life
    • Greg, W.R.1
  • 63
    • 0041833833 scopus 로고
    • Evolution and character
    • Percy Parker (ed.), London
    • See W. R. Greg. "Non-survival of the Fittest," in Enigmas of Life (London, 1872). Wallace summarizes his own views in "Evolution and Character," in Percy Parker (ed.), Character and Life (London, 1912), 3-50.
    • (1912) Character and Life , pp. 3-50
    • Wallace1
  • 64
    • 0011572486 scopus 로고
    • London
    • David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), vi; The Principles of State Interference (London, 1891), 50.
    • (1901) Darwinism and Politics
    • Ritchie, D.1
  • 65
    • 0004122913 scopus 로고
    • London
    • David Ritchie, Darwinism and Politics (London, 1901), vi; The Principles of State Interference (London, 1891), 50.
    • (1891) The Principles of State Interference , pp. 50
  • 66
    • 0040587865 scopus 로고
    • Socialism and natural selection
    • NS
    • A summary of the socialist case is given in Karl Pearson, "Socialism and Natural Selection," The Fortnightly Review, NS 62 (1894), 1-21.
    • (1894) The Fortnightly Review , vol.62 , pp. 1-21
    • Pearson, K.1
  • 67
    • 84905540894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Without of course making the claim that Malthus is a proto-Social Darwinist as such. See Donald Winch, Malthus, 102-3; James Bonar, Malthus and His Work (London, 1924); Donald Winch, Riches and Poverty; An Intellectual History of Political Economy in Britain, 1750-1834 (Cambridge, 1996), pt. 3.
    • Malthus , pp. 102-103
    • Winch, D.1
  • 68
    • 0039370983 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Without of course making the claim that Malthus is a proto-Social Darwinist as such. See Donald Winch, Malthus, 102-3; James Bonar, Malthus and His Work (London, 1924); Donald Winch, Riches and Poverty; An Intellectual History of Political Economy in Britain, 1750-1834 (Cambridge, 1996), pt. 3.
    • (1924) Malthus and His Work
    • Bonar, J.1
  • 72
    • 0003543467 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Quoted in Patricia James, Population Malthus: His Life and Times (London, 1979), 100. Malthus further reiterated that "no essential improvement can take place without the denial of a legal claim." Quoted in Southey, Essays Moral and Political (London, 1832), I, 210. This passage came to represent Malthus's most extreme formulations, and was often thereafter quoted against him, either directly (e.g., in Godwin's Of Population, 19, or Southey, 92), or indirectly, as in George Ensor's assertion that in the Essay "The banquet of nature shrinks into short allowance ministered by a miser," in An Inquiry concerning the Population of Nations (London, 1818), 80.
    • (1979) Population Malthus: His Life and Times , pp. 100
    • James, P.1
  • 73
    • 0042334991 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Quoted in Patricia James, Population Malthus: His Life and Times (London, 1979), 100. Malthus further reiterated that "no essential improvement can take place without the denial of a legal claim." Quoted in Southey, Essays Moral and Political (London, 1832), I, 210. This passage came to represent Malthus's most extreme formulations, and was often thereafter quoted against him, either directly (e.g., in Godwin's Of Population, 19, or Southey, 92), or indirectly, as in George Ensor's assertion that in the Essay "The banquet of nature shrinks into short allowance ministered by a miser," in An Inquiry concerning the Population of Nations (London, 1818), 80.
    • (1832) Essays Moral and Political
    • Southey1
  • 74
    • 0041833834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • or Southey, 92
    • Quoted in Patricia James, Population Malthus: His Life and Times (London, 1979), 100. Malthus further reiterated that "no essential improvement can take place without the denial of a legal claim." Quoted in Southey, Essays Moral and Political (London, 1832), I, 210. This passage came to represent Malthus's most extreme formulations, and was often thereafter quoted against him, either directly (e.g., in Godwin's Of Population, 19, or Southey, 92), or indirectly, as in George Ensor's assertion that in the Essay "The banquet of nature shrinks into short allowance ministered by a miser," in An Inquiry concerning the Population of Nations (London, 1818), 80.
    • Of Population , pp. 19
    • Godwin1
  • 75
    • 0041833830 scopus 로고
    • The banquet of nature shrinks into short allowance ministered by a miser
    • London
    • Quoted in Patricia James, Population Malthus: His Life and Times (London, 1979), 100. Malthus further reiterated that "no essential improvement can take place without the denial of a legal claim." Quoted in Southey, Essays Moral and Political (London, 1832), I, 210. This passage came to represent Malthus's most extreme formulations, and was often thereafter quoted against him, either directly (e.g., in Godwin's Of Population, 19, or Southey, 92), or indirectly, as in George Ensor's assertion that in the Essay "The banquet of nature shrinks into short allowance ministered by a miser," in An Inquiry concerning the Population of Nations (London, 1818), 80.
    • (1818) An Inquiry Concerning the Population of Nations , pp. 80
    • Ensor, G.1
  • 76
    • 0018499341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London
    • Essay on Population (London, 1798), 363. Malthus's theodicy was that "Evil exists in the world not to create despair but activity." Ibid., 217. See generally D. L. LeMahieu, "Malthus and the Theology of Scarcity," JHI, 40 (1979), 467-74; J. M. Pullen, "Malthus" Theological Ideas and their Influence on his Principle of Population," History of Political Economy, 13 (1981), 38-54; Edmund Santuri, "Theodicy and Social Policy in Malthus' Thought," JHI, 43 (1982), 315-50; M. B. Harvey-Phillips, "Malthus' Theodicy; the Intellectual Background of His Contribution to Political Economy," History of Political Economy, 16 (1984), 591-608. The development of Christian economics in this period is analyzed in Boyd Hilton, The Age of Atonement: The Influence of Evangelicism on Social and Economic Thought, 1785-1865 (Oxford, 1988).
    • (1798) Essay on Population , pp. 363
  • 77
    • 0018499341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essay on Population (London, 1798), 363. Malthus's theodicy was that "Evil exists in the world not to create despair but activity." Ibid., 217. See generally D. L. LeMahieu, "Malthus and the Theology of Scarcity," JHI, 40 (1979), 467-74; J. M. Pullen, "Malthus' Theological Ideas and their Influence on his Principle of Population," History of Political Economy, 13 (1981), 38-54; Edmund Santuri, "Theodicy and Social Policy in Malthus' Thought," JHI, 43 (1982), 315-50; M. B. Harvey-Phillips, "Malthus' Theodicy; the Intellectual Background of His Contribution to Political Economy," History of Political Economy, 16 (1984), 591-608. The development of Christian economics in this period is analyzed in Boyd Hilton, The Age of Atonement: The Influence of Evangelicism on Social and Economic Thought, 1785-1865 (Oxford, 1988).
    • Essay on Population , pp. 217
  • 78
    • 0018499341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Malthus and the theology of scarcity
    • Essay on Population (London, 1798), 363. Malthus's theodicy was that "Evil exists in the world not to create despair but activity." Ibid., 217. See generally D. L. LeMahieu, "Malthus and the Theology of Scarcity," JHI, 40 (1979), 467-74; J. M. Pullen, "Malthus' Theological Ideas and their Influence on his Principle of Population," History of Political Economy, 13 (1981), 38-54; Edmund Santuri, "Theodicy and Social Policy in Malthus' Thought," JHI, 43 (1982), 315-50; M. B. Harvey-Phillips, "Malthus' Theodicy; the Intellectual Background of His Contribution to Political Economy," History of Political Economy, 16 (1984), 591-608. The development of Christian economics in this period is analyzed in Boyd Hilton, The Age of Atonement: The Influence of Evangelicism on Social and Economic Thought, 1785-1865 (Oxford, 1988).
    • (1979) JHI , vol.40 , pp. 467-474
    • LeMahieu, D.L.1
  • 79
    • 0018499341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Malthus' theological ideas and their influence on his principle of population
    • Essay on Population (London, 1798), 363. Malthus's theodicy was that "Evil exists in the world not to create despair but activity." Ibid., 217. See generally D. L. LeMahieu, "Malthus and the Theology of Scarcity," JHI, 40 (1979), 467-74; J. M. Pullen, "Malthus' Theological Ideas and their Influence on his Principle of Population," History of Political Economy, 13 (1981), 38-54; Edmund Santuri, "Theodicy and Social Policy in Malthus' Thought," JHI, 43 (1982), 315-50; M. B. Harvey-Phillips, "Malthus' Theodicy; the Intellectual Background of His Contribution to Political Economy," History of Political Economy, 16 (1984), 591-608. The development of Christian economics in this period is analyzed in Boyd Hilton, The Age of Atonement: The Influence of Evangelicism on Social and Economic Thought, 1785-1865 (Oxford, 1988).
    • (1981) History of Political Economy , vol.13 , pp. 38-54
    • Pullen, J.M.1
  • 80
    • 0020123026 scopus 로고
    • Theodicy and social policy in Malthus' thought
    • Essay on Population (London, 1798), 363. Malthus's theodicy was that "Evil exists in the world not to create despair but activity." Ibid., 217. See generally D. L. LeMahieu, "Malthus and the Theology of Scarcity," JHI, 40 (1979), 467-74; J. M. Pullen, "Malthus' Theological Ideas and their Influence on his Principle of Population," History of Political Economy, 13 (1981), 38-54; Edmund Santuri, "Theodicy and Social Policy in Malthus' Thought," JHI, 43 (1982), 315-50; M. B. Harvey-Phillips, "Malthus' Theodicy; the Intellectual Background of His Contribution to Political Economy," History of Political Economy, 16 (1984), 591-608. The development of Christian economics in this period is analyzed in Boyd Hilton, The Age of Atonement: The Influence of Evangelicism on Social and Economic Thought, 1785-1865 (Oxford, 1988).
    • (1982) JHI , vol.43 , pp. 315-350
    • Santuri, E.1
  • 81
    • 0018499341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Malthus' theodicy; the intellectual background of his contribution to political economy
    • Essay on Population (London, 1798), 363. Malthus's theodicy was that "Evil exists in the world not to create despair but activity." Ibid., 217. See generally D. L. LeMahieu, "Malthus and the Theology of Scarcity," JHI, 40 (1979), 467-74; J. M. Pullen, "Malthus' Theological Ideas and their Influence on his Principle of Population," History of Political Economy, 13 (1981), 38-54; Edmund Santuri, "Theodicy and Social Policy in Malthus' Thought," JHI, 43 (1982), 315-50; M. B. Harvey-Phillips, "Malthus' Theodicy; the Intellectual Background of His Contribution to Political Economy," History of Political Economy, 16 (1984), 591-608. The development of Christian economics in this period is analyzed in Boyd Hilton, The Age of Atonement: The Influence of Evangelicism on Social and Economic Thought, 1785-1865 (Oxford, 1988).
    • (1984) History of Political Economy , vol.16 , pp. 591-608
    • Harvey-Phillips, M.B.1
  • 82
    • 0018499341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • Essay on Population (London, 1798), 363. Malthus's theodicy was that "Evil exists in the world not to create despair but activity." Ibid., 217. See generally D. L. LeMahieu, "Malthus and the Theology of Scarcity," JHI, 40 (1979), 467-74; J. M. Pullen, "Malthus' Theological Ideas and their Influence on his Principle of Population," History of Political Economy, 13 (1981), 38-54; Edmund Santuri, "Theodicy and Social Policy in Malthus' Thought," JHI, 43 (1982), 315-50; M. B. Harvey-Phillips, "Malthus' Theodicy; the Intellectual Background of His Contribution to Political Economy," History of Political Economy, 16 (1984), 591-608. The development of Christian economics in this period is analyzed in Boyd Hilton, The Age of Atonement: The Influence of Evangelicism on Social and Economic Thought, 1785-1865 (Oxford, 1988).
    • (1988) The Age of Atonement: The Influence of Evangelicism on Social and Economic Thought, 1785-1865
    • Hilton, B.1
  • 83
    • 0041833832 scopus 로고
    • London
    • For an early critique which derides Malthus's treatment of the laboring class as "not only inhuman to the last degree, but unjust and iniquitous, see Charles Hall, Observations on the Principal Conclusions in Mr. Malthus's Essay on Population (London, 1805), 338-40. On the development of the Malthusian controversy generally, see Kenneth Smith, The Malthusian Controversy (London, 1951); James Alfred Field, "The Malthusian Controversy in England," in Essays on Population (Chicago, 1931), 1-86.
    • (1805) Observations on the Principal Conclusions in Mr. Malthus's Essay on Population , pp. 338-340
    • Hall, C.1
  • 84
    • 0008371444 scopus 로고
    • London
    • For an early critique which derides Malthus's treatment of the laboring class as "not only inhuman to the last degree, but unjust and iniquitous, see Charles Hall, Observations on the Principal Conclusions in Mr. Malthus's Essay on Population (London, 1805), 338-40. On the development of the Malthusian controversy generally, see Kenneth Smith, The Malthusian Controversy (London, 1951); James Alfred Field, "The Malthusian Controversy in England," in Essays on Population (Chicago, 1931), 1-86.
    • (1951) The Malthusian Controversy
    • Smith, K.1
  • 85
    • 0042835879 scopus 로고
    • The Malthusian controversy in England
    • Chicago
    • For an early critique which derides Malthus's treatment of the laboring class as "not only inhuman to the last degree, but unjust and iniquitous, see Charles Hall, Observations on the Principal Conclusions in Mr. Malthus's Essay on Population (London, 1805), 338-40. On the development of the Malthusian controversy generally, see Kenneth Smith, The Malthusian Controversy (London, 1951); James Alfred Field, "The Malthusian Controversy in England," in Essays on Population (Chicago, 1931), 1-86.
    • (1931) Essays on Population , pp. 1-86
    • Field, J.A.1
  • 90
    • 0003961257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed the language of "fitness" is already present in the assertion (in 1798) that the perils of existence enable some, at least, to attain "such high qualities and powers, as seem to indicate their fitness for some superior state" (Malthus, Essay on Population, 352). See Ritchie, Studies in Political and Social Ethics (London, 1902), 5.
    • Essay on Population , pp. 352
    • Malthus1
  • 91
    • 0042334987 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Indeed the language of "fitness" is already present in the assertion (in 1798) that the perils of existence enable some, at least, to attain "such high qualities and powers, as seem to indicate their fitness for some superior state" (Malthus, Essay on Population, 352). See Ritchie, Studies in Political and Social Ethics (London, 1902), 5.
    • (1902) Studies in Political and Social Ethics , pp. 5
    • Ritchie1
  • 94
    • 4344621752 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 9), 392; Roger Cooter, The Cultural Meaning of Popular Science: Phrenology and the Organisation of Consent in Nineteenth-Century Britain (Cambridge, 1984). Phrenology was an important element in Wallace's thinking. Mesmerism is a further influence which needs to be integrated into a fuller account of this subject.
    • (1860) The Constitution of Man , pp. 392
    • Combe, G.1
  • 96
    • 0041833831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lyle was even more influential on Wallace than on Darwin. See R. M. Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists," 129-33. On Darwin's use of the term, "struggle," see especially Peter Bowler, "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50.
    • Malthus and the Evolutionists , pp. 129-133
    • Young, R.M.1
  • 97
    • 0017004967 scopus 로고
    • Malthus, Darwin, and the concept of struggle
    • Lyle was even more influential on Wallace than on Darwin. See R. M. Young, "Malthus and the Evolutionists," 129-33. On Darwin's use of the term, "struggle," see especially Peter Bowler, "Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle," JHI, 37 (1976), 631-50.
    • (1976) JHI , vol.37 , pp. 631-650
    • Bowler, P.1
  • 98
    • 0001478648 scopus 로고
    • Social Darwinism: A definition
    • The general connection between laissez-faire economics and Social Darwinism, particularly in the United States, has of course long been recognised. See R. J. Halliday, "Social Darwinism: A Definition," Victorian Studies, 14 (1971), 396-97. Socialists tended to emphasize the connection most vehemently; see G. Bernard Shaw (ed.), Fabian Essays in Socialism (London, 1889), 28. There is however little discussion of Malthus, and much less of political economy, in many of the standard works on Darwin and Darwinism, e.g., William Irvine, Apes, Angels, and Victorians: Darwin, Huxley and Evolution (New York, 1959), 179, which devotes a paragraph to "laissez-faire" as a "master idea of the nineteenth century." Similarly Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century: Evolution and the Men Who Discovered It (New York, 1961), disposes of Malthus in a few sentences, while acknowledging him as "the source of most of nineteenth-century England's thinking on the struggle for existence" (182) and says nothing of political economy. On Darwinism and American political economy see Richard Hofstadter, Social Darwinism in American Thought, 143-56. An important exception is Silvan Schweber, "Darwin and the Political Economists: Divergence of Character," Journal of the History of Biology, 13 (1980), 195-289. which focuses on Darwin's use of ideas of the division of labor.
    • (1971) Victorian Studies , vol.14 , pp. 396-397
    • Halliday, R.J.1
  • 99
    • 0005429814 scopus 로고
    • London
    • The general connection between laissez-faire economics and Social Darwinism, particularly in the United States, has of course long been recognised. See R. J. Halliday, "Social Darwinism: A Definition," Victorian Studies, 14 (1971), 396-97. Socialists tended to emphasize the connection most vehemently; see G. Bernard Shaw (ed.), Fabian Essays in Socialism (London, 1889), 28. There is however little discussion of Malthus, and much less of political economy, in many of the standard works on Darwin and Darwinism, e.g., William Irvine, Apes, Angels, and Victorians: Darwin, Huxley and Evolution (New York, 1959), 179, which devotes a paragraph to "laissez-faire" as a "master idea of the nineteenth century." Similarly Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century: Evolution and the Men Who Discovered It (New York, 1961), disposes of Malthus in a few sentences, while acknowledging him as "the source of most of nineteenth-century England's thinking on the struggle for existence" (182) and says nothing of political economy. On Darwinism and American political economy see Richard Hofstadter, Social Darwinism in American Thought, 143-56. An important exception is Silvan Schweber, "Darwin and the Political Economists: Divergence of Character," Journal of the History of Biology, 13 (1980), 195-289. which focuses on Darwin's use of ideas of the division of labor.
    • (1889) Fabian Essays in Socialism , pp. 28
    • Shaw, G.B.1
  • 100
    • 0011565393 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • The general connection between laissez-faire economics and Social Darwinism, particularly in the United States, has of course long been recognised. See R. J. Halliday, "Social Darwinism: A Definition," Victorian Studies, 14 (1971), 396-97. Socialists tended to emphasize the connection most vehemently; see G. Bernard Shaw (ed.), Fabian Essays in Socialism (London, 1889), 28. There is however little discussion of Malthus, and much less of political economy, in many of the standard works on Darwin and Darwinism, e.g., William Irvine, Apes, Angels, and Victorians: Darwin, Huxley and Evolution (New York, 1959), 179, which devotes a paragraph to "laissez-faire" as a "master idea of the nineteenth century." Similarly Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century: Evolution and the Men Who Discovered It (New York, 1961), disposes of Malthus in a few sentences, while acknowledging him as "the source of most of nineteenth-century England's thinking on the struggle for existence" (182) and says nothing of political economy. On Darwinism and American political economy see Richard Hofstadter, Social Darwinism in American Thought, 143-56. An important exception is Silvan Schweber, "Darwin and the Political Economists: Divergence of Character," Journal of the History of Biology, 13 (1980), 195-289. which focuses on Darwin's use of ideas of the division of labor.
    • (1959) Apes, Angels, and Victorians: Darwin, Huxley and Evolution , pp. 179
    • Irvine, W.1
  • 101
    • 0003940610 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • The general connection between laissez-faire economics and Social Darwinism, particularly in the United States, has of course long been recognised. See R. J. Halliday, "Social Darwinism: A Definition," Victorian Studies, 14 (1971), 396-97. Socialists tended to emphasize the connection most vehemently; see G. Bernard Shaw (ed.), Fabian Essays in Socialism (London, 1889), 28. There is however little discussion of Malthus, and much less of political economy, in many of the standard works on Darwin and Darwinism, e.g., William Irvine, Apes, Angels, and Victorians: Darwin, Huxley and Evolution (New York, 1959), 179, which devotes a paragraph to "laissez-faire" as a "master idea of the nineteenth century." Similarly Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century: Evolution and the Men Who Discovered It (New York, 1961), disposes of Malthus in a few sentences, while acknowledging him as "the source of most of nineteenth-century England's thinking on the struggle for existence" (182) and says nothing of political economy. On Darwinism and American political economy see Richard Hofstadter, Social Darwinism in American Thought, 143-56. An important exception is Silvan Schweber, "Darwin and the Political Economists: Divergence of Character," Journal of the History of Biology, 13 (1980), 195-289. which focuses on Darwin's use of ideas of the division of labor.
    • (1961) Darwin's Century: Evolution and the Men Who Discovered It
    • Eiseley, L.1
  • 102
    • 0003967363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The general connection between laissez-faire economics and Social Darwinism, particularly in the United States, has of course long been recognised. See R. J. Halliday, "Social Darwinism: A Definition," Victorian Studies, 14 (1971), 396-97. Socialists tended to emphasize the connection most vehemently; see G. Bernard Shaw (ed.), Fabian Essays in Socialism (London, 1889), 28. There is however little discussion of Malthus, and much less of political economy, in many of the standard works on Darwin and Darwinism, e.g., William Irvine, Apes, Angels, and Victorians: Darwin, Huxley and Evolution (New York, 1959), 179, which devotes a paragraph to "laissez-faire" as a "master idea of the nineteenth century." Similarly Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century: Evolution and the Men Who Discovered It (New York, 1961), disposes of Malthus in a few sentences, while acknowledging him as "the source of most of nineteenth-century England's thinking on the struggle for existence" (182) and says nothing of political economy. On Darwinism and American political economy see Richard Hofstadter, Social Darwinism in American Thought, 143-56. An important exception is Silvan Schweber, "Darwin and the Political Economists: Divergence of Character," Journal of the History of Biology, 13 (1980), 195-289. which focuses on Darwin's use of ideas of the division of labor.
    • Social Darwinism in American Thought , pp. 143-156
    • Hofstadter, R.1
  • 103
    • 0019054603 scopus 로고
    • Darwin and the political economists: Divergence of character
    • The general connection between laissez-faire economics and Social Darwinism, particularly in the United States, has of course long been recognised. See R. J. Halliday, "Social Darwinism: A Definition," Victorian Studies, 14 (1971), 396-97. Socialists tended to emphasize the connection most vehemently; see G. Bernard Shaw (ed.), Fabian Essays in Socialism (London, 1889), 28. There is however little discussion of Malthus, and much less of political economy, in many of the standard works on Darwin and Darwinism, e.g., William Irvine, Apes, Angels, and Victorians: Darwin, Huxley and Evolution (New York, 1959), 179, which devotes a paragraph to "laissez-faire" as a "master idea of the nineteenth century." Similarly Loren Eiseley, Darwin's Century: Evolution and the Men Who Discovered It (New York, 1961), disposes of Malthus in a few sentences, while acknowledging him as "the source of most of nineteenth-century England's thinking on the struggle for existence" (182) and says nothing of political economy. On Darwinism and American political economy see Richard Hofstadter, Social Darwinism in American Thought, 143-56. An important exception is Silvan Schweber, "Darwin and the Political Economists: Divergence of Character," Journal of the History of Biology, 13 (1980), 195-289. which focuses on Darwin's use of ideas of the division of labor.
    • (1980) Journal of the History of Biology , vol.13 , pp. 195-289
    • Schweber, S.1
  • 105
    • 0041833828 scopus 로고
    • Toronto
    • As Mill put it in 1844, "In proportion to the amount of the productive labour and consumption of a country, the country . . . is enriched: in proportion to the amount of unproductive labour and consumption, the country is impoverished." John Stuart Mill, Works (Toronto, 1975), IV, 283-84.
    • (1975) Works
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 109
    • 0042835875 scopus 로고
    • London
    • E.g., William Hearn, Plutology, or the Theory of the Efforts to Satisfy Human Wants (London, 1864), 345-46. Amongst the first political economists to cite Darwin, Hearn particularly noted the value of his "stern yet salutary law" of natural selection to society (347), and to link this theory to Malthus (392-93).
    • (1864) Plutology, or the Theory of the Efforts to Satisfy Human Wants , pp. 345-346
    • Hearn, W.1
  • 110
    • 0003551629 scopus 로고
    • London
    • See Harold Perkin, The Origins of Modern English Society 1780-1880 (London, 1969): The success of the "entrepreneurial ideal" has of course been challenged, notably by Martin Wiener, in English Culture and the Decline of the Industrial Spirit (Cambridge, 1985).
    • (1969) The Origins of Modern English Society 1780-1880
    • Perkin, H.1
  • 111
    • 0003837124 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • See Harold Perkin, The Origins of Modern English Society 1780-1880 (London, 1969): The success of the "entrepreneurial ideal" has of course been challenged, notably by Martin Wiener, in English Culture and the Decline of the Industrial Spirit (Cambridge, 1985).
    • (1985) English Culture and the Decline of the Industrial Spirit
    • Wiener, M.1
  • 114
    • 0041833825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus Huxley believed that Spencer's phrase, "the survival of the fittest," was a poor choice on Darwin's part, "in consequence of the ambiguity of the 'fittest,' which many take to mean 'best' or 'highest' - whereas natural selection may work towards degradation" (quoted in James Allen Rodgers, "Darwinism and Social Darwinism," 278).
    • Darwinism and Social Darwinism , pp. 27
    • Rodgers, J.A.1
  • 115
    • 0002368104 scopus 로고
    • The origin of the human races and the antiquity of man deduced from the theory of natural selection
    • See Wallace, "The Origin of the Human Races and the Antiquity of Man Deduced from the Theory of Natural Selection," Anthropological Review, 2, (1864), clxiv.
    • (1864) Anthropological Review , vol.2
    • Wallace1
  • 116
    • 0000350213 scopus 로고
    • Gregariousness in cattle and men
    • Macmillan's Magazine, 18 (June and August 1865), 166, 321. The trend was continued in Galton's "Gregariousness in Cattle and Men," Macmillan's Magazine, 23 (1870-71), 353-57.
    • (1870) Macmillan's Magazine , vol.23 , pp. 353-357
  • 117
    • 0017462104 scopus 로고
    • Darwin as a social evolutionist
    • On the making of Darwin as a Social Darwinist, see John Greene, "Darwin as a Social Evolutionist," Journal of the History of Biology, 10 (1977), 1-27 .
    • (1977) Journal of the History of Biology , vol.10 , pp. 1-27
    • Greene, J.1
  • 118
    • 0242705651 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Fraser's Magazine, September 1868. See further W. R. Greg, Enigmas of Life (London, 1873), 92-132.
    • (1873) Enigmas of Life , pp. 92-132
    • Greg, W.R.1
  • 119
    • 0042638086 scopus 로고
    • A theory of population, deduced from the general law of animal fertility
    • ns.
    • Spencer, "A Theory of Population, Deduced From the General Law of Animal Fertility," Westminster Review, ns. 1 (1852), 496.
    • (1852) Westminster Review , vol.1 , pp. 496
    • Spencer1
  • 122
    • 0003418143 scopus 로고
    • 2 vols.; London
    • Yet Darwin also supported the Galtonian, radical conclusion that "There should be open competition for all men; and the most able should not be prevented by laws or customs from succeeding best and rearing the largest number of offspring" (Descent of Man, 618), and similarly opposed primogeniture, writing in 1864 on the British aristocracy that "what a shame is primogeniture for destroying Natural Selection!" Frances Darwin and A. Seward (eds.), More Letters of Charles Darwin (2 vols.; London, 1903), II, 34. On the background to the Descent, see Jones, "The Social History of Darwin's Descent of Man," Economy and Society, 1 (1978), 1-23.
    • (1903) More Letters of Charles Darwin
    • Darwin, F.1    Seward, A.2
  • 123
    • 0043138993 scopus 로고
    • The social history of Darwin's descent of man
    • Yet Darwin also supported the Galtonian, radical conclusion that "There should be open competition for all men; and the most able should not be prevented by laws or customs from succeeding best and rearing the largest number of offspring" (Descent of Man, 618), and similarly opposed primogeniture, writing in 1864 on the British aristocracy that "what a shame is primogeniture for destroying Natural Selection!" Frances Darwin and A. Seward (eds.), More Letters of Charles Darwin (2 vols.; London, 1903), II, 34. On the background to the Descent, see Jones, "The Social History of Darwin's Descent of Man," Economy and Society, 1 (1978), 1-23.
    • (1978) Economy and Society , vol.1 , pp. 1-23
    • Jones1
  • 125
    • 0003620561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • What is not new, thus, is a "new scientific vocabulary of struggle and survival." Nancy Stepan, The Idea of Race in Science; Great Britain 1800-1960 (New York, 1982), 49. On the evolution of systems of racial classification see also generally Louis L. Snyder, The Idea of Racialism (New York, 1962); J. S. Haller, Outcasts from Evolution: Scientific Attitudes of Racial Inferiority, 1859-1900 (1971); and Jones, Social Darwinism, 140-59.
    • (1982) The Idea of Race in Science; Great Britain 1800-1960 , pp. 49
    • Stepan, N.1
  • 126
    • 0040082808 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • What is not new, thus, is a "new scientific vocabulary of struggle and survival." Nancy Stepan, The Idea of Race in Science; Great Britain 1800-1960 (New York, 1982), 49. On the evolution of systems of racial classification see also generally Louis L. Snyder, The Idea of Racialism (New York, 1962); J. S. Haller, Outcasts from Evolution: Scientific Attitudes of Racial Inferiority, 1859-1900 (1971); and Jones, Social Darwinism, 140-59.
    • (1962) The Idea of Racialism
    • Snyder, L.L.1
  • 127
    • 0004093810 scopus 로고
    • What is not new, thus, is a "new scientific vocabulary of struggle and survival." Nancy Stepan, The Idea of Race in Science; Great Britain 1800-1960 (New York, 1982), 49. On the evolution of systems of racial classification see also generally Louis L. Snyder, The Idea of Racialism (New York, 1962); J. S. Haller, Outcasts from Evolution: Scientific Attitudes of Racial Inferiority, 1859-1900 (1971); and Jones, Social Darwinism, 140-59.
    • (1971) Outcasts from Evolution: Scientific Attitudes of Racial Inferiority, 1859-1900
    • Haller, J.S.1
  • 128
    • 0042834975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is not new, thus, is a "new scientific vocabulary of struggle and survival." Nancy Stepan, The Idea of Race in Science; Great Britain 1800-1960 (New York, 1982), 49. On the evolution of systems of racial classification see also generally Louis L. Snyder, The Idea of Racialism (New York, 1962); J. S. Haller, Outcasts from Evolution: Scientific Attitudes of Racial Inferiority, 1859-1900 (1971); and Jones, Social Darwinism, 140-59.
    • Social Darwinism , pp. 140-159
    • Jones1
  • 129
    • 0003362628 scopus 로고
    • London
    • The best general account of such views in Britain in this period is Christine Bolt, Victorian Attitudes to Race (London, 1971).
    • (1971) Victorian Attitudes to Race
    • Bolt, C.1
  • 130
    • 0003620561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this development see generally Stepan. The Idea of Race in Science, Marvin Harris, The Rise of Anthropological Theory (London, 1968), ch. 4, "The Rise of Racial Determinism"; Haller, Outcasts from Evolution; Mike Hawkins, Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 184-215.
    • The Idea of Race in Science
    • Stepan1
  • 131
    • 0042334075 scopus 로고
    • The rise of racial determinism
    • London, ch. 4
    • On this development see generally Stepan. The Idea of Race in Science, Marvin Harris, The Rise of Anthropological Theory (London, 1968), ch. 4, "The Rise of Racial Determinism"; Haller, Outcasts from Evolution; Mike Hawkins, Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 184-215.
    • (1968) The Rise of Anthropological Theory
    • Harris, M.1
  • 132
    • 0012660768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this development see generally Stepan. The Idea of Race in Science, Marvin Harris, The Rise of Anthropological Theory (London, 1968), ch. 4, "The Rise of Racial Determinism"; Haller, Outcasts from Evolution; Mike Hawkins, Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 184-215.
    • Outcasts from Evolution
    • Haller1
  • 133
    • 0004099842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this development see generally Stepan. The Idea of Race in Science, Marvin Harris, The Rise of Anthropological Theory (London, 1968), ch. 4, "The Rise of Racial Determinism"; Haller, Outcasts from Evolution; Mike Hawkins, Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 184-215.
    • Social Darwinism in European and American Thought , pp. 184-215
    • Hawkins, M.1
  • 134
    • 0010099734 scopus 로고
    • The origins of racial Anglo-Saxonism in Great Britain before 1850
    • On the origins of this process see in particular Reginald Horsman, "The Origins of Racial Anglo-Saxonism in Great Britain before 1850," JHI, 37 (1976), 387-410. On the emergence of racial determinism between 1830-50, which lays particulary stress on the role played by phrenology, see Nancy Stepan, The Idea of Race in Science, 20-46.
    • (1976) JHI , vol.37 , pp. 387-410
    • Horsman, R.1
  • 135
    • 0003620561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the origins of this process see in particular Reginald Horsman, "The Origins of Racial Anglo-Saxonism in Great Britain before 1850," JHI, 37 (1976), 387-410. On the emergence of racial determinism between 1830-50, which lays particulary stress on the role played by phrenology, see Nancy Stepan, The Idea of Race in Science, 20-46.
    • The Idea of Race in Science , pp. 20-46
    • Stepan, N.1
  • 136
    • 0040954350 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Robert Knox, The Races of Man (London, 1850), 411. See Stepan, The Idea of Race in Science, 43, for an analysis of the displacement of earlier, more environmentalist notions of race in this period.
    • (1850) The Races of Man , pp. 411
    • Knox, R.1
  • 137
    • 0003620561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Knox, The Races of Man (London, 1850), 411. See Stepan, The Idea of Race in Science, 43, for an analysis of the displacement of earlier, more environmentalist notions of race in this period.
    • The Idea of Race in Science , pp. 43
    • Stepan1
  • 138
    • 0041832955 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Edward Freeman, Comparative Politics (London, 1873), iv. Even A. R. Wallace was led to concluded that differences in racial character were seemingly primordial. See "Evolution and Character," in Percy Parker (ed.), Character and Life (London, 1912), 38-40. But he was equally certain that human "ethical and moral nature has not advanced in any perceptible degree" throughout the process of evolution (43), and that savages were thus not inferior mentally to more civilized peoples. See generally John Burrow. Evolution and Society.
    • (1873) Comparative Politics
    • Freeman, E.1
  • 139
    • 0041832957 scopus 로고
    • Evolution and character
    • London
    • Edward Freeman, Comparative Politics (London, 1873), iv. Even A. R. Wallace was led to concluded that differences in racial character were seemingly primordial. See "Evolution and Character," in Percy Parker (ed.), Character and Life (London, 1912), 38-40. But he was equally certain that human "ethical and moral nature has not advanced in any perceptible degree" throughout the process of evolution (43), and that savages were thus not inferior mentally to more civilized peoples. See generally John Burrow. Evolution and Society.
    • (1912) Character and Life , pp. 38-40
    • Parker, P.1
  • 140
    • 0003717996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Edward Freeman, Comparative Politics (London, 1873), iv. Even A. R. Wallace was led to concluded that differences in racial character were seemingly primordial. See "Evolution and Character," in Percy Parker (ed.), Character and Life (London, 1912), 38-40. But he was equally certain that human "ethical and moral nature has not advanced in any perceptible degree" throughout the process of evolution (43), and that savages were thus not inferior mentally to more civilized peoples. See generally John Burrow. Evolution and Society.
    • Evolution and Society
    • Burrow, J.1
  • 142
    • 0042334074 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • Particularly in relation to Africa, for in the Descent of Man Darwin, among others, asserted that both Indians and Europeans were derived from the same Aryan stock, an ideal originating largely in late eighteenth-century philology. On the Indian context, see more broadly G. D. Bearce, British Attitudes towards India, 1784-1858 (Oxford, 1961). Even liberals like Bagehot were affected. See the comments on race mixtures in Physics and Politics (London, 1884), 70-71.
    • (1961) British Attitudes Towards India, 1784-1858
    • Bearce, G.D.1
  • 143
    • 0042834974 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Particularly in relation to Africa, for in the Descent of Man Darwin, among others, asserted that both Indians and Europeans were derived from the same Aryan stock, an ideal originating largely in late eighteenth-century philology. On the Indian context, see more broadly G. D. Bearce, British Attitudes towards India, 1784-1858 (Oxford, 1961). Even liberals like Bagehot were affected. See the comments on race mixtures in Physics and Politics (London, 1884), 70-71.
    • (1884) Physics and Politics , pp. 70-71


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.