메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 46, Issue 2, 1998, Pages 276-294

'Inevitable and unacceptable?' Methodological Rawlsianism in Anglo-American political philosophy

(1)  Norman, Wayne a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0039938974     PISSN: 00323217     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1467-9248.00140     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (17)

References (183)
  • 1
    • 84936020353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berkeley CA, University of California Press
    • B. Barry, Theories of Justice (Berkeley CA, University of California Press, 1989), pp. 257f.
    • (1989) Theories of Justice
    • Barry, B.1
  • 2
    • 0041934796 scopus 로고
    • Moral theories and received opinion
    • G. R. Grice, 'Moral theories and received opinion', Aristotelian Society, supp. 52 (1978), 1-12, p. 12.
    • (1978) Aristotelian Society , vol.1-12 , Issue.52 SUPPL. , pp. 12
    • Grice, G.R.1
  • 3
    • 0040339073 scopus 로고
    • Coherence and models for moral theorizing
    • The argument would require a laborious cataloguing of published works which nobody, as far as I am aware, has had the patience to carry out. Hunches about the pervasiveness of a vaguely Rawlsian methodological influence are, however, common. See, e.g., G. Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66 (1985), pp. 170, 176, 181, and D. Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', in Peter Singer (ed.), A Companion to Ethics (Oxford, Blackwell, 1991), p. 476, 481f, on Rawlsian coherentism; and R. Audi, 'Ethical reflectionism', The Monist, (1993), 295-315, on the appeal to intuitions.
    • (1985) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.66 , pp. 170
    • Sayre-McCord, G.1
  • 4
    • 0007242254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Method and moral theory
    • Peter Singer (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell
    • The argument would require a laborious cataloguing of published works which nobody, as far as I am aware, has had the patience to carry out. Hunches about the pervasiveness of a vaguely Rawlsian methodological influence are, however, common. See, e.g., G. Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66 (1985), pp. 170, 176, 181, and D. Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', in Peter Singer (ed.), A Companion to Ethics (Oxford, Blackwell, 1991), p. 476, 481f, on Rawlsian coherentism; and R. Audi, 'Ethical reflectionism', The Monist, (1993), 295-315, on the appeal to intuitions.
    • (1991) A Companion to Ethics , pp. 476
    • Jamieson, D.1
  • 5
    • 0040339074 scopus 로고
    • Ethical reflectionism
    • The argument would require a laborious cataloguing of published works which nobody, as far as I am aware, has had the patience to carry out. Hunches about the pervasiveness of a vaguely Rawlsian methodological influence are, however, common. See, e.g., G. Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66 (1985), pp. 170, 176, 181, and D. Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', in Peter Singer (ed.), A Companion to Ethics (Oxford, Blackwell, 1991), p. 476, 481f, on Rawlsian coherentism; and R. Audi, 'Ethical reflectionism', The Monist, (1993), 295-315, on the appeal to intuitions.
    • (1993) The Monist , pp. 295-315
    • Audi, R.1
  • 6
    • 0002037012 scopus 로고
    • Toward fin de siècle ethics; some trends
    • I take the mainstream to be represented by the great majority of articles in political philosophy published in journals like Ethics, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Social Philosophy and Policy, Political Studies, the Journal of Applied Philosophy and the Journal of Political Philosophy. I assert but do not here defend the claim that most writers in these journals are methodological Rawlsians. The method certainly has its detractors, even in the English-speaking world: on the one hand, there is a large minority of philosophers, such as Charles Taylor and Alasdair MacIntyre, who work within a more historical, continental tradition; and on the other, there is a (perhaps growing) contingent of 'foundationalists' who employ the tools of game theory, sociobiology and cognitive science in an attempt to ground personal and political morality in human nature and rational self-interest. For a comprehensive survey of this latter approach, see P. Railton, A. Gibbard, and S. Darwall, 'Toward fin de siècle ethics; some trends', Philosophical Review, 101 (1992).
    • (1992) Philosophical Review , vol.101
    • Railton, P.1    Gibbard, A.2    Darwall, S.3
  • 7
    • 77952487204 scopus 로고
    • Facing diversity: The case of epistemic abstinence
    • See J. Raz, 'Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 19 (1990), 3-46, for a critique of this kind of 'epistemic abstinence' in Rawls. For a sympathetic discussion of Raz's critique see J. Hampton, 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism', in D. Copp, J. Hampton and J. Roemer (eds), The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 293.
    • (1990) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.19 , pp. 3-46
    • Raz, J.1
  • 8
    • 0003284395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The moral commitments of liberalism
    • D. Copp, J. Hampton and J. Roemer (eds), Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
    • See J. Raz, 'Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 19 (1990), 3-46, for a critique of this kind of 'epistemic abstinence' in Rawls. For a sympathetic discussion of Raz's critique see J. Hampton, 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism', in D. Copp, J. Hampton and J. Roemer (eds), The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 293.
    • (1993) The Idea of Democracy , pp. 293
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 10
    • 84859701269 scopus 로고
    • Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism
    • M. DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', American Philosophical Quarterly, 23 (1986), 68. In this passage Michael DePaul is referring directly to the notion of reflective equilibrium which forms the core of what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism.
    • (1986) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.23 , pp. 68
    • DePaul, M.1
  • 11
    • 0039747089 scopus 로고
    • Carbondale IL, Southern Illinois University Press
    • See Carl Wellman, Challenge and Response: Justification in Ethics (Carbondale IL, Southern Illinois University Press, 1971), p. 132, on this distinction. For a general discussion of the process/ product distinction for several nouns ending in 'tion' and 'ment' see D.-H. Ruben, Explaining Explanation (London, Routledge, 1991), pp. 6-9.
    • (1971) Challenge and Response: Justification in Ethics , pp. 132
    • Wellman, C.1
  • 12
    • 0002081982 scopus 로고
    • London, Routledge
    • See Carl Wellman, Challenge and Response: Justification in Ethics (Carbondale IL, Southern Illinois University Press, 1971), p. 132, on this distinction. For a general discussion of the process/ product distinction for several nouns ending in 'tion' and 'ment' see D.-H. Ruben, Explaining Explanation (London, Routledge, 1991), pp. 6-9.
    • (1991) Explaining Explanation , pp. 6-9
    • Ruben, D.-H.1
  • 13
    • 0001501318 scopus 로고
    • Kantian constructivism in moral theory
    • J. Rawls, 'Kantian constructivism in moral theory', Journal of Philosophy, 77 (1980), p. 517.
    • (1980) Journal of Philosophy , vol.77 , pp. 517
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 14
    • 63849086576 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Oxford University Press
    • See J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972), p. 51n, where he cites a passage from H. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (London, Macmillan, 1907), pp. 373f. See also H. Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', Mind, 4 (1879), p. 109, for another rather Rawlsian moment. For a similar interpretation of Sidgwick's method see J. Schneewind, 'First principles and common sense morality in Sidgwick's ethics', Archiv für Geschichten der Philosophie, 45 (1963). The 'Rawlsian' interpretation of Sidgwick is disputed in P. Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', The Monist, 58 (1974), 490-517, and F. Snare, 'John Rawls and the methods of ethics', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 36 (1976), 100-12. Rawls makes no similar claims in his brief introduction to a recent edition of Sidgwick's The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis IN, Hackett, 1981), pp. v-vi. Singer is interpreting Rawls's methodology as a deep theory of justification, and finds convincing evidence that Sidgwick did not espouse the same deep theory. By Singer's own admission, however, Sidgwick does adopt an argument strategy that, I would argue, is consistent with what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism.
    • (1972) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 15
    • 0004255852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London, Macmillan
    • See J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972), p. 51n, where he cites a passage from H. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (London, Macmillan, 1907), pp. 373f. See also H. Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', Mind, 4 (1879), p. 109, for another rather Rawlsian moment. For a similar interpretation of Sidgwick's method see J. Schneewind, 'First principles and common sense morality in Sidgwick's ethics', Archiv für Geschichten der Philosophie, 45 (1963). The 'Rawlsian' interpretation of Sidgwick is disputed in P. Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', The Monist, 58 (1974), 490-517, and F. Snare, 'John Rawls and the methods of ethics', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 36 (1976), 100-12. Rawls makes no similar claims in his brief introduction to a recent edition of Sidgwick's The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis IN, Hackett, 1981), pp. v-vi. Singer is interpreting Rawls's methodology as a deep theory of justification, and finds convincing evidence that Sidgwick did not espouse the same deep theory. By Singer's own admission, however, Sidgwick does adopt an argument strategy that, I would argue, is consistent with what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism.
    • (1907) The Methods of Ethics
    • Sidgwick, H.1
  • 16
    • 0040933067 scopus 로고
    • The establishment of ethical first principles
    • See J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972), p. 51n, where he cites a passage from H. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (London, Macmillan, 1907), pp. 373f. See also H. Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', Mind, 4 (1879), p. 109, for another rather Rawlsian moment. For a similar interpretation of Sidgwick's method see J. Schneewind, 'First principles and common sense morality in Sidgwick's ethics', Archiv für Geschichten der Philosophie, 45 (1963). The 'Rawlsian' interpretation of Sidgwick is disputed in P. Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', The Monist, 58 (1974), 490-517, and F. Snare, 'John Rawls and the methods of ethics', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 36 (1976), 100-12. Rawls makes no similar claims in his brief introduction to a recent edition of Sidgwick's The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis IN, Hackett, 1981), pp. v-vi. Singer is interpreting Rawls's methodology as a deep theory of justification, and finds convincing evidence that Sidgwick did not espouse the same deep theory. By Singer's own admission, however, Sidgwick does adopt an argument strategy that, I would argue, is consistent with what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism.
    • (1879) Mind , vol.4 , pp. 109
    • Sidgwick, H.1
  • 17
    • 0039747085 scopus 로고
    • First principles and common sense morality in Sidgwick's ethics
    • See J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972), p. 51n, where he cites a passage from H. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (London, Macmillan, 1907), pp. 373f. See also H. Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', Mind, 4 (1879), p. 109, for another rather Rawlsian moment. For a similar interpretation of Sidgwick's method see J. Schneewind, 'First principles and common sense morality in Sidgwick's ethics', Archiv für Geschichten der Philosophie, 45 (1963). The 'Rawlsian' interpretation of Sidgwick is disputed in P. Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', The Monist, 58 (1974), 490-517, and F. Snare, 'John Rawls and the methods of ethics', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 36 (1976), 100-12. Rawls makes no similar claims in his brief introduction to a recent edition of Sidgwick's The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis IN, Hackett, 1981), pp. v-vi. Singer is interpreting Rawls's methodology as a deep theory of justification, and finds convincing evidence that Sidgwick did not espouse the same deep theory. By Singer's own admission, however, Sidgwick does adopt an argument strategy that, I would argue, is consistent with what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism.
    • (1963) Archiv für Geschichten der Philosophie , vol.45
    • Schneewind, J.1
  • 18
    • 0010135219 scopus 로고
    • Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium
    • See J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972), p. 51n, where he cites a passage from H. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (London, Macmillan, 1907), pp. 373f. See also H. Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', Mind, 4 (1879), p. 109, for another rather Rawlsian moment. For a similar interpretation of Sidgwick's method see J. Schneewind, 'First principles and common sense morality in Sidgwick's ethics', Archiv für Geschichten der Philosophie, 45 (1963). The 'Rawlsian' interpretation of Sidgwick is disputed in P. Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', The Monist, 58 (1974), 490-517, and F. Snare, 'John Rawls and the methods of ethics', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 36 (1976), 100-12. Rawls makes no similar claims in his brief introduction to a recent edition of Sidgwick's The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis IN, Hackett, 1981), pp. v-vi. Singer is interpreting Rawls's methodology as a deep theory of justification, and finds convincing evidence that Sidgwick did not espouse the same deep theory. By Singer's own admission, however, Sidgwick does adopt an argument strategy that, I would argue, is consistent with what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism.
    • (1974) The Monist , vol.58 , pp. 490-517
    • Singer, P.1
  • 19
    • 0040933064 scopus 로고
    • John rawls and the methods of ethics
    • See J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972), p. 51n, where he cites a passage from H. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (London, Macmillan, 1907), pp. 373f. See also H. Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', Mind, 4 (1879), p. 109, for another rather Rawlsian moment. For a similar interpretation of Sidgwick's method see J. Schneewind, 'First principles and common sense morality in Sidgwick's ethics', Archiv für Geschichten der Philosophie, 45 (1963). The 'Rawlsian' interpretation of Sidgwick is disputed in P. Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', The Monist, 58 (1974), 490-517, and F. Snare, 'John Rawls and the methods of ethics', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 36 (1976), 100-12. Rawls makes no similar claims in his brief introduction to a recent edition of Sidgwick's The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis IN, Hackett, 1981), pp. v-vi. Singer is interpreting Rawls's methodology as a deep theory of justification, and finds convincing evidence that Sidgwick did not espouse the same deep theory. By Singer's own admission, however, Sidgwick does adopt an argument strategy that, I would argue, is consistent with what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism.
    • (1976) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.36 , pp. 100-112
    • Snare, F.1
  • 20
    • 0004255852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis IN, Hackett
    • See J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972), p. 51n, where he cites a passage from H. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (London, Macmillan, 1907), pp. 373f. See also H. Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', Mind, 4 (1879), p. 109, for another rather Rawlsian moment. For a similar interpretation of Sidgwick's method see J. Schneewind, 'First principles and common sense morality in Sidgwick's ethics', Archiv für Geschichten der Philosophie, 45 (1963). The 'Rawlsian' interpretation of Sidgwick is disputed in P. Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', The Monist, 58 (1974), 490-517, and F. Snare, 'John Rawls and the methods of ethics', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 36 (1976), 100-12. Rawls makes no similar claims in his brief introduction to a recent edition of Sidgwick's The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis IN, Hackett, 1981), pp. v-vi. Singer is interpreting Rawls's methodology as a deep theory of justification, and finds convincing evidence that Sidgwick did not espouse the same deep theory. By Singer's own admission, however, Sidgwick does adopt an argument strategy that, I would argue, is consistent with what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism.
    • (1981) The Methods of Ethics
    • Sidgwick1
  • 21
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 51n. Hampshire and Grice also find the roots of this method in Aristotle. See S. Hampshire, Two Theories of Morality (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 5; and G. R. Grice, 'Moral theories and received opinion', p. 11.
    • A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls1
  • 22
    • 0009414062 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Oxford University Press
    • See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 51n. Hampshire and Grice also find the roots of this method in Aristotle. See S. Hampshire, Two Theories of Morality (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 5; and G. R. Grice, 'Moral theories and received opinion', p. 11.
    • (1977) Two Theories of Morality , pp. 5
    • Hampshire, S.1
  • 23
    • 0039154646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 51n. Hampshire and Grice also find the roots of this method in Aristotle. See S. Hampshire, Two Theories of Morality (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 5; and G. R. Grice, 'Moral theories and received opinion', p. 11.
    • Moral Theories and Received Opinion , pp. 11
    • Grice, G.R.1
  • 24
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 49. See also K. Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', Analyse & Kritik, 13 (1991); K. Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy: contextualist justice and wide reflective equilibrium', Queen's Law Journal, 20 (1994), 101-5; and R. Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', in A. Malachowski (ed.), Reading Rorty (Oxford, Blackwell, 1990), p. 291.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 49
    • Rawls1
  • 25
    • 85055407012 scopus 로고
    • Rawls and the socratic ideal
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 49. See also K. Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', Analyse & Kritik, 13 (1991); K. Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy: contextualist justice and wide reflective equilibrium', Queen's Law Journal, 20 (1994), 101-5; and R. Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', in A. Malachowski (ed.), Reading Rorty (Oxford, Blackwell, 1990), p. 291.
    • (1991) Analyse & Kritik , vol.13
    • Nielsen, K.1
  • 26
    • 0040933061 scopus 로고
    • How to proceed in social philosophy: Contextualist justice and wide reflective equilibrium
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 49. See also K. Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', Analyse & Kritik, 13 (1991); K. Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy: contextualist justice and wide reflective equilibrium', Queen's Law Journal, 20 (1994), 101-5; and R. Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', in A. Malachowski (ed.), Reading Rorty (Oxford, Blackwell, 1990), p. 291.
    • (1994) Queen's Law Journal , vol.20 , pp. 101-105
    • Nielsen, K.1
  • 27
    • 0006963490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The priority of democracy to philosophy
    • A. Malachowski (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 49. See also K. Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', Analyse & Kritik, 13 (1991); K. Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy: contextualist justice and wide reflective equilibrium', Queen's Law Journal, 20 (1994), 101-5; and R. Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', in A. Malachowski (ed.), Reading Rorty (Oxford, Blackwell, 1990), p. 291.
    • (1990) Reading Rorty , pp. 291
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 28
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both David Lyons and Barry question whether Rawls's practice is consistent with his methodological pronouncements, even in A Theory of Justice. See D. Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', in N. Daniels (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 141-67: and Barry, Theories of Justice, pp. 278-82. Barry thinks that Rawls' actual practice in A Theory of Justice and later is best understood in terms of the method of constructivism, 'in spite of recurrent intrusions by the methodological claims first made [by Rawls] in [J. Rawls, "Outline of a decision procedure for ethics", Philosophical Review, 60 (1951), 177-97]'. Constructivism, according to Barry, is 'dependent on but not reducible to intuitionism' (Theories of Justice, p. 282). (By 'intuitionism' here, I believe he means reflective equilibrium, the central feature of methodological Rawlsianism.) The question of whether Rawls is a consistent methodological Rawlsian will depend on how loosely the method is characterized. Rawls himself, as we shall see, has several ways of describing the method, some of which are not at all incompatible with constructivism.
    • A Theory of Justice
  • 29
    • 60949364193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • N. Daniels (ed.), Reading Rawls New York NY, Basic
    • Both David Lyons and Barry question whether Rawls's practice is consistent with his methodological pronouncements, even in A Theory of Justice. See D. Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', in N. Daniels (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 141-67: and Barry, Theories of Justice, pp. 278-82. Barry thinks that Rawls' actual practice in A Theory of Justice and later is best understood in terms of the method of constructivism, 'in spite of recurrent intrusions by the methodological claims first made [by Rawls] in [J. Rawls, "Outline of a decision procedure for ethics", Philosophical Review, 60 (1951), 177-97]'. Constructivism, according to Barry, is 'dependent on but not reducible to intuitionism' (Theories of Justice, p. 282). (By 'intuitionism' here, I believe he means reflective equilibrium, the central feature of methodological Rawlsianism.) The question of whether Rawls is a consistent methodological Rawlsian will depend on how loosely the method is characterized. Rawls himself, as we shall see, has several ways of describing the method, some of which are not at all incompatible with constructivism.
    • (1975) Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments , pp. 141-167
    • Lyons, D.1
  • 30
    • 84936020353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both David Lyons and Barry question whether Rawls's practice is consistent with his methodological pronouncements, even in A Theory of Justice. See D. Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', in N. Daniels (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 141-67: and Barry, Theories of Justice, pp. 278-82. Barry thinks that Rawls' actual practice in A Theory of Justice and later is best understood in terms of the method of constructivism, 'in spite of recurrent intrusions by the methodological claims first made [by Rawls] in [J. Rawls, "Outline of a decision procedure for ethics", Philosophical Review, 60 (1951), 177-97]'. Constructivism, according to Barry, is 'dependent on but not reducible to intuitionism' (Theories of Justice, p. 282). (By 'intuitionism' here, I believe he means reflective equilibrium, the central feature of methodological Rawlsianism.) The question of whether Rawls is a consistent methodological Rawlsian will depend on how loosely the method is characterized. Rawls himself, as we shall see, has several ways of describing the method, some of which are not at all incompatible with constructivism.
    • Theories of Justice , pp. 278-282
    • Barry1
  • 31
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both David Lyons and Barry question whether Rawls's practice is consistent with his methodological pronouncements, even in A Theory of Justice. See D. Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', in N. Daniels (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 141-67: and Barry, Theories of Justice, pp. 278-82. Barry thinks that Rawls' actual practice in A Theory of Justice and later is best understood in terms of the method of constructivism, 'in spite of recurrent intrusions by the methodological claims first made [by Rawls] in [J. Rawls, "Outline of a decision procedure for ethics", Philosophical Review, 60 (1951), 177-97]'. Constructivism, according to Barry, is 'dependent on but not reducible to intuitionism' (Theories of Justice, p. 282). (By 'intuitionism' here, I believe he means reflective equilibrium, the central feature of methodological Rawlsianism.) The question of whether Rawls is a consistent methodological Rawlsian will depend on how loosely the method is characterized. Rawls himself, as we shall see, has several ways of describing the method, some of which are not at all incompatible with constructivism.
    • A Theory of Justice
  • 32
    • 0001333853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Outline of a decision procedure for ethics
    • Both David Lyons and Barry question whether Rawls's practice is consistent with his methodological pronouncements, even in A Theory of Justice. See D. Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', in N. Daniels (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 141-67: and Barry, Theories of Justice, pp. 278-82. Barry thinks that Rawls' actual practice in A Theory of Justice and later is best understood in terms of the method of constructivism, 'in spite of recurrent intrusions by the methodological claims first made [by Rawls] in [J. Rawls, "Outline of a decision procedure for ethics", Philosophical Review, 60 (1951), 177-97]'. Constructivism, according to Barry, is 'dependent on but not reducible to intuitionism' (Theories of Justice, p. 282). (By 'intuitionism' here, I believe he means reflective equilibrium, the central feature of methodological Rawlsianism.) The question of whether Rawls is a consistent methodological Rawlsian will depend on how loosely the method is characterized. Rawls himself, as we shall see, has several ways of describing the method, some of which are not at all incompatible with constructivism.
    • (1951) Philosophical Review , vol.60 , pp. 177-197
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 33
    • 84936020353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both David Lyons and Barry question whether Rawls's practice is consistent with his methodological pronouncements, even in A Theory of Justice. See D. Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', in N. Daniels (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 141-67: and Barry, Theories of Justice, pp. 278-82. Barry thinks that Rawls' actual practice in A Theory of Justice and later is best understood in terms of the method of constructivism, 'in spite of recurrent intrusions by the methodological claims first made [by Rawls] in [J. Rawls, "Outline of a decision procedure for ethics", Philosophical Review, 60 (1951), 177-97]'. Constructivism, according to Barry, is 'dependent on but not reducible to intuitionism' (Theories of Justice, p. 282). (By 'intuitionism' here, I believe he means reflective equilibrium, the central feature of methodological Rawlsianism.) The question of whether Rawls is a consistent methodological Rawlsian will depend on how loosely the method is characterized. Rawls himself, as we shall see, has several ways of describing the method, some of which are not at all incompatible with constructivism.
    • Theories of Justice , pp. 282
  • 34
    • 85033873000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are vastly more methodological than substantive Rawlsians, so this is arguably Rawls's most enduring legacy
    • There are vastly more methodological than substantive Rawlsians, so this is arguably Rawls's most enduring legacy.
  • 35
    • 84935547375 scopus 로고
    • Justice as fairness: Political not metaphysical
    • Contemporary debates about political liberalism were launched by J. Rawls, 'Justice as fairness: political not metaphysical', Philosophy and Public Affair, 14 (1985). See C. Larmore, 'Political liberalism', Political Theory, 18 (1990), 339-60, for an analysis of these debates.
    • (1985) Philosophy and Public Affair , vol.14
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 36
    • 84972623105 scopus 로고
    • Political liberalism
    • Contemporary debates about political liberalism were launched by J. Rawls, 'Justice as fairness: political not metaphysical', Philosophy and Public Affair, 14 (1985). See C. Larmore, 'Political liberalism', Political Theory, 18 (1990), 339-60, for an analysis of these debates.
    • (1990) Political Theory , vol.18 , pp. 339-360
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 37
    • 84928849215 scopus 로고
    • Justice and the aims of political philosophy
    • See K. Baier, 'Justice and the aims of political philosophy', Ethics, 99 (1989), p. 781 on the relation between ethics and political philosophy in Rawls's recent work.
    • (1989) Ethics , vol.99 , pp. 781
    • Baier, K.1
  • 38
    • 84974082107 scopus 로고
    • The power of example
    • O. O'Neill, 'The power of example', Philosophy, 61 (1986), p. 5.
    • (1986) Philosophy , vol.61 , pp. 5
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 40
    • 84928439850 scopus 로고
    • Taking "free action" too seriously
    • For a case against their even being of much instrumental value for normative political theory, see W. Norman, Taking Freedom Too Seriously? An Essay on Analytic and Post-Analytic Political Philosophy (New York, Garland, 1991), and 'Taking "free action" too seriously', Ethics, 101 (1991), 505-20.
    • (1991) Ethics , vol.101 , pp. 505-520
  • 41
    • 0038305074 scopus 로고
    • Paris, Seuil
    • Scholarship and polemic seem so deeply entrenched in Franco-German circles of political philosophy that the Belgian methodological Rawlsian, Philippe van Parijs, felt it necessary to begin his recent introductory text with the bold assertion that 'L'invective et l'exégèse ne sont pas les seuls registres de la philosophie politique' (P. van Parijs, Qu'est-ce qu'une société juste? (Paris, Seuil, 1991), p. 9). For a brief plea in favour of what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism, directed at continental philosophers, see P. van Parijs, 'Bref plaidoyer pour la philosophie politique, manière Anglo-Saxonne', Revue de métaphysique et de morale, (1988), 69-79.
    • (1991) Qu'est-ce Qu'une Société Juste? , pp. 9
    • Van Parijs, P.1
  • 42
    • 85033892931 scopus 로고
    • Bref plaidoyer pour la philosophie politique, manière Anglo-Saxonne
    • Scholarship and polemic seem so deeply entrenched in Franco-German circles of political philosophy that the Belgian methodological Rawlsian, Philippe van Parijs, felt it necessary to begin his recent introductory text with the bold assertion that 'L'invective et l'exégèse ne sont pas les seuls registres de la philosophie politique' (P. van Parijs, Qu'est-ce qu'une société juste? (Paris, Seuil, 1991), p. 9). For a brief plea in favour of what I am calling methodological Rawlsianism, directed at continental philosophers, see P. van Parijs, 'Bref plaidoyer pour la philosophie politique, manière Anglo-Saxonne', Revue de métaphysique et de morale, (1988), 69-79.
    • (1988) Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale , pp. 69-79
    • Van Parijs, P.1
  • 43
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 580f. See also J. Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York NY, Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 100; and C. Perelman, Justice (New York, Random House, 1967), p. 64.
    • A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls1
  • 44
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York NY, Columbia University Press
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 580f. See also J. Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York NY, Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 100; and C. Perelman, Justice (New York, Random House, 1967), p. 64.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 100
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 45
    • 0039747086 scopus 로고
    • New York, Random House
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 580f. See also J. Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York NY, Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 100; and C. Perelman, Justice (New York, Random House, 1967), p. 64.
    • (1967) Justice , pp. 64
    • Perelman, C.1
  • 46
    • 0040933065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer calls this an ad hominem argument (a usage at odds with the standard definition in informal logic texts), and notes that it is widely used by Sidgwick (Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', pp. 495-509). In this sense, Sidgwick wrote like a methodological Rawlsian, which is tantamount to saying he was one, at least much of the time. The same might be said of J. S. Mill, who went to great lengths to employ arguments to lead his conservative readers to his liberal conclusions, and of many other non-dogmatic writers in the history of political thought.
    • Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium , pp. 495-509
    • Singer1
  • 47
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 21
    • Rawls1
  • 48
    • 0003778425 scopus 로고
    • New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • (1991) Conversations with Isaiah Berlin , pp. 32
    • Berlin, I.1
  • 49
    • 0006963490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy , pp. 291
    • Rorty1
  • 50
    • 0001333853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics , pp. 177
    • Rawls1
  • 51
    • 0040339068 scopus 로고
    • Wittgenstein, rawls and conservatism
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • (1994) Philosophy and Social Criticism , vol.20 , pp. 29
    • Cladis, M.1
  • 52
    • 2842528961 scopus 로고
    • Retlective equilibrium and archimedean points
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • (1980) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.10 , pp. 102
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 53
    • 0000625557 scopus 로고
    • Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • (1979) Journal of Philosophy , vol.76 , pp. 256
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 54
    • 61249312850 scopus 로고
    • Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • (1993) The Monist , pp. 323
    • Nielsen, K.1
  • 55
    • 85033883379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • How to Proceed in Social Philosophy , pp. 323
    • Nielsen1
  • 56
    • 0007242254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • Method and Moral Theory , pp. 482
    • Jamieson1
  • 57
    • 0040339070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • Coherence and Models for Moral Theorizing , pp. 176
    • Sayre-McCord1
  • 58
    • 0009366417 scopus 로고
    • The original position
    • N. Daniels, (ed.), New York NY, Basic
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • (1975) Reading Rawls , pp. 27-37
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 59
    • 84937576730 scopus 로고
    • The claims of reflective equilibrium
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • (1982) Inquiry , vol.25 , pp. 308
    • Raz, J.1
  • 60
    • 0040933053 scopus 로고
    • Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?
    • 'A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.' (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21; see Isaiah Berlin, Conversations with Isaiah Berlin (New York NY, Charles Scribner's Sons, 1991), p. 32). Richard Rorty and Kai Nielsen are strong supporters both of this interpretation of Rawls and of this pragmatic view of justification more generally. See Rorty. 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal', and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'. Others interpret Rawls as being neutral about the prospects of deeper foundations (see, e.g., Rawls, 'Outline of a decision procedure for ethics', p. 177; M. Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', Philosophy and Social Criticism, 20 (1994), p. 29). It is widely granted that Rawls has a coherentist, anti-foundationalist theory of justification. See, e.g., N. Daniels, 'Retlective equilibrium and Archimedean points', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1980), p. 102; N. Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), p. 256; K. Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', The Monist, (1993), p. 323; Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 323; Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 482; Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing', p. 176; R. Dworkin, 'The Original Position', in N. Daniels, (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York NY, Basic, 1975), pp. 27-37; J. Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', Inquiry, 25 (1982), 308. Not surprisingly, the critical literature makes room for a 'moderate foundationalist' interpretation of Rawls in R. Ebertz, 'Is reflective equilibrium a coherentist model?', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23 (1993), 193-214. I am sympathetic with Michael DePaul's view that the justificatory model in Rawls, on the one hand, and the kinds of epistemic theories in the foundationalism/coherentism debate, on the other, 'are not really positions on the same topic, although they are surely positions on related topics' (DePaul, 'Reflective equilibrium and foundationalism', p. 68).
    • (1993) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.23 , pp. 193-214
    • Ebertz, R.1
  • 62
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 50. This claim is disputed by Raz in 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', pp. 314f.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 50
    • Rawls1
  • 63
    • 0039747067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Wellman (Challenge and Response, p. 138) one needs to justify only when one is challenged, and '[m]eeting a challenge is responding to it in a way that would, after indefinite criticism, cause any normal person to withdraw that challenge'. See also T. Scanlon, 'Contractualism and Utilitarianism', in A. Sen and B. Williams (eds), Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1982).
    • Challenge and Response , pp. 138
    • Wellman1
  • 64
    • 0002000290 scopus 로고
    • Contractualism and utilitarianism
    • A. Sen and B. Williams (eds), Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
    • According to Wellman (Challenge and Response, p. 138) one needs to justify only when one is challenged, and '[m]eeting a challenge is responding to it in a way that would, after indefinite criticism, cause any normal person to withdraw that challenge'. See also T. Scanlon, 'Contractualism and Utilitarianism', in A. Sen and B. Williams (eds), Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1982).
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and Beyond
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 65
    • 77955125591 scopus 로고
    • What basis for morality? A minimalist approach
    • See S. Bok, 'What basis for morality? A minimalist approach', The Monist, (1993), p. 353; David Miller and G. Klosko argue that Rawlsians should use empirical studies to discover what moral and political beliefs are actually shared. See D. Miller, 'Review of K. R. Scherer (ed.), Justice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives', Social Justice Research, 7 (1994), 171-181; D. Miller, 'Distributive justice: What the people think?', Ethics, 102/3 (1992); and G. Klosko, 'Rawls' "political" philosophy and American democracy', American Political Science Review, 87 (1993), p. 184.
    • (1993) The Monist , pp. 353
    • Bok, S.1
  • 66
    • 85033902551 scopus 로고
    • Review of K. R. Scherer (ed.)
    • See S. Bok, 'What basis for morality? A minimalist approach', The Monist, (1993), p. 353; David Miller and G. Klosko argue that Rawlsians should use empirical studies to discover what moral and political beliefs are actually shared. See D. Miller, 'Review of K. R. Scherer (ed.), Justice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives', Social Justice Research, 7 (1994), 171-181; D. Miller, 'Distributive justice: What the people think?', Ethics, 102/3 (1992); and G. Klosko, 'Rawls' "political" philosophy and American democracy', American Political Science Review, 87 (1993), p. 184.
    • (1994) Justice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives, Social Justice Research , vol.7 , pp. 171-181
    • Miller, D.1
  • 67
    • 84934564113 scopus 로고
    • Distributive justice: What the people think?
    • See S. Bok, 'What basis for morality? A minimalist approach', The Monist, (1993), p. 353; David Miller and G. Klosko argue that Rawlsians should use empirical studies to discover what moral and political beliefs are actually shared. See D. Miller, 'Review of K. R. Scherer (ed.), Justice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives', Social Justice Research, 7 (1994), 171-181; D. Miller, 'Distributive justice: What the people think?', Ethics, 102/3 (1992); and G. Klosko, 'Rawls' "political" philosophy and American democracy', American Political Science Review, 87 (1993), p. 184.
    • (1992) Ethics , vol.102 , Issue.3
    • Miller, D.1
  • 68
    • 0000460954 scopus 로고
    • 'Rawls' "political" philosophy and american democracy
    • See S. Bok, 'What basis for morality? A minimalist approach', The Monist, (1993), p. 353; David Miller and G. Klosko argue that Rawlsians should use empirical studies to discover what moral and political beliefs are actually shared. See D. Miller, 'Review of K. R. Scherer (ed.), Justice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives', Social Justice Research, 7 (1994), 171-181; D. Miller, 'Distributive justice: What the people think?', Ethics, 102/3 (1992); and G. Klosko, 'Rawls' "political" philosophy and American democracy', American Political Science Review, 87 (1993), p. 184.
    • (1993) American Political Science Review , vol.87 , pp. 184
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 70
    • 84875609191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, for example, assumes that moral knowledge is accessible to every person who is normally reasonable and conscientious, and that we have in our nature sufficient motives to lead us to act as we ought without the need of external threats and inducements (Political Liberalism, pp. xxvi-xxvii). Hence, moral theories are 'commonly regarded as abstract structures whose role is to supply justification rather than motivation' (Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 476).
    • Political Liberalism
  • 71
    • 0007242254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, for example, assumes that moral knowledge is accessible to every person who is normally reasonable and conscientious, and that we have in our nature sufficient motives to lead us to act as we ought without the need of external threats and inducements (Political Liberalism, pp. xxvi-xxvii). Hence, moral theories are 'commonly regarded as abstract structures whose role is to supply justification rather than motivation' (Jamieson, 'Method and Moral Theory', p. 476).
    • Method and Moral Theory , pp. 476
    • Jamieson1
  • 72
    • 0039747083 scopus 로고
    • Is "why should I be moral?" An absurdity?
    • This last assumption is so widely shared amongst methodological Rawlsians that I doubt many have even questioned it. In the heyday of linguistic analysis and meta-ethics, during the 1950s, philosophers did discuss the question 'Why be moral?'. But in the end most found it to be deceptively uninteresting, perhaps even meaningless: proffering moral reasons for being moral would be circular; and wholly self-interested reasons for being moral would be inappropriate, since the question 'Why be moral?' is only germane in cases when being moral is not to one's advantage. See, e.g., K. Nielsen, 'Is "why should I be moral?" an absurdity?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 36 (1958). Of course, such analytic arguments are wholly irrelevant to the much more complex project of trying to provide an evolutionary or game-theoretic explanation for the emergence of moral norms among rational agents - see D. Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1986); T. Scanlon, 'Moral theory: understanding and disagreement', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55 (1995), 346f; and K. Nielsen, 'Justice as a kind of impartiality', Laval théologique et philosophique, 50 (1994), p. 527. Methodological Rawlsians do not, for the most part, engage in this project (cp. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 503); but they need not deny its importance to various meta-ethical issues.
    • (1958) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.36
    • Nielsen, K.1
  • 73
    • 0004274311 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Oxford University Press
    • This last assumption is so widely shared amongst methodological Rawlsians that I doubt many have even questioned it. In the heyday of linguistic analysis and meta-ethics, during the 1950s, philosophers did discuss the question 'Why be moral?'. But in the end most found it to be deceptively uninteresting, perhaps even meaningless: proffering moral reasons for being moral would be circular; and wholly self-interested reasons for being moral would be inappropriate, since the question 'Why be moral?' is only germane in cases when being moral is not to one's advantage. See, e.g., K. Nielsen, 'Is "why should I be moral?" an absurdity?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 36 (1958). Of course, such analytic arguments are wholly irrelevant to the much more complex project of trying to provide an evolutionary or game-theoretic explanation for the emergence of moral norms among rational agents - see D. Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1986); T. Scanlon, 'Moral theory: understanding and disagreement', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55 (1995), 346f; and K. Nielsen, 'Justice as a kind of impartiality', Laval théologique et philosophique, 50 (1994), p. 527. Methodological Rawlsians do not, for the most part, engage in this project (cp. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 503); but they need not deny its importance to various meta-ethical issues.
    • (1986) Morals by Agreement
    • Gauthier, D.1
  • 74
    • 4243940466 scopus 로고
    • Moral theory: Understanding and disagreement
    • This last assumption is so widely shared amongst methodological Rawlsians that I doubt many have even questioned it. In the heyday of linguistic analysis and meta-ethics, during the 1950s, philosophers did discuss the question 'Why be moral?'. But in the end most found it to be deceptively uninteresting, perhaps even meaningless: proffering moral reasons for being moral would be circular; and wholly self-interested reasons for being moral would be inappropriate, since the question 'Why be moral?' is only germane in cases when being moral is not to one's advantage. See, e.g., K. Nielsen, 'Is "why should I be moral?" an absurdity?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 36 (1958). Of course, such analytic arguments are wholly irrelevant to the much more complex project of trying to provide an evolutionary or game-theoretic explanation for the emergence of moral norms among rational agents - see D. Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1986); T. Scanlon, 'Moral theory: understanding and disagreement', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55 (1995), 346f; and K. Nielsen, 'Justice as a kind of impartiality', Laval théologique et philosophique, 50 (1994), p. 527. Methodological Rawlsians do not, for the most part, engage in this project (cp. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 503); but they need not deny its importance to various meta-ethical issues.
    • (1995) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.55
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 75
    • 84894934941 scopus 로고
    • Justice as a kind of impartiality
    • This last assumption is so widely shared amongst methodological Rawlsians that I doubt many have even questioned it. In the heyday of linguistic analysis and meta-ethics, during the 1950s, philosophers did discuss the question 'Why be moral?'. But in the end most found it to be deceptively uninteresting, perhaps even meaningless: proffering moral reasons for being moral would be circular; and wholly self-interested reasons for being moral would be inappropriate, since the question 'Why be moral?' is only germane in cases when being moral is not to one's advantage. See, e.g., K. Nielsen, 'Is "why should I be moral?" an absurdity?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 36 (1958). Of course, such analytic arguments are wholly irrelevant to the much more complex project of trying to provide an evolutionary or game-theoretic explanation for the emergence of moral norms among rational agents - see D. Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1986); T. Scanlon, 'Moral theory: understanding and disagreement', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55 (1995), 346f; and K. Nielsen, 'Justice as a kind of impartiality', Laval théologique et philosophique, 50 (1994), p. 527. Methodological Rawlsians do not, for the most part, engage in this project (cp. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 503); but they need not deny its importance to various meta-ethical issues.
    • (1994) Laval Théologique et Philosophique , vol.50 , pp. 527
    • Nielsen, K.1
  • 76
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This last assumption is so widely shared amongst methodological Rawlsians that I doubt many have even questioned it. In the heyday of linguistic analysis and meta-ethics, during the 1950s, philosophers did discuss the question 'Why be moral?'. But in the end most found it to be deceptively uninteresting, perhaps even meaningless: proffering moral reasons for being moral would be circular; and wholly self-interested reasons for being moral would be inappropriate, since the question 'Why be moral?' is only germane in cases when being moral is not to one's advantage. See, e.g., K. Nielsen, 'Is "why should I be moral?" an absurdity?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 36 (1958). Of course, such analytic arguments are wholly irrelevant to the much more complex project of trying to provide an evolutionary or game-theoretic explanation for the emergence of moral norms among rational agents - see D. Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1986); T. Scanlon, 'Moral theory: understanding and disagreement', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55 (1995), 346f; and K. Nielsen, 'Justice as a kind of impartiality', Laval théologique et philosophique, 50 (1994), p. 527. Methodological Rawlsians do not, for the most part, engage in this project (cp. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 503); but they need not deny its importance to various meta-ethical issues.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 503
    • Rawls1
  • 78
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, he makes this claim about the contractual representation of 'weak premises' in the original position.
    • A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls1
  • 79
    • 0004123120 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Clarendon
    • See, e.g., R. M. Hare, Freedom and Reason (Oxford, Clarendon, 1963), and J. Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, (Cambridge MA, MIT Press, 1990), trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen and Christian Lenhardt.
    • (1963) Freedom and Reason
    • Hare, R.M.1
  • 80
    • 0003807937 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge MA, MIT Press, trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen and Christian Lenhardt
    • See, e.g., R. M. Hare, Freedom and Reason (Oxford, Clarendon, 1963), and J. Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, (Cambridge MA, MIT Press, 1990), trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen and Christian Lenhardt.
    • (1990) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 83
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By 'speculative' the methodological Rawlsian has in mind theories that are unfalsifiable, practically impossible to test, or which are opposed by many leading experts in the relevant fields. I should think that much of the social, psychoanalytic and linguistic theory cited by Habermas falls into this category. So might the social-psychological theories of Kohlberg used by both Habermas and the earlier Rawls. More recently Rawls has been willing to exclude appeal even to 'elaborate economic theories of general equilibrium' (Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 225). Note that this maxim can be embraced by philosophers who hold strong views on these controversial subjects. See, e.g., Kent Greenawalt's arguments for why his fellow believers should nevertheless avoid appealing to religious premises in most public debates, in K. Greenawalt, Religious Convictions and Political Choice (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1988).
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 225
    • Rawls1
  • 84
    • 0003547455 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Oxford University Press
    • By 'speculative' the methodological Rawlsian has in mind theories that are unfalsifiable, practically impossible to test, or which are opposed by many leading experts in the relevant fields. I should think that much of the social, psychoanalytic and linguistic theory cited by Habermas falls into this category. So might the social-psychological theories of Kohlberg used by both Habermas and the earlier Rawls. More recently Rawls has been willing to exclude appeal even to 'elaborate economic theories of general equilibrium' (Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 225). Note that this maxim can be embraced by philosophers who hold strong views on these controversial subjects. See, e.g., Kent Greenawalt's arguments for why his fellow believers should nevertheless avoid appealing to religious premises in most public debates, in K. Greenawalt, Religious Convictions and Political Choice (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1988).
    • (1988) Religious Convictions and Political Choice
    • Greenawalt, K.1
  • 85
    • 85033885519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 90. A sceptical colleague, Hilliard Aronovitch, asks whether they travel light in order to make a quick getaway.
    • How to Proceed in Social Philosophy , pp. 90
  • 86
    • 0039154638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Raz, Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence'; J. Hampton, 'Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics?', Ethics, 99/4 (1989), and 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism'; S. Scheffler, 'Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and polities', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 318. Rawls denies these charges (Political Liberalism, pp. 10, 95) and Kai Nielsen has made something of a crusade on Rawls's behalf. See, e.g., Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', pp. 101-7, where he replies directly to Hampton's critique. See also Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', p. 29; and Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291.
    • Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence
    • Raz1
  • 87
    • 84929066602 scopus 로고
    • Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics?
    • See, e.g., Raz, Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence'; J. Hampton, 'Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics?', Ethics, 99/4 (1989), and 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism'; S. Scheffler, 'Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and polities', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 318. Rawls denies these charges (Political Liberalism, pp. 10, 95) and Kai Nielsen has made something of a crusade on Rawls's behalf. See, e.g., Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', pp. 101-7, where he replies directly to Hampton's critique. See also Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', p. 29; and Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291.
    • (1989) Ethics , vol.99 , Issue.4
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 88
    • 85033885245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Raz, Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence'; J. Hampton, 'Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics?', Ethics, 99/4 (1989), and 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism'; S. Scheffler, 'Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and polities', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 318. Rawls denies these charges (Political Liberalism, pp. 10, 95) and Kai Nielsen has made something of a crusade on Rawls's behalf. See, e.g., Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', pp. 101-7, where he replies directly to Hampton's critique. See also Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', p. 29; and Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291.
    • The Moral Commitments of Liberalism
  • 89
    • 84880884624 scopus 로고
    • Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and polities
    • See, e.g., Raz, Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence'; J. Hampton, 'Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics?', Ethics, 99/4 (1989), and 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism'; S. Scheffler, 'Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and polities', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 318. Rawls denies these charges (Political Liberalism, pp. 10, 95) and Kai Nielsen has made something of a crusade on Rawls's behalf. See, e.g., Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', pp. 101-7, where he replies directly to Hampton's critique. See also Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', p. 29; and Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291.
    • (1992) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.21 , pp. 318
    • Scheffler, S.1
  • 90
    • 84875609191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Raz, Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence'; J. Hampton, 'Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics?', Ethics, 99/4 (1989), and 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism'; S. Scheffler, 'Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and polities', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 318. Rawls denies these charges (Political Liberalism, pp. 10, 95) and Kai Nielsen has made something of a crusade on Rawls's behalf. See, e.g., Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', pp. 101-7, where he replies directly to Hampton's critique. See also Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', p. 29; and Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291.
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 10
  • 91
    • 85033883379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Raz, Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence'; J. Hampton, 'Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics?', Ethics, 99/4 (1989), and 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism'; S. Scheffler, 'Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and polities', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 318. Rawls denies these charges (Political Liberalism, pp. 10, 95) and Kai Nielsen has made something of a crusade on Rawls's behalf. See, e.g., Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', pp. 101-7, where he replies directly to Hampton's critique. See also Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', p. 29; and Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291.
    • How to Proceed in Social Philosophy , pp. 101-107
    • Nielsen1
  • 92
    • 85033884986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Raz, Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence'; J. Hampton, 'Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics?', Ethics, 99/4 (1989), and 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism'; S. Scheffler, 'Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and polities', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 318. Rawls denies these charges (Political Liberalism, pp. 10, 95) and Kai Nielsen has made something of a crusade on Rawls's behalf. See, e.g., Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', pp. 101-7, where he replies directly to Hampton's critique. See also Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', p. 29; and Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291.
    • Wittgenstein, Rawls and Conservatism , pp. 29
    • Cladis1
  • 93
    • 0006963490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Raz, Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence'; J. Hampton, 'Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics?', Ethics, 99/4 (1989), and 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism'; S. Scheffler, 'Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and polities', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21 (1992), p. 318. Rawls denies these charges (Political Liberalism, pp. 10, 95) and Kai Nielsen has made something of a crusade on Rawls's behalf. See, e.g., Nielsen, 'How to proceed in social philosophy', pp. 101-7, where he replies directly to Hampton's critique. See also Cladis, 'Wittgenstein, Rawls and conservatism', p. 29; and Rorty, 'The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy', p. 291.
    • The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy , pp. 291
    • Rorty1
  • 94
    • 0039747067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As will become clear in my discussion of 'reflective equilibrium', below, the reasoning within the process of reflective equilibrium cannot possibly be construed as deductive. This should provide methodological Rawlsians with leeway in dealing with controversial premises. For a sustained defence of a non-deductive model of moral reasoning see Wellman, Challenge and Response.
    • Challenge and Response
    • Wellman1
  • 96
    • 84995016751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paris, Presses Universitaires de la France
    • C. Larmore, Modernité et Morale, (Paris, Presses Universitaires de la France, 1993), p. 15. For a summary in English, see D. Weinstock, 'Review of C. Larmore, Modernité et morale', Journal of Philosophy, 93, 1 (1996), 41-8. Larmore lists among philosophers who violate this ethics of thought 'Heidegger, the critical theory of the Frankfurt School (before Habermas), and the neo-Nietzschean thought of Foucault and Derrida'. Gadamer, Ricoeur, Habermas and Bergson are among the continental philosophers who respect it (pp. 15f). Note that general principles involving vague references to freedom, equality and welfare would also violate this maxim (see Norman, Taking Freedom Too Seriously?, pp. 153-62). See Folke Tersman's argument (pp. 404f) for why reflective equilibrium would have to reject utilitarianism on these grounds, in F. Tersman, 'Utilitarianism and the idea of reflective equilibrium', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 29 (1991), 395-406.
    • (1993) Modernité et Morale , pp. 15
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 97
    • 84995016751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Review of C. Larmore, modernité et morale
    • C. Larmore, Modernité et Morale, (Paris, Presses Universitaires de la France, 1993), p. 15. For a summary in English, see D. Weinstock, 'Review of C. Larmore, Modernité et morale', Journal of Philosophy, 93, 1 (1996), 41-8. Larmore lists among philosophers who violate this ethics of thought 'Heidegger, the critical theory of the Frankfurt School (before Habermas), and the neo-Nietzschean thought of Foucault and Derrida'. Gadamer, Ricoeur, Habermas and Bergson are among the continental philosophers who respect it (pp. 15f). Note that general principles involving vague references to freedom, equality and welfare would also violate this maxim (see Norman, Taking Freedom Too Seriously?, pp. 153-62). See Folke Tersman's argument (pp. 404f) for why reflective equilibrium would have to reject utilitarianism on these grounds, in F. Tersman, 'Utilitarianism and the idea of reflective equilibrium', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 29 (1991), 395-406.
    • (1996) Journal of Philosophy , vol.93 , Issue.1 , pp. 41-48
    • Weinstock, D.1
  • 98
    • 84995016751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • C. Larmore, Modernité et Morale, (Paris, Presses Universitaires de la France, 1993), p. 15. For a summary in English, see D. Weinstock, 'Review of C. Larmore, Modernité et morale', Journal of Philosophy, 93, 1 (1996), 41-8. Larmore lists among philosophers who violate this ethics of thought 'Heidegger, the critical theory of the Frankfurt School (before Habermas), and the neo-Nietzschean thought of Foucault and Derrida'. Gadamer, Ricoeur, Habermas and Bergson are among the continental philosophers who respect it (pp. 15f). Note that general principles involving vague references to freedom, equality and welfare would also violate this maxim (see Norman, Taking Freedom Too Seriously?, pp. 153-62). See Folke Tersman's argument (pp. 404f) for why reflective equilibrium would have to reject utilitarianism on these grounds, in F. Tersman, 'Utilitarianism and the idea of reflective equilibrium', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 29 (1991), 395-406.
    • Freedom Too Seriously? , pp. 153-162
    • Norman, T.1
  • 99
    • 84995016751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism and the idea of reflective equilibrium
    • C. Larmore, Modernité et Morale, (Paris, Presses Universitaires de la France, 1993), p. 15. For a summary in English, see D. Weinstock, 'Review of C. Larmore, Modernité et morale', Journal of Philosophy, 93, 1 (1996), 41-8. Larmore lists among philosophers who violate this ethics of thought 'Heidegger, the critical theory of the Frankfurt School (before Habermas), and the neo-Nietzschean thought of Foucault and Derrida'. Gadamer, Ricoeur, Habermas and Bergson are among the continental philosophers who respect it (pp. 15f). Note that general principles involving vague references to freedom, equality and welfare would also violate this maxim (see Norman, Taking Freedom Too Seriously?, pp. 153-62). See Folke Tersman's argument (pp. 404f) for why reflective equilibrium would have to reject utilitarianism on these grounds, in F. Tersman, 'Utilitarianism and the idea of reflective equilibrium', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 29 (1991), 395-406.
    • (1991) Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.29 , pp. 395-406
    • Tersman, F.1
  • 100
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There has been a great deal written about intuitions and considered judgments in Rawls's method. For the most widely cited descriptions of these ideas, see. e.g., Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 18-21; J. Rawls, 'The independence of moral theory', Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48 (1974), 5-22; Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 45; Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', and 'Reflective equilibrium and Archimedean points'.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 18-21
    • Rawls1
  • 101
    • 0039154628 scopus 로고
    • The independence of moral theory
    • There has been a great deal written about intuitions and considered judgments in Rawls's method. For the most widely cited descriptions of these ideas, see. e.g., Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 18-21; J. Rawls, 'The independence of moral theory', Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48 (1974), 5-22; Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 45; Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', and 'Reflective equilibrium and Archimedean points'.
    • (1974) Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association , vol.48 , pp. 5-22
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 102
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There has been a great deal written about intuitions and considered judgments in Rawls's method. For the most widely cited descriptions of these ideas, see. e.g., Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 18-21; J. Rawls, 'The independence of moral theory', Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48 (1974), 5-22; Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 45; Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', and 'Reflective equilibrium and Archimedean points'.
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 45
    • Rawls1
  • 103
    • 0039747082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There has been a great deal written about intuitions and considered judgments in Rawls's method. For the most widely cited descriptions of these ideas, see. e.g., Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 18-21; J. Rawls, 'The independence of moral theory', Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48 (1974), 5-22; Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 45; Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', and 'Reflective equilibrium and Archimedean points'.
    • Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics
    • Daniels1
  • 104
    • 85033871466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There has been a great deal written about intuitions and considered judgments in Rawls's method. For the most widely cited descriptions of these ideas, see. e.g., Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 18-21; J. Rawls, 'The independence of moral theory', Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48 (1974), 5-22; Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 45; Daniels, 'Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics', and 'Reflective equilibrium and Archimedean points'.
    • Reflective Equilibrium and Archimedean Points
  • 105
    • 0004024838 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Oxford University Press
    • Will Kymlicka emphasizes that principles must not only cohere with, but also illuminate, our considered convictions, Contemporary Political Philosophy, (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1990), p. 7.
    • (1990) Contemporary Political Philosophy , pp. 7
  • 106
    • 0040339065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls himself introduced the distinction between wide and narrow reflective equilibrium, implicitly in A Theory of Justice, pp. 49f, and explicitly in his 'The Independence of Moral Theory'. DePaul proposes a distinction between conservative and radical conceptions of reflective equilibrium which cuts across that between wide and narrow, in 'Two Conceptions of Coherence Methods in Ethics', Mind, 96 (1987), 463-81.
    • A Theory of Justice
  • 107
    • 0040339065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two conceptions of coherence methods in ethics
    • Rawls himself introduced the distinction between wide and narrow reflective equilibrium, implicitly in A Theory of Justice, pp. 49f, and explicitly in his 'The Independence of Moral Theory'. DePaul proposes a distinction between conservative and radical conceptions of reflective equilibrium which cuts across that between wide and narrow, in 'Two Conceptions of Coherence Methods in Ethics', Mind, 96 (1987), 463-81.
    • (1987) Mind , vol.96 , pp. 463-481
  • 108
    • 85033901531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R. M. Hare, 'The Argument from Received Opinion', in R. M. Hare, Essays on Philosophical Method (London, Macmillan, 1971), p. 122; criticized in Grice, 'Moral theories and received opinion'. See also S. Sencerz, 'Moral intuitions and justification in ethics', Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986), p. 78.
    • The Argument from Received Opinion
    • Hare, R.M.1
  • 109
    • 0004350757 scopus 로고
    • London, Macmillan
    • R. M. Hare, 'The Argument from Received Opinion', in R. M. Hare, Essays on Philosophical Method (London, Macmillan, 1971), p. 122; criticized in Grice, 'Moral theories and received opinion'. See also S. Sencerz, 'Moral intuitions and justification in ethics', Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986), p. 78.
    • (1971) Essays on Philosophical Method , pp. 122
    • Hare, R.M.1
  • 110
    • 0039154646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R. M. Hare, 'The Argument from Received Opinion', in R. M. Hare, Essays on Philosophical Method (London, Macmillan, 1971), p. 122; criticized in Grice, 'Moral theories and received opinion'. See also S. Sencerz, 'Moral intuitions and justification in ethics', Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986), p. 78.
    • Moral Theories and Received Opinion
  • 111
    • 0039747076 scopus 로고
    • Moral intuitions and justification in ethics
    • R. M. Hare, 'The Argument from Received Opinion', in R. M. Hare, Essays on Philosophical Method (London, Macmillan, 1971), p. 122; criticized in Grice, 'Moral theories and received opinion'. See also S. Sencerz, 'Moral intuitions and justification in ethics', Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986), p. 78.
    • (1986) Philosophical Studies , vol.50 , pp. 78
    • Sencerz, S.1
  • 112
    • 0004262926 scopus 로고
    • London, Macmillan
    • See S. Lukes, Essays in Social Theory (London, Macmillan, 1977), pp. 154-74, 177-80; S. Blackburn, 'Can Philosophy Exist?', in J. Couture and K. Nielsen (eds), Méta-philosophie: Reconstructing Philosophy? New Essays on Metaphilosophy (Calgary, University of Calgary Press, 1993), p. 91, n20; Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', pp. 516f. The passages from Singer and Blackburn are among the most colourful in this otherwise bone-dry literature on moral methodology. Others who are less scathing in their judgments on intuitive starting points, but troubled by reliance on them nonetheless, include Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', p. 146; D. Little, 'Reflective equilibrium and justification', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22 (1984), 373-87; and Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium'.
    • (1977) Essays in Social Theory , pp. 154-174
    • Lukes, S.1
  • 113
    • 74149093373 scopus 로고
    • Can philosophy exist?
    • J. Couture and K. Nielsen (eds), Calgary, University of Calgary Press, n20
    • See S. Lukes, Essays in Social Theory (London, Macmillan, 1977), pp. 154-74, 177-80; S. Blackburn, 'Can Philosophy Exist?', in J. Couture and K. Nielsen (eds), Méta-philosophie: Reconstructing Philosophy? New Essays on Metaphilosophy (Calgary, University of Calgary Press, 1993), p. 91, n20; Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', pp. 516f. The passages from Singer and Blackburn are among the most colourful in this otherwise bone-dry literature on moral methodology. Others who are less scathing in their judgments on intuitive starting points, but troubled by reliance on them nonetheless, include Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', p. 146; D. Little, 'Reflective equilibrium and justification', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22 (1984), 373-87; and Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium'.
    • (1993) Méta-philosophie: Reconstructing Philosophy? New Essays on Metaphilosophy , pp. 91
    • Blackburn, S.1
  • 114
    • 0040933065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See S. Lukes, Essays in Social Theory (London, Macmillan, 1977), pp. 154-74, 177-80; S. Blackburn, 'Can Philosophy Exist?', in J. Couture and K. Nielsen (eds), Méta-philosophie: Reconstructing Philosophy? New Essays on Metaphilosophy (Calgary, University of Calgary Press, 1993), p. 91, n20; Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', pp. 516f. The passages from Singer and Blackburn are among the most colourful in this otherwise bone-dry literature on moral methodology. Others who are less scathing in their judgments on intuitive starting points, but troubled by reliance on them nonetheless, include Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', p. 146; D. Little, 'Reflective equilibrium and justification', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22 (1984), 373-87; and Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium'.
    • Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium
    • Singer1
  • 115
    • 60949364193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See S. Lukes, Essays in Social Theory (London, Macmillan, 1977), pp. 154-74, 177-80; S. Blackburn, 'Can Philosophy Exist?', in J. Couture and K. Nielsen (eds), Méta-philosophie: Reconstructing Philosophy? New Essays on Metaphilosophy (Calgary, University of Calgary Press, 1993), p. 91, n20; Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', pp. 516f. The passages from Singer and Blackburn are among the most colourful in this otherwise bone-dry literature on moral methodology. Others who are less scathing in their judgments on intuitive starting points, but troubled by reliance on them nonetheless, include Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', p. 146; D. Little, 'Reflective equilibrium and justification', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22 (1984), 373-87; and Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium'.
    • Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments , pp. 146
    • Lyons1
  • 116
    • 84979405938 scopus 로고
    • Reflective equilibrium and justification
    • See S. Lukes, Essays in Social Theory (London, Macmillan, 1977), pp. 154-74, 177-80; S. Blackburn, 'Can Philosophy Exist?', in J. Couture and K. Nielsen (eds), Méta-philosophie: Reconstructing Philosophy? New Essays on Metaphilosophy (Calgary, University of Calgary Press, 1993), p. 91, n20; Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', pp. 516f. The passages from Singer and Blackburn are among the most colourful in this otherwise bone-dry literature on moral methodology. Others who are less scathing in their judgments on intuitive starting points, but troubled by reliance on them nonetheless, include Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', p. 146; D. Little, 'Reflective equilibrium and justification', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22 (1984), 373-87; and Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium'.
    • (1984) Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.22 , pp. 373-387
    • Little, D.1
  • 117
    • 85033888917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See S. Lukes, Essays in Social Theory (London, Macmillan, 1977), pp. 154-74, 177-80; S. Blackburn, 'Can Philosophy Exist?', in J. Couture and K. Nielsen (eds), Méta-philosophie: Reconstructing Philosophy? New Essays on Metaphilosophy (Calgary, University of Calgary Press, 1993), p. 91, n20; Singer, 'Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium', pp. 516f. The passages from Singer and Blackburn are among the most colourful in this otherwise bone-dry literature on moral methodology. Others who are less scathing in their judgments on intuitive starting points, but troubled by reliance on them nonetheless, include Lyons, 'Nature and Soundness of the Contract and Coherence Arguments', p. 146; D. Little, 'Reflective equilibrium and justification', Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22 (1984), 373-87; and Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium'.
    • The Claims of Reflective Equilibrium
    • Raz1
  • 118
    • 0004255852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, pp. 373f. See also Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', p. 109. Like Sidgwick in his day, Audi notes that this kind of 'appeal to intuitions is a pervasive strategy in contemporary philosophical discourse ... Ethical theory is no exception.' (Audi, 'Ethical reflectionism', p. 295).
    • Methods of Ethics
    • Sidgwick1
  • 119
    • 85033894263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, pp. 373f. See also Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', p. 109. Like Sidgwick in his day, Audi notes that this kind of 'appeal to intuitions is a pervasive strategy in contemporary philosophical discourse ... Ethical theory is no exception.' (Audi, 'Ethical reflectionism', p. 295).
    • The Establishment of Ethical First Principles , pp. 109
    • Sidgwick1
  • 120
    • 85033875714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, pp. 373f. See also Sidgwick, 'The establishment of ethical first principles', p. 109. Like Sidgwick in his day, Audi notes that this kind of 'appeal to intuitions is a pervasive strategy in contemporary philosophical discourse ... Ethical theory is no exception.' (Audi, 'Ethical reflectionism', p. 295).
    • Ethical Reflectionism , pp. 295
    • Audi1
  • 121
    • 84936020353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barry, Theories of Justice, p. 258. See H. Aronovitch, 'A defence of analogical argument', Political Studies, 45, 1 (1997), 78-92.
    • Theories of Justice , pp. 258
    • Barry1
  • 122
    • 0040933062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A defence of analogical argument
    • Barry, Theories of Justice, p. 258. See H. Aronovitch, 'A defence of analogical argument', Political Studies, 45, 1 (1997), 78-92.
    • (1997) Political Studies , vol.45 , Issue.1 , pp. 78-92
    • Aronovitch, H.1
  • 124
    • 0039747069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', p. 317. Sencerz ('Moral Intuitions and Justification in Ethics', pp. 80f) makes a brief and surely disingenuous case for not winnowing out judgments made in the heat of passion. Raz ('The claims of reflective equilibrium', p. 318) questions why one would have to jettison 'unconsidered' judgments at the start if reflective equilibrium will get rid of them later anyway.
    • Relativism and Wide Reflective Equilibrium , pp. 317
    • Nielsen1
  • 125
    • 85033899420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', p. 317. Sencerz ('Moral Intuitions and Justification in Ethics', pp. 80f) makes a brief and surely disingenuous case for not winnowing out judgments made in the heat of passion. Raz ('The claims of reflective equilibrium', p. 318) questions why one would have to jettison 'unconsidered' judgments at the start if reflective equilibrium will get rid of them later anyway.
    • Moral Intuitions and Justification in Ethics
    • Sencerz1
  • 126
    • 85033888917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nielsen, 'Relativism and wide reflective equilibrium', p. 317. Sencerz ('Moral Intuitions and Justification in Ethics', pp. 80f) makes a brief and surely disingenuous case for not winnowing out judgments made in the heat of passion. Raz ('The claims of reflective equilibrium', p. 318) questions why one would have to jettison 'unconsidered' judgments at the start if reflective equilibrium will get rid of them later anyway.
    • The Claims of Reflective Equilibrium , pp. 318
    • Raz1
  • 130
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 20
    • Rawls1
  • 131
    • 0004293523 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • (1955) Fact, Fiction, and Forecast , pp. 65-68
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 132
    • 0040339049 scopus 로고
    • On some methods of ethics and linguistics
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • (1980) Philosophical Studies , vol.37 , pp. 21-36
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 133
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls1
  • 134
    • 0003517608 scopus 로고
    • Standford CA, Stanford University Press
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • (1990) Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics , pp. 7
    • Kukathas, C.1    Pettit, P.2
  • 135
    • 0039747062 scopus 로고
    • Considered judgements again
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • (1982) Human Studies , vol.5 , pp. 117
    • Nielsen, K.1
  • 136
    • 85033885519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • How to Proceed in Social Philosophy , pp. 120
  • 137
    • 85033875714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • Ethical Reflectionism , pp. 307
    • Audi1
  • 138
    • 0039747068 scopus 로고
    • Ethics and science
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • (1980) Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy
    • English, J.1
  • 139
    • 85033881790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • Reflective Equilibrium and Justification , pp. 384
    • Little1
  • 140
    • 84936020353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • Theories of Justice
    • Barry1
  • 141
    • 0039747067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 20, where he cites N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-8. Daniels makes a convincing case that Rawls's suggestion about an analogy between the methods of ethics and linguistics is unhelpful; see N. Daniels, 'On some methods of ethics and linguistics', Philosophical Studies, 37 (1980), 21-36; Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 47f; C. Kukathas, and P. Pettit, Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its Critics (Standford CA, Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 7. Several authors have discussed the alleged parallel between reflective equilibrium and scientific method. Those receptive to the parallel include Nielsen (K. Nielsen, 'Considered judgements again', Human Studies, 5 (1982), p. 117; 'How to proceed in social philosophy', p. 120), Audi ('Ethical reflectionism', p. 307), and J. English, 'Ethics and science', Proceedings of the XVI International Congress of Philosophy, 1980; those noting significant differences between the methods include Little ('Reflective Equilibrium and Justification', p. 384), and Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 263f), among many others, including Wellman (Challenge and Response, pp. 36-44), who does not discuss reflective equilibrium explicitly.
    • Challenge and Response , pp. 36-44
    • Wellman1
  • 144
    • 84936020353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • After discussing the highly theorized motivations of the parties in the original position in Rawls's Dewey Lectures, Barry remarks: 'It seems clear that Rawls has hit upon a method whereby you can get anything out of the theory at the end by simply putting it in at the beginning'. (Barry, Theories of Justice, p. 337.) See also P. Ricoeur, 'Le cercle de la démonstration', in C. Audard (ed.), Individu et justice sociale autour de John Rawls (Paris, Seuil, 1988), pp. 129-41.
    • Theories of Justice , pp. 337
    • Barry1
  • 145
    • 0040339050 scopus 로고
    • Le cercle de la démonstration
    • C. Audard (ed.), Paris, Seuil
    • After discussing the highly theorized motivations of the parties in the original position in Rawls's Dewey Lectures, Barry remarks: 'It seems clear that Rawls has hit upon a method whereby you can get anything out of the theory at the end by simply putting it in at the beginning'. (Barry, Theories of Justice, p. 337.) See also P. Ricoeur, 'Le cercle de la démonstration', in C. Audard (ed.), Individu et justice sociale autour de John Rawls (Paris, Seuil, 1988), pp. 129-41.
    • (1988) Individu et Justice Sociale Autour de John Rawls , pp. 129-141
    • Ricoeur, P.1
  • 146
    • 85033874336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, Theories of Justice, p. 48. Note, Rawls couches this remark in a misleading descriptive mode.
    • Theories of Justice , pp. 48
    • Rawls1
  • 147
    • 0040933055 scopus 로고
    • The justification of political liberalism
    • D. Weinstock, 'The justification of political liberalism', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 75 (1994), p. 166.
    • (1994) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.75 , pp. 166
    • Weinstock, D.1
  • 148
    • 0010773136 scopus 로고
    • Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press
    • 'It is mere Kantian dogma that behind every moral intuition lies a universal rule, behind every set of rules a single stateable principle or system of principles.' (A. Baier, Postures of the Mind (Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1985), p. 208). See also Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', p. 329; and A. Gibbard, 'Why theorize how to live with each other?', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55 (1995), 323-28.
    • (1985) Postures of the Mind , pp. 208
    • Baier, A.1
  • 149
    • 85033888917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'It is mere Kantian dogma that behind every moral intuition lies a universal rule, behind every set of rules a single stateable principle or system of principles.' (A. Baier, Postures of the Mind (Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1985), p. 208). See also Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', p. 329; and A. Gibbard, 'Why theorize how to live with each other?', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55 (1995), 323-28.
    • The Claims of Reflective Equilibrium , pp. 329
    • Raz1
  • 150
    • 0040933054 scopus 로고
    • Why theorize how to live with each other?
    • 'It is mere Kantian dogma that behind every moral intuition lies a universal rule, behind every set of rules a single stateable principle or system of principles.' (A. Baier, Postures of the Mind (Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1985), p. 208). See also Raz, 'The claims of reflective equilibrium', p. 329; and A. Gibbard, 'Why theorize how to live with each other?', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55 (1995), 323-28.
    • (1995) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.55 , pp. 323-328
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 151
    • 0039747078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Larmore (Modernité et Morale, p. 17) says the same about the defining characteristic of the Anglo-American philosophical tradition.
    • Modernité et Morale , pp. 17
    • Larmore1
  • 152
    • 85033899122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am not concerned here with whether it is a theory with an analogous content (e.g., confirmation procedure) to methodologies of science; but rather whether it is a theory of the same kind
    • I am not concerned here with whether it is a theory with an analogous content (e.g., confirmation procedure) to methodologies of science; but rather whether it is a theory of the same kind.
  • 153
    • 84936020353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Barry, Theories of Justice, p. 263 for a similar observation. Of all the explanations of reflective equilibrium I have read, there is only one extended hypothetical description of a typical process of arriving at an equilibrium, and it is scarcely a page long - De Paul's 'Two Conceptions of Coherence Methods in Ethics', pp. 468f.
    • Theories of Justice , pp. 263
    • Barry1
  • 154
    • 85033895338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Barry, Theories of Justice, p. 263 for a similar observation. Of all the explanations of reflective equilibrium I have read, there is only one extended hypothetical description of a typical process of arriving at an equilibrium, and it is scarcely a page long - De Paul's 'Two Conceptions of Coherence Methods in Ethics', pp. 468f.
    • Two Conceptions of Coherence Methods in Ethics
    • De Paul's1
  • 155
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21, my italics. Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 281) and Snare ('John Rawls and the methods of ethics', pp. 109f) cite this fact as evidence that Rawls might not actually be using the method.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 21
    • Rawls1
  • 156
    • 84936020353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21, my italics. Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 281) and Snare ('John Rawls and the methods of ethics', pp. 109f) cite this fact as evidence that Rawls might not actually be using the method.
    • Theories of Justice , pp. 281
    • Barry1
  • 157
    • 85033896077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 21, my italics. Barry (Theories of Justice, p. 281) and Snare ('John Rawls and the methods of ethics', pp. 109f) cite this fact as evidence that Rawls might not actually be using the method.
    • John Rawls and the Methods of Ethics
    • Snare1
  • 158
    • 85033893136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Hence, if there is an analogy with science here, then reflective equilibrium may tell us more about the so-called logic of discovery - how thoughtful philosophers come up with principles -than about the logic of justification, which was the object of scientific methodology.
  • 159
    • 85033874336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, Theories of Justice, p. 49; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal' and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'; Kukathas and Pettit, Rawls, p. 69.
    • Theories of Justice , pp. 49
    • Rawls1
  • 160
    • 85033873879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, Theories of Justice, p. 49; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal' and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'; Kukathas and Pettit, Rawls, p. 69.
    • Rawls and the Socratic Ideal
    • Nielsen1
  • 161
    • 85033885519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, Theories of Justice, p. 49; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal' and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'; Kukathas and Pettit, Rawls, p. 69.
    • How to Proceed in Social Philosophy
  • 162
    • 85031041899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, Theories of Justice, p. 49; Nielsen, 'Rawls and the Socratic ideal' and 'How to proceed in social philosophy'; Kukathas and Pettit, Rawls, p. 69.
    • Rawls , pp. 69
    • Kukathas1    Pettit2
  • 164
    • 85033882995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a similar vision of political philosophizing, see Perelman, Justice, 58f. When Snare ('John Rawls and the methods of ethics', p. 110) and Raz ('The claims of reflective equilibrium', p. 329) consider reflective equilibrium interpreted this way they think of it as a 'weasel concept' (Snare's term) that places 'few actual restraints' on investigation. For Raz, its appealing features are 'shared by many other conceptions of morality and of moral progress.'
    • Justice
    • Perelman1
  • 165
    • 85033896077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a similar vision of political philosophizing, see Perelman, Justice, 58f. When Snare ('John Rawls and the methods of ethics', p. 110) and Raz ('The claims of reflective equilibrium', p. 329) consider reflective equilibrium interpreted this way they think of it as a 'weasel concept' (Snare's term) that places 'few actual restraints' on investigation. For Raz, its appealing features are 'shared by many other conceptions of morality and of moral progress.'
    • John Rawls and the Methods of Ethics , pp. 110
    • Snare1
  • 166
    • 85033888917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a similar vision of political philosophizing, see Perelman, Justice, 58f. When Snare ('John Rawls and the methods of ethics', p. 110) and Raz ('The claims of reflective equilibrium', p. 329) consider reflective equilibrium interpreted this way they think of it as a 'weasel concept' (Snare's term) that places 'few actual restraints' on investigation. For Raz, its appealing features are 'shared by many other conceptions of morality and of moral progress.'
    • The Claims of Reflective Equilibrium , pp. 329
    • Raz1
  • 167
    • 85033897929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In theory, methadone is supposed to stop the addict's craving for heroin without getting her high. Nielsen seems to think of the therapeutic effects of reflective equilibrium in this way. Veterans of methadone treatment, however, often speak favourably of the high they get from the drug. Norman Daniels is one of the few methodological Rawlsians who seems to have enjoyed an epistemological high with reflective equilibrium. See, e.g., his full-page, graphic illustration of it in Daniels, 'Reflective equilibrium and Archimedean points', p. 88.
    • Reflective Equilibrium and Archimedean Points , pp. 88
    • Daniels1
  • 168
    • 1642531640 scopus 로고
    • New York NY, Farrar
    • See the quote from Barry at the outset and T. Wolfe, Painted Word (New York NY, Farrar, 1975).
    • (1975) Painted Word
    • Barry1    Wolfe, T.2
  • 169
    • 0040339054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Writing in ethics which accepts without thought too much that is the traditional or current outlook and discourse of the staff of policy-making institutions and of other professions is, however, in danger of providing no more than a limited critique of institutional and social arrangements. The worldly success of problem-centred writing in ethics ... is in part achieved by willingness to accept established and establishment views of what moral problems there are.' (O'Neill, 'The Power of Example', pp. 21f.)
    • The Power of Example
    • O'Neill1
  • 171
    • 84972051636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a central idea in Rawls, 'Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical' and 'The Idea of Overlapping Consensus'. The moralization of the philosopher's task is criticized in Raz, 'Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence', Hampton 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism', p. 293 and J. Hampton, 'The common faith of liberalism', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 75 (1994), 186-216. Weinstock ('Justification of Political Liberalism', pp. 175f) presents a powerful argument for the incoherence of reflective equilibrium once Rawls substitutes 'shared notions implicit in the political culture' for his early notion of considered judgments. But I have not seen an analysis of Rawls that explains how political liberalism seems to grow out of his earlier methodological ideas. See P. Forster, 'A critique of Rorty's pragmatic defence of liberalism', (unpublished, Department of Philosophy, University of Ottawa) for a meticulous critique of the move from pragmatism to liberalism in Rorty.
    • Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical
    • Rawls1
  • 172
    • 85033871401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a central idea in Rawls, 'Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical' and 'The Idea of Overlapping Consensus'. The moralization of the philosopher's task is criticized in Raz, 'Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence', Hampton 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism', p. 293 and J. Hampton, 'The common faith of liberalism', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 75 (1994), 186-216. Weinstock ('Justification of Political Liberalism', pp. 175f) presents a powerful argument for the incoherence of reflective equilibrium once Rawls substitutes 'shared notions implicit in the political culture' for his early notion of considered judgments. But I have not seen an analysis of Rawls that explains how political liberalism seems to grow out of his earlier methodological ideas. See P. Forster, 'A critique of Rorty's pragmatic defence of liberalism', (unpublished, Department of Philosophy, University of Ottawa) for a meticulous critique of the move from pragmatism to liberalism in Rorty.
    • The Idea of Overlapping Consensus
  • 173
    • 0039154638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a central idea in Rawls, 'Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical' and 'The Idea of Overlapping Consensus'. The moralization of the philosopher's task is criticized in Raz, 'Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence', Hampton 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism', p. 293 and J. Hampton, 'The common faith of liberalism', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 75 (1994), 186-216. Weinstock ('Justification of Political Liberalism', pp. 175f) presents a powerful argument for the incoherence of reflective equilibrium once Rawls substitutes 'shared notions implicit in the political culture' for his early notion of considered judgments. But I have not seen an analysis of Rawls that explains how political liberalism seems to grow out of his earlier methodological ideas. See P. Forster, 'A critique of Rorty's pragmatic defence of liberalism', (unpublished, Department of Philosophy, University of Ottawa) for a meticulous critique of the move from pragmatism to liberalism in Rorty.
    • Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence
    • Raz1
  • 174
    • 0003284395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a central idea in Rawls, 'Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical' and 'The Idea of Overlapping Consensus'. The moralization of the philosopher's task is criticized in Raz, 'Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence', Hampton 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism', p. 293 and J. Hampton, 'The common faith of liberalism', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 75 (1994), 186-216. Weinstock ('Justification of Political Liberalism', pp. 175f) presents a powerful argument for the incoherence of reflective equilibrium once Rawls substitutes 'shared notions implicit in the political culture' for his early notion of considered judgments. But I have not seen an analysis of Rawls that explains how political liberalism seems to grow out of his earlier methodological ideas. See P. Forster, 'A critique of Rorty's pragmatic defence of liberalism', (unpublished, Department of Philosophy, University of Ottawa) for a meticulous critique of the move from pragmatism to liberalism in Rorty.
    • The Moral Commitments of Liberalism , pp. 293
    • Hampton1
  • 175
    • 0002152078 scopus 로고
    • The common faith of liberalism
    • This is a central idea in Rawls, 'Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical' and 'The Idea of Overlapping Consensus'. The moralization of the philosopher's task is criticized in Raz, 'Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence', Hampton 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism', p. 293 and J. Hampton, 'The common faith of liberalism', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 75 (1994), 186-216. Weinstock ('Justification of Political Liberalism', pp. 175f) presents a powerful argument for the incoherence of reflective equilibrium once Rawls substitutes 'shared notions implicit in the political culture' for his early notion of considered judgments. But I have not seen an analysis of Rawls that explains how political liberalism seems to grow out of his earlier methodological ideas. See P. Forster, 'A critique of Rorty's pragmatic defence of liberalism', (unpublished, Department of Philosophy, University of Ottawa) for a meticulous critique of the move from pragmatism to liberalism in Rorty.
    • (1994) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.75 , pp. 186-216
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 176
    • 31144475789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a central idea in Rawls, 'Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical' and 'The Idea of Overlapping Consensus'. The moralization of the philosopher's task is criticized in Raz, 'Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence', Hampton 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism', p. 293 and J. Hampton, 'The common faith of liberalism', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 75 (1994), 186-216. Weinstock ('Justification of Political Liberalism', pp. 175f) presents a powerful argument for the incoherence of reflective equilibrium once Rawls substitutes 'shared notions implicit in the political culture' for his early notion of considered judgments. But I have not seen an analysis of Rawls that explains how political liberalism seems to grow out of his earlier methodological ideas. See P. Forster, 'A critique of Rorty's pragmatic defence of liberalism', (unpublished, Department of Philosophy, University of Ottawa) for a meticulous critique of the move from pragmatism to liberalism in Rorty.
    • Justification of Political Liberalism
    • Weinstock1
  • 177
    • 85033897410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished, Department of Philosophy, University of Ottawa
    • This is a central idea in Rawls, 'Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical' and 'The Idea of Overlapping Consensus'. The moralization of the philosopher's task is criticized in Raz, 'Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence', Hampton 'The Moral Commitments of Liberalism', p. 293 and J. Hampton, 'The common faith of liberalism', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 75 (1994), 186-216. Weinstock ('Justification of Political Liberalism', pp. 175f) presents a powerful argument for the incoherence of reflective equilibrium once Rawls substitutes 'shared notions implicit in the political culture' for his early notion of considered judgments. But I have not seen an analysis of Rawls that explains how political liberalism seems to grow out of his earlier methodological ideas. See P. Forster, 'A critique of Rorty's pragmatic defence of liberalism', (unpublished, Department of Philosophy, University of Ottawa) for a meticulous critique of the move from pragmatism to liberalism in Rorty.
    • A Critique of Rorty's Pragmatic Defence of Liberalism
    • Forster, P.1
  • 178
    • 0040339070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He argues against adopting coherence models on these (and other) grounds
    • Sayre-McCord, 'Coherence and models for moral theorizing, pp. 185-7. He argues against adopting coherence models on these (and other) grounds.
    • Coherence and Models for Moral Theorizing , pp. 185-187
    • Sayre-McCord1
  • 179
    • 0003250073 scopus 로고
    • The group right to linguistic security; whose right, what duties?
    • J. Baker (ed.), Toronto, University of Toronto Press
    • For exemplary practice of methodological Rawlsianism on these three subjects see, respectively, D. Réaume, 'The Group Right to Linguistic Security; Whose Right, What Duties?', in J. Baker (ed.), Group Rights, (Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 1994), pp. 118-41; J. Carens, 'Aliens and Citizens: the Case for Open Borders', in W. Kymlicka (ed.), The Rights of Minority Cultures (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 331-49; and W. Kymlicka, 'Moral philosophy and public policy: the case of NRTs', Bioethics, 7 (1993), 1-26.
    • (1994) Group Rights , pp. 118-141
    • Réaume, D.1
  • 180
    • 0039154630 scopus 로고
    • Aliens and citizens: The case for open borders
    • W. Kymlicka (ed.), Oxford, Oxford University Press
    • For exemplary practice of methodological Rawlsianism on these three subjects see, respectively, D. Réaume, 'The Group Right to Linguistic Security; Whose Right, What Duties?', in J. Baker (ed.), Group Rights, (Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 1994), pp. 118-41; J. Carens, 'Aliens and Citizens: the Case for Open Borders', in W. Kymlicka (ed.), The Rights of Minority Cultures (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 331-49; and W. Kymlicka, 'Moral philosophy and public policy: the case of NRTs', Bioethics, 7 (1993), 1-26.
    • (1995) The Rights of Minority Cultures , pp. 331-349
    • Carens, J.1
  • 181
    • 0027487818 scopus 로고
    • Moral philosophy and public policy: The case of NRTs
    • For exemplary practice of methodological Rawlsianism on these three subjects see, respectively, D. Réaume, 'The Group Right to Linguistic Security; Whose Right, What Duties?', in J. Baker (ed.), Group Rights, (Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 1994), pp. 118-41; J. Carens, 'Aliens and Citizens: the Case for Open Borders', in W. Kymlicka (ed.), The Rights of Minority Cultures (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 331-49; and W. Kymlicka, 'Moral philosophy and public policy: the case of NRTs', Bioethics, 7 (1993), 1-26.
    • (1993) Bioethics , vol.7 , pp. 1-26
    • Kymlicka, W.1
  • 182
  • 183
    • 0004027544 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth, Penguin
    • J. Fishkin, A Dialogue of Justice: Toward a Self-Reflective Society (New Haven CT, Yale University Press, 1993), p. 5. See also S. Hampshire, Innocence and Experience (Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1989), p. 72.
    • (1989) Innocence and Experience , pp. 72
    • Hampshire, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.