메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 46, Issue 4, 1998, Pages 693-708

Transnational and international exploitation

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0039992053     PISSN: 00323217     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1467-9248.00162     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (10)

References (51)
  • 1
    • 85033888372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Freedom and Trade conference, Manchester, March 1996. I have benefitted a lot from comments by Jonathan Wolff, Daniel Attas and the two referees. I would also like to thank Simon Caney, Jerry Cohen, Peter Jones, Peter Ingram, William Lucy, David Milman, Geraint Parry, Hillel Steiner, and Bhaskar Vira. While writing this paper I enjoyed the hospitality of Mansfield College, Oxford, and the Oxford Centre for Environment, Ethics and Society, where I was a Visiting Research Fellow.
  • 2
    • 85033903690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By 'transnational exploitation' I mean exploitative exchange that takes place between bodies and individuals in different societies; by 'international exploitation' I mean exploitative exchange that takes place between states.
  • 3
    • 0009400576 scopus 로고
    • New York, Free
    • For some very interesting works see J. Galtung, The True Worlds (New York, Free, 1980); I. Wallerstein, Geopolitics and Geoculture: Essays on the Changing World-System (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), especially chapter 6 ('Marx, Marxism-Leninism and Socialist Experience in the Modern World-System', pp. 65-84); I. Wallerstein, The Capitalist World Economy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1979); T. Hopkins, 'Notes in Class Analysis and the World System', in T. Hopkins and I. Wallerstein (eds), World-Systems Analysis (Beverly Hills, Sage, 1982), pp. 83-91; and R. Barnet, Global Reach: the Power of Multinational Corporations (New York, Simon and Schuster, 1974), especially chapter 6 in which he discusses the global corporations and the 'underdeveloped' world.
    • (1980) The True Worlds
    • Galtung, J.1
  • 4
    • 85040891909 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, especially chapter 6
    • For some very interesting works see J. Galtung, The True Worlds (New York, Free, 1980); I. Wallerstein, Geopolitics and Geoculture: Essays on the Changing World-System (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), especially chapter 6 ('Marx, Marxism-Leninism and Socialist Experience in the Modern World-System', pp. 65-84); I. Wallerstein, The Capitalist World Economy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1979); T. Hopkins, 'Notes in Class Analysis and the World System', in T. Hopkins and I. Wallerstein (eds), World-Systems Analysis (Beverly Hills, Sage, 1982), pp. 83-91; and R. Barnet, Global Reach: the Power of Multinational Corporations (New York, Simon and Schuster, 1974), especially chapter 6 in which he discusses the global corporations and the 'underdeveloped' world.
    • (1991) Geopolitics and Geoculture: Essays on the Changing World-system
    • Wallerstein, I.1
  • 5
    • 85033900613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For some very interesting works see J. Galtung, The True Worlds (New York, Free, 1980); I. Wallerstein, Geopolitics and Geoculture: Essays on the Changing World-System (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), especially chapter 6 ('Marx, Marxism-Leninism and Socialist Experience in the Modern World-System', pp. 65-84); I. Wallerstein, The Capitalist World Economy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1979); T. Hopkins, 'Notes in Class Analysis and the World System', in T. Hopkins and I. Wallerstein (eds), World-Systems Analysis (Beverly Hills, Sage, 1982), pp. 83-91; and R. Barnet, Global Reach: the Power of Multinational Corporations (New York, Simon and Schuster, 1974), especially chapter 6 in which he discusses the global corporations and the 'underdeveloped' world.
    • Marx, Marxism-Leninism and Socialist Experience in the Modern World-system , pp. 65-84
  • 6
    • 0003721432 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
    • For some very interesting works see J. Galtung, The True Worlds (New York, Free, 1980); I. Wallerstein, Geopolitics and Geoculture: Essays on the Changing World-System (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), especially chapter 6 ('Marx, Marxism-Leninism and Socialist Experience in the Modern World-System', pp. 65-84); I. Wallerstein, The Capitalist World Economy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1979); T. Hopkins, 'Notes in Class Analysis and the World System', in T. Hopkins and I. Wallerstein (eds), World-Systems Analysis (Beverly Hills, Sage, 1982), pp. 83-91; and R. Barnet, Global Reach: the Power of Multinational Corporations (New York, Simon and Schuster, 1974), especially chapter 6 in which he discusses the global corporations and the 'underdeveloped' world.
    • (1979) The Capitalist World Economy
    • Wallerstein, I.1
  • 7
    • 84931093221 scopus 로고
    • Notes in class analysis and the world system
    • T. Hopkins and I. Wallerstein (eds), Beverly Hills, Sage
    • For some very interesting works see J. Galtung, The True Worlds (New York, Free, 1980); I. Wallerstein, Geopolitics and Geoculture: Essays on the Changing World-System (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), especially chapter 6 ('Marx, Marxism-Leninism and Socialist Experience in the Modern World-System', pp. 65-84); I. Wallerstein, The Capitalist World Economy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1979); T. Hopkins, 'Notes in Class Analysis and the World System', in T. Hopkins and I. Wallerstein (eds), World-Systems Analysis (Beverly Hills, Sage, 1982), pp. 83-91; and R. Barnet, Global Reach: the Power of Multinational Corporations (New York, Simon and Schuster, 1974), especially chapter 6 in which he discusses the global corporations and the 'underdeveloped' world.
    • (1982) World-systems Analysis , pp. 83-91
    • Hopkins, T.1
  • 8
    • 84894872825 scopus 로고
    • New York, Simon and Schuster
    • For some very interesting works see J. Galtung, The True Worlds (New York, Free, 1980); I. Wallerstein, Geopolitics and Geoculture: Essays on the Changing World-System (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), especially chapter 6 ('Marx, Marxism-Leninism and Socialist Experience in the Modern World-System', pp. 65-84); I. Wallerstein, The Capitalist World Economy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1979); T. Hopkins, 'Notes in Class Analysis and the World System', in T. Hopkins and I. Wallerstein (eds), World-Systems Analysis (Beverly Hills, Sage, 1982), pp. 83-91; and R. Barnet, Global Reach: the Power of Multinational Corporations (New York, Simon and Schuster, 1974), especially chapter 6 in which he discusses the global corporations and the 'underdeveloped' world.
    • (1974) Global Reach: the Power of Multinational Corporations
    • Barnet, R.1
  • 10
    • 85033884478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am assuming that playing tricks in order to avoid taxes is another way of exploiting the poor, who cannot avoid taxation by the same means.
  • 11
    • 85033889548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A good example is coffee, which is often grown and picked in Third World countries in which the gaps between the rich and the poor are enormous, but is processed in northern countries which may be proud of diminishing exploitation in their own societies.
  • 12
    • 84976998862 scopus 로고
    • A structural theory of imperialism
    • See J. Galtung, 'A Structural theory of imperialism', Journal of Peace Research, 8 (1971), (1971), 81-118.
    • (1971) Journal of Peace Research , vol.8 , pp. 81-118
    • Galtung, J.1
  • 13
    • 85033871471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I shall later discuss whether they are forced or even coerced to sell their labour power.
  • 14
    • 0004202764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another case in the same category is when an international corporation exploits a state. See R. Barnet, Global Reach.
    • Global Reach.
    • Barnet, R.1
  • 15
    • 0004084217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
    • J. Elster, Making Sense of Marx (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 167.
    • (1987) Making Sense of Marx , pp. 167
    • Elster, J.1
  • 17
    • 0040605089 scopus 로고
    • A theory of exploitation
    • I take Hillel Steiner's 'A theory of exploitation', Ethics, 94 (1984) to be the only one, and therefore I shall discuss it here as the liberal theory of exploitation.
    • (1984) Ethics , vol.94
    • Steiner, H.1
  • 18
    • 0041199144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Steiner, 'A liberal theory of exploitation', p. 227. I wonder whether this is right, because a 'hard-line capitalist would not engage in a deal from which s/he cannot get more than s/he gives; in other words s/he is looking for the surplus value, or for exploitation, as a motivation to enter a deal. Now Steiner could answer that what s/he gets may be more important for her or him than what s/he gives, but the only criteria for a 'hard-line' capitalist is the market value rather than a subjective notion of value. In that case, it seems to me wrong to argue that the 'exploiters and exploited would voluntarily become exchangers'. But this is beyond the interest of this paper.
    • A Liberal Theory of Exploitation , pp. 227
    • Steiner1
  • 19
    • 0003493951 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley, University of California Press
    • There is a wide critique of the inadequacy of Marxian theory of exploitation to encompass a variety of forms of domination and exploitation. (See A. Giddens, A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism (Berkeley, University of California Press, 1990) and R. Murphy, 'Exploitation or exclusion', Sociology, 19 (1985).) But 1 would like to emphasize the inadequacy with regard to the international domination. It should also be mentioned that Marx did think about exploitation in the international arena. Marx wrote that 'the richer country exploits the poorer one, even where the latter gains by the exchange' (Theories of Surplus Value, cited in Elster, Making Sense of Marx, 181). Elster notes that 'Marx certainly did not mean that the rich country does so by hiring the workers of the poor', mainly because this phenomenon developed after Marx's death. This implies that he meant exploitation between states.
    • (1990) A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism
    • Giddens, A.1
  • 20
    • 84970358967 scopus 로고
    • Exploitation or exclusion
    • There is a wide critique of the inadequacy of Marxian theory of exploitation to encompass a variety of forms of domination and exploitation. (See A. Giddens, A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism (Berkeley, University of California Press, 1990) and R. Murphy, 'Exploitation or exclusion', Sociology, 19 (1985).) But 1 would like to emphasize the inadequacy with regard to the international domination. It should also be mentioned that Marx did think about exploitation in the international arena. Marx wrote that 'the richer country exploits the poorer one, even where the latter gains by the exchange' (Theories of Surplus Value, cited in Elster, Making Sense of Marx, 181). Elster notes that 'Marx certainly did not mean that the rich country does so by hiring the workers of the poor', mainly because this phenomenon developed after Marx's death. This implies that he meant exploitation between states.
    • (1985) Sociology , vol.19
    • Murphy, R.1
  • 21
    • 85033873457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theories of surplus value
    • There is a wide critique of the inadequacy of Marxian theory of exploitation to encompass a variety of forms of domination and exploitation. (See A. Giddens, A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism (Berkeley, University of California Press, 1990) and R. Murphy, 'Exploitation or exclusion', Sociology, 19 (1985).) But 1 would like to emphasize the inadequacy with regard to the international domination. It should also be mentioned that Marx did think about exploitation in the international arena. Marx wrote that 'the richer country exploits the poorer one, even where the latter gains by the exchange' (Theories of Surplus Value, cited in Elster, Making Sense of Marx, 181). Elster notes that 'Marx certainly did not mean that the rich country does so by hiring the workers of the poor', mainly because this phenomenon developed after Marx's death. This implies that he meant exploitation between states.
    • Making Sense of Marx , pp. 181
    • Elster1
  • 22
    • 0040011962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact the main challenge to Steiner's theory in general is that since it is a trilateral matter it is sensitive to irrelevant factors. As Miller argues, suppose A prevents C from offering B a better deal by other means, e.g. bribe rather than threat. Does this make the same exchange between A and B different from B's point of view? See D. Miller, 'Exploitation in the market' and Steiner's reply 'Exploitation: a liberal theory amended, defended and extended', both in A. Reeve (ed.), Modern Theories of Exploitation.
    • Exploitation in the Market
    • Miller, D.1
  • 23
    • 0003232207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exploitation: A liberal theory amended, defended and extended
    • A. Reeve (ed.)
    • In fact the main challenge to Steiner's theory in general is that since it is a trilateral matter it is sensitive to irrelevant factors. As Miller argues, suppose A prevents C from offering B a better deal by other means, e.g. bribe rather than threat. Does this make the same exchange between A and B different from B's point of view? See D. Miller, 'Exploitation in the market' and Steiner's reply 'Exploitation: a liberal theory amended, defended and extended', both in A. Reeve (ed.), Modern Theories of Exploitation.
    • Modern Theories of Exploitation
    • Steiner1
  • 24
    • 85033878929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By 'capable' I mean that it is also willing to do so. A more powerful state may still restrain itself, either for internal reasons or because although its militaristic powers are greater, it does not enjoy strategic superiority over the other state.
  • 25
    • 85033896788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It should be noted that within the state forcing someone to trade on your terms by threatening does not imply exploitation, because the threatened party can rely on the police or the judicial system to prevent the threatening party from actually doing what it threatens to do. These institutions are absent in the international arena.
  • 26
    • 0041199149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exploitation, freedom and justice
    • J. R. Pennock and J. W. Chapman (eds)
    • J. Elster, 'Exploitation, Freedom and Justice', in J. R. Pennock and J. W. Chapman (eds), Marxism (Nomos XXVI) (New York, New York University Press, 1983); and Making Sense of Marx, p. 168. The slave example poses a similar difficulty for the liberal theory - for it is the slave's rights rather than a third party's that are violated. I owe this point to Daniel Attas.
    • (1983) Marxism (Nomos XXVI) New York, New York University Press
    • Elster, J.1
  • 27
    • 84973185828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • J. Elster, 'Exploitation, Freedom and Justice', in J. R. Pennock and J. W. Chapman (eds), Marxism (Nomos XXVI) (New York, New York University Press, 1983); and Making Sense of Marx, p. 168. The slave example poses a similar difficulty for the liberal theory - for it is the slave's rights rather than a third party's that are violated. I owe this point to Daniel Attas.
    • Making Sense of Marx , pp. 168
  • 29
    • 0004276654 scopus 로고
    • col. 1 New York, International Publishers
    • K. Marx, Capital, col. 1 (New York, International Publishers, 1967), p. 332.
    • (1967) Capital , pp. 332
    • Marx, K.1
  • 30
    • 0345837777 scopus 로고
    • Property relations vs. surplus value Marxian exploitation
    • J. Roemer, 'Property relations vs. surplus value Marxian exploitation', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 11 (1982), 285.
    • (1982) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.11 , pp. 285
    • Roemer, J.1
  • 31
    • 85033873039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Notice that some of these Palestinians argue that they are not better off even in political terms, since the new autonomous regime is so undemocratic. Nevertheless, this does not mean that they were not exploited by Israel. This points to the possibility that exploitation has no relation at all to the alternative of being better off, but rather to the lack of autonomy, or to being treated as having no autonomy.
  • 32
    • 0039419681 scopus 로고
    • Five faces of oppression
    • See I. Young, 'Five faces of oppression', The Philosophical Forum, 29 (1988), 270-90.
    • (1988) The Philosophical Forum , vol.29 , pp. 270-290
    • Young, I.1
  • 34
    • 85033895512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Except for cases of occupation. Then the occupier tends to capture the natural resources or means of production, and may use force (the police or the army) to prevent the occupied people from autonomous (or any) use of these means of production.
  • 35
    • 0041199149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elster ('Exploitation, Freedom and Justice,' p. 278) does mention treating others merely as means, but thinks that it is more akin to alienation than to exploitation.
    • Exploitation, Freedom and Justice , pp. 278
    • Elster1
  • 36
    • 85033872356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I assume that the reader is familiar with the Kantian imperative and with the works of Dworkin about treating as equals (as distinguished from equal treatment).
  • 37
    • 85033888776 scopus 로고
    • unpublished M.A. Thesis University College
    • On the difference between exploiting circumstances and exploiting a person, see J. Wolff, 'Exploitation', unpublished M.A. Thesis (University College, 1985), pp 24-41. Similarly, Goodin distinguishes between exploiting a situation and exploiting a person although he accepts that exploiting a person is a particular case of exploiting a situation, where the situation describes personal characteristics as well. See R. Goodin, 'Exploiting a Situation and Exploiting a Person', in A. Reeve (ed.), Modern Theories of Exploitation (London, Sage, 1987), pp. 149-66.
    • (1985) Exploitation , pp. 24-41
    • Wolff, J.1
  • 38
    • 0007363723 scopus 로고
    • Exploiting a situation and exploiting a person
    • A. Reeve (ed.), London, Sage
    • On the difference between exploiting circumstances and exploiting a person, see J. Wolff, 'Exploitation', unpublished M.A. Thesis (University College, 1985), pp 24-41. Similarly, Goodin distinguishes between exploiting a situation and exploiting a person although he accepts that exploiting a person is a particular case of exploiting a situation, where the situation describes personal characteristics as well. See R. Goodin, 'Exploiting a Situation and Exploiting a Person', in A. Reeve (ed.), Modern Theories of Exploitation (London, Sage, 1987), pp. 149-66.
    • (1987) Modern Theories of Exploitation , pp. 149-166
    • Goodin, R.1
  • 39
    • 85033881601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I do not wish to discuss this further. The interested reader may refer to Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom and Equality.
  • 40
    • 0040477281 scopus 로고
    • London, Routledge
    • Another version is that it would be in the interest of his or her descendants (future generations), and hence in his or her interest as well. I have discussed this in my Why Posterity Matters (London, Routledge, 1995).
    • (1995) Why Posterity Matters
  • 41
    • 85033895029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • However, the fact that the exploiter is aware of his/her actions and their consequences, should not imply that the potential victim is aware of him/herself being exploited. The workers' false consciousness, described by Marx, is a good example of such a case.
  • 43
    • 0004128375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen (Self-Ownership, Freedom and Equality, p. 241) dismisses this claim forcefully. However, in case the reader still believes so, it is safer to stick to the Dworkinian formula.
    • Self-ownership, Freedom and Equality , pp. 241
    • Cohen1
  • 44
    • 85033894971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Since Wood adopts a totally objective definition he runs into difficulties. For example, he writes that 'some instances of exploitation (exploiting the weakness of one's opponent in a game) can be regarded as innocent. One would not enter into the game with good sportmanship if one did not expect (or even want) one's opponent to use one's weakness wherever possible' (p. 152). Indeed, our intuition is that sport games cannot be regarded as exploitation. But notice that in my definition this is not exploitation at all. Assuming that both competitors respect each other, there is no intention (in the game) to benefit by treating not as equals. The fact that objectively Oxford United are much weaker than Newcastle United does not mastter. All players respect each other equally, and therefore Newcastles's players do not exploit Oxford's players when they beat them 5-0.
  • 47
    • 0004084217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coercion implies the presence of an intentional agent or coercer, while force need not imply more than the presence of constraints that leave no room for choice: 'I am forced to live in my native town if I cannot get a job elsewhere, but I am coerced to live there if I would be arrested were I to try to leave'. Elster, Making Sense of Marx, p. 212.
    • Making Sense of Marx , pp. 212
    • Elster1
  • 48
    • 0004157494 scopus 로고
    • New York, Oxford University Press
    • The distinction between entering the situation of exploitative exchange and the absence of a way out of it is important for all theories of exploitation. Many authors regard exploitation as not necessarily involuntary. Joel Feinberg claims that exploitation may follow a voluntary consent (Harmless Wrongdoing (New York, Oxford University Press, 1988), p. 176), and Wertheimer even claims that the exploited party benefits more than the exploiter does, and that this is the reason that the exploited party's bargaining position is so weak ('Two questions about surrogacy and exploitation', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 223). Allen Wood quotes the two and adds that people can often be eager to be exploited since 'being benefited and exploited are often merely two sides of the same coin, and people may often be in dire need of the benefits in question' (Wood, 'Exploitation', p. 149). In my view this attitude discounts the immorality of exploitation. The exploited one is exploited, but also benefits. But benefits in relation to what? Not in relation to his or her original status (the one prior to the new circumstances which have led to this exploitative exchange), but rather in relation to his new position. The exploiting party manipulates the exploited one to a position in which he is desperate, and then offers him a generous way out of it, namely by exploiting him. See, for instance, the example which Wood raises. A gambler who owes a large amount of money to ruthless and violent characters will be in desperate need of the loan from the shark who offers the needed funds at a usurious rate of interest. Such a person will be more than willing under these conditions to consent to virtually any terms of payment (Wood, 'Exploitation', p. 149). Shouldn't we consider also the dignity, self-esteem, etc., of the gambler? And does he continue to be in this position because he wants to?
    • (1988) Harmless Wrongdoing , pp. 176
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 49
    • 0026882749 scopus 로고
    • Two questions about surrogacy and exploitation
    • The distinction between entering the situation of exploitative exchange and the absence of a way out of it is important for all theories of exploitation. Many authors regard exploitation as not necessarily involuntary. Joel Feinberg claims that exploitation may follow a voluntary consent (Harmless Wrongdoing (New York, Oxford University Press, 1988), p. 176), and Wertheimer even claims that the exploited party benefits more than the exploiter does, and that this is the reason that the exploited party's bargaining position is so weak ('Two questions about surrogacy and exploitation', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 223). Allen Wood quotes the two and adds that people can often be eager to be exploited since 'being benefited and exploited are often merely two sides of the same coin, and people may often be in dire need of the benefits in question' (Wood, 'Exploitation', p. 149). In my view this attitude discounts the immorality of exploitation. The exploited one is exploited, but also benefits. But benefits in relation to what? Not in relation to his or her original status (the one prior to the new circumstances which have led to this exploitative exchange), but rather in relation to his new position. The exploiting party manipulates the exploited one to a position in which he is desperate, and then offers him a generous way out of it, namely by exploiting him. See, for instance, the example which Wood raises. A gambler who owes a large amount of money to ruthless and violent characters will be in desperate need of the loan from the shark who offers the needed funds at a usurious rate of interest. Such a person will be more than willing under these conditions to consent to virtually any terms of payment (Wood, 'Exploitation', p. 149). Shouldn't we consider also the dignity, self-esteem, etc., of the gambler? And does he continue to be in this position because he wants to?
    • (1992) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.21 , pp. 223
  • 50
    • 77449132121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The distinction between entering the situation of exploitative exchange and the absence of a way out of it is important for all theories of exploitation. Many authors regard exploitation as not necessarily involuntary. Joel Feinberg claims that exploitation may follow a voluntary consent (Harmless Wrongdoing (New York, Oxford University Press, 1988), p. 176), and Wertheimer even claims that the exploited party benefits more than the exploiter does, and that this is the reason that the exploited party's bargaining position is so weak ('Two questions about surrogacy and exploitation', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 223). Allen Wood quotes the two and adds that people can often be eager to be exploited since 'being benefited and exploited are often merely two sides of the same coin, and people may often be in dire need of the benefits in question' (Wood, 'Exploitation', p. 149). In my view this attitude discounts the immorality of exploitation. The exploited one is exploited, but also benefits. But benefits in relation to what? Not in relation to his or her original status (the one prior to the new circumstances which have led to this exploitative exchange), but rather in relation to his new position. The exploiting party manipulates the exploited one to a position in which he is desperate, and then offers him a generous way out of it, namely by exploiting him. See, for instance, the example which Wood raises. A gambler who owes a large amount of money to ruthless and violent characters will be in desperate need of the loan from the shark who offers the needed funds at a usurious rate of interest. Such a person will be more than willing under these conditions to consent to virtually any terms of payment (Wood, 'Exploitation', p. 149). Shouldn't we consider also the dignity, self-esteem, etc., of the gambler? And does he continue to be in this position because he wants to?
    • Exploitation , pp. 149
    • Wood1
  • 51
    • 77449132121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The distinction between entering the situation of exploitative exchange and the absence of a way out of it is important for all theories of exploitation. Many authors regard exploitation as not necessarily involuntary. Joel Feinberg claims that exploitation may follow a voluntary consent (Harmless Wrongdoing (New York, Oxford University Press, 1988), p. 176), and Wertheimer even claims that the exploited party benefits more than the exploiter does, and that this is the reason that the exploited party's bargaining position is so weak ('Two questions about surrogacy and exploitation', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 223). Allen Wood quotes the two and adds that people can often be eager to be exploited since 'being benefited and exploited are often merely two sides of the same coin, and people may often be in dire need of the benefits in question' (Wood, 'Exploitation', p. 149). In my view this attitude discounts the immorality of exploitation. The exploited one is exploited, but also benefits. But benefits in relation to what? Not in relation to his or her original status (the one prior to the new circumstances which have led to this exploitative exchange), but rather in relation to his new position. The exploiting party manipulates the exploited one to a position in which he is desperate, and then offers him a generous way out of it, namely by exploiting him. See, for instance, the example which Wood raises. A gambler who owes a large amount of money to ruthless and violent characters will be in desperate need of the loan from the shark who offers the needed funds at a usurious rate of interest. Such a person will be more than willing under these conditions to consent to virtually any terms of payment (Wood, 'Exploitation', p. 149). Shouldn't we consider also the dignity, self-esteem, etc., of the gambler? And does he continue to be in this position because he wants to?
    • Exploitation , pp. 149
    • Wood1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.