-
1
-
-
0346291947
-
Rational Egoism, Self, and Others
-
Cambridge: MIT Press
-
I have discussed some of these issues elsewhere, for instance, in "Rational Egoism, Self, and Others," in Identity, Character, and Morality, ed. O. Flanagan and A. Rorty (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990). Here, I focus on developing a nonstrategic form of egoism; I try to give a fuller sense of the historical traditions on which my own account draws so heavily and to present the principal systematic claims, worries, and resources more clearly than I have before.
-
(1990)
Identity, Character, and Morality
-
-
Flanagan, O.1
Rorty, A.2
-
2
-
-
34247522132
-
Kantian Rationalism: Inescapability, Authority, and Supremacy
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
For a discussion of one version of this second form of the worry, see my "Kantian Rationalism: Inescapability, Authority, and Supremacy," in Ethics and Practical Reason, ed. Garrett Cullity and Berys Gaut (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
-
(1997)
Ethics and Practical Reason
-
-
Cullity, G.1
Gaut, B.2
-
3
-
-
0347553200
-
-
note
-
Because I do not assume that moral requirements must be rationally authoritative, I do not assume that doubts about the authority of morality imply skepticism or relativism. Moral requirements can be objective and important even if immoral conduct is not always irrational. Nonetheless, I have rationalist ambitions; I would like to see how far we can go in the direction of reconciling the demands of morality and the demands of practical reason, without distorting our views of morality or practical reason.
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
0346292016
-
-
supra note 1
-
See my "Rational Egoism, Self, and Others" (supra note 1) and "Objectivity, Motivation, and Authority in Ethics" (unpublished).
-
Rational Egoism, Self, and Others
-
-
-
6
-
-
0004255852
-
-
Indianapolis: Hackett
-
Cf. Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), pp. 164-70, 499-503; and Gregory Kavka, "The Reconciliation Project," in Morality, Reason, and Truth, ed. David Copp and David Zimmerman (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld, 1984).
-
(1981)
The Methods of Ethics, 7th Ed.
, pp. 164-170
-
-
Sidgwick, H.1
-
7
-
-
0001826003
-
The Reconciliation Project
-
ed. David Copp and David Zimmerman (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld)
-
Cf. Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), pp. 164-70, 499-503; and Gregory Kavka, "The Reconciliation Project," in Morality, Reason, and Truth, ed. David Copp and David Zimmerman (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld, 1984).
-
(1984)
Morality, Reason, and Truth
-
-
Kavka, G.1
-
8
-
-
0348182726
-
-
note
-
References to these works will be given parenthetically in the text.
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
0347553206
-
-
Some might deny the relevance of counterfactual instability. It has been suggested that the Epicureans thought that they did not need to consider merely counterfactual challenges to justice. See Cicero, De Officiis iii 39, and De Re Publica iii 27; cf. A. A. Long and D. N. Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 135. If my commitment to other-regarding norms would collapse in radically different circumstances, does this show that there is anything wrong with my commitment to them in actual circumstances? Even if one's commitments in some counterfactual circumstances - for instance, those in which everyone was self-sufficient and invulnerable - seem irrelevant to one's commitments in actual circumstances, other forms of counterfactual stability are more difficult to ignore. The story of Gyges, though fictional, merely makes vivid considerations that are often at work in real-life situations. Often I can fail to observe norms of cooperation, aid, and nonaggression with assurance of impunity. In these cases, it is as if I had a ring of Gyges. If Gyges has no reason to honor these norms, neither do I in such cases. And even in circumstances in which compliance with other-regarding norms is rational, the accessibility of Gyges' circumstances suggests that my commitment in actual circumstances is to my own self-interest, not to other-regarding morality. Cf. Terence Irwin, Plato's Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), section 130.
-
De Officiis
, vol.3
, pp. 39
-
-
Cicero1
-
10
-
-
0347553204
-
-
Some might deny the relevance of counterfactual instability. It has been suggested that the Epicureans thought that they did not need to consider merely counterfactual challenges to justice. See Cicero, De Officiis iii 39, and De Re Publica iii 27; cf. A. A. Long and D. N. Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 135. If my commitment to other-regarding norms would collapse in radically different circumstances, does this show that there is anything wrong with my commitment to them in actual circumstances? Even if one's commitments in some counterfactual circumstances - for instance, those in which everyone was self-sufficient and invulnerable - seem irrelevant to one's commitments in actual circumstances, other forms of counterfactual stability are more difficult to ignore. The story of Gyges, though fictional, merely makes vivid considerations that are often at work in real-life situations. Often I can fail to observe norms of cooperation, aid, and nonaggression with assurance of impunity. In these cases, it is as if I had a ring of Gyges. If Gyges has no reason to honor these norms, neither do I in such cases. And even in circumstances in which compliance with other-regarding norms is rational, the accessibility of Gyges' circumstances suggests that my commitment in actual circumstances is to my own self-interest, not to other-regarding morality. Cf. Terence Irwin, Plato's Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), section 130.
-
De Re Publica
, vol.3
, pp. 27
-
-
-
11
-
-
0003419754
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Some might deny the relevance of counterfactual instability. It has been suggested that the Epicureans thought that they did not need to consider merely counterfactual challenges to justice. See Cicero, De Officiis iii 39, and De Re Publica iii 27; cf. A. A. Long and D. N. Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 135. If my commitment to other-regarding norms would collapse in radically different circumstances, does this show that there is anything wrong with my commitment to them in actual circumstances? Even if one's commitments in some counterfactual circumstances - for instance, those in which everyone was self-sufficient and invulnerable - seem irrelevant to one's commitments in actual circumstances, other forms of counterfactual stability are more difficult to ignore. The story of Gyges, though fictional, merely makes vivid considerations that are often at work in real-life situations. Often I can fail to observe norms of cooperation, aid, and nonaggression with assurance of impunity. In these cases, it is as if I had a ring of Gyges. If Gyges has no reason to honor these norms, neither do I in such cases. And even in circumstances in which compliance with other-regarding norms is rational, the accessibility of Gyges' circumstances suggests that my commitment in actual circumstances is to my own self-interest, not to other-regarding morality. Cf. Terence Irwin, Plato's Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), section 130.
-
(1987)
The Hellenistic Philosophers
, pp. 135
-
-
Long, A.A.1
Sedley, D.N.2
-
12
-
-
0004345996
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press, section 130
-
Some might deny the relevance of counterfactual instability. It has been suggested that the Epicureans thought that they did not need to consider merely counterfactual challenges to justice. See Cicero, De Officiis iii 39, and De Re Publica iii 27; cf. A. A. Long and D. N. Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 135. If my commitment to other-regarding norms would collapse in radically different circumstances, does this show that there is anything wrong with my commitment to them in actual circumstances? Even if one's commitments in some counterfactual circumstances - for instance, those in which everyone was self-sufficient and invulnerable - seem irrelevant to one's commitments in actual circumstances, other forms of counterfactual stability are more difficult to ignore. The story of Gyges, though fictional, merely makes vivid considerations that are often at work in real-life situations. Often I can fail to observe norms of cooperation, aid, and nonaggression with assurance of impunity. In these cases, it is as if I had a ring of Gyges. If Gyges has no reason to honor these norms, neither do I in such cases. And even in circumstances in which compliance with other-regarding norms is rational, the accessibility of Gyges' circumstances suggests that my commitment in actual circumstances is to my own self-interest, not to other-regarding morality. Cf. Terence Irwin, Plato's Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), section 130.
-
(1995)
Plato's Ethics
-
-
Irwin, T.1
-
13
-
-
0348182722
-
A Fallacy in the Republic
-
ed. Gregory Vlastos (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press)
-
Cf. David Sachs, "A Fallacy in the Republic," in Plato II, ed. Gregory Vlastos (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1971).
-
(1971)
Plato II
, vol.2
-
-
Sachs, D.1
-
14
-
-
0004146328
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
This perspective on Platonic love is suggested and explored in Terence Irwin, Plato's Moral Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 241-42, 267-73, and Irwin, Plato's Ethics, ch. 18.
-
(1977)
Plato's Moral Theory
, pp. 241-242
-
-
Irwin, T.1
-
15
-
-
0004345996
-
-
ch. 18
-
This perspective on Platonic love is suggested and explored in Terence Irwin, Plato's Moral Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 241-42, 267-73, and Irwin, Plato's Ethics, ch. 18.
-
Plato's Ethics
-
-
Irwin1
-
16
-
-
0004126717
-
-
ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (Princeton: Princeton University Press)
-
This translation from the Symposium is adapted from that of Michael Joyce in The Collected Dialogues of Plato, ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1961).
-
(1961)
The Collected Dialogues of Plato
-
-
Joyce, M.1
-
17
-
-
84924910822
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
Translations of passages from the Rhetoric are from the revised Oxford translation in The Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. Jonathan Barnes (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984).
-
(1984)
The Complete Works of Aristotle
-
-
Barnes, J.1
-
18
-
-
0003986649
-
-
Indianapolis: Hackett
-
Translations of passages from the Nicomachean Ethics (NE) are from Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1985).
-
(1985)
Nicomachean Ethics
-
-
Irwin, T.1
-
19
-
-
0040598810
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press, esp. ch. 18
-
My understanding of Aristotle's account of friendship and its role in his ethical theory has been influenced by Terence Irwin, Aristotle's First Principles (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), esp. ch. 18.
-
(1988)
Aristotle's First Principles
-
-
Irwin, T.1
-
20
-
-
0346922093
-
-
note
-
Even justice gets only one book (NE V), and it is not uncommon to regard friendship, unlike justice, as a comparatively minor virtue.
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
0348182723
-
-
note
-
Insofar as this is true, Aristotle can provide further justification for his assumption that there are posthumous benefits and harms and that the welfare of one's loved ones and the success of one's projects, after one is dead, are part of a complete good (NE 1100a10-31, 1101a23-30).
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
0003894851
-
-
ed. A. C. Bradley (New York: Thomas Crowell)
-
T. H. Green, Prolegomena to Ethics, ed. A. C. Bradley (New York: Thomas Crowell, 1969); references to specific sections of this work will be given parenthetically in the text.
-
(1969)
Prolegomena to Ethics
-
-
Green, T.H.1
-
24
-
-
0346292020
-
-
note
-
To my mind, Green's ethical theory is vastly superior to Bradley's; it is not only better informed as to the history of ethics and less dogmatic, but also much more subtle and resourceful.
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
0042065736
-
Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel
-
ed. Stephen Darwall (Indianapolis: Hackett), sermon II, paragraphs 13-14
-
Here, as elsewhere, Green shows the influence of both Butler and Kant. Cf. Bishop Butler, Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel, abridged as Five Sermons, ed. Stephen Darwall (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983), sermon II, paragraphs 13-14; Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. J. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), pp. 446-48, 457, 459-60 (Academy pagination); and Kant, The Critique of Practical Reason, trans. L. W. Beck (Indianapolis: Library of Liberal Arts, 1956), pp. 61-62, 72, 87 (Academy pagination).
-
(1983)
Five Sermons
-
-
Butler, B.1
-
26
-
-
0003630580
-
-
trans. J. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett)
-
Here, as elsewhere, Green shows the influence of both Butler and Kant. Cf. Bishop Butler, Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel, abridged as Five Sermons, ed. Stephen Darwall (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983), sermon II, paragraphs 13-14; Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. J. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), pp. 446-48, 457, 459-60 (Academy pagination); and Kant, The Critique of Practical Reason, trans. L. W. Beck (Indianapolis: Library of Liberal Arts, 1956), pp. 61-62, 72, 87 (Academy pagination).
-
(1981)
Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals
, pp. 446-448
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
27
-
-
0004183724
-
-
trans. L. W. Beck (Indianapolis: Library of Liberal Arts)
-
Here, as elsewhere, Green shows the influence of both Butler and Kant. Cf. Bishop Butler, Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel, abridged as Five Sermons, ed. Stephen Darwall (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983), sermon II, paragraphs 13-14; Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. J. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), pp. 446-48, 457, 459-60 (Academy pagination); and Kant, The Critique of Practical Reason, trans. L. W. Beck (Indianapolis: Library of Liberal Arts, 1956), pp. 61-62, 72, 87 (Academy pagination).
-
(1956)
The Critique of Practical Reason
, pp. 61-62
-
-
Kant1
-
28
-
-
0346292019
-
Morality and Personality: Kant and Green
-
ed. Allen W. Wood (Ithaca: Cornell University Press)
-
Cf. Terence Irwin, "Morality and Personality: Kant and Green," in Self and Nature in Kant's Philosophy, ed. Allen W. Wood (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1984).
-
(1984)
Self and Nature in Kant's Philosophy
-
-
Irwin, T.1
-
29
-
-
0347553193
-
-
ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press), book II, chapter xxvii, sections 8, 15, 17-21, 23, 26
-
John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), book II, chapter xxvii, sections 8, 15, 17-21, 23, 26.
-
(1975)
An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
-
-
Locke, J.1
-
30
-
-
0348182716
-
-
note
-
Nonresponsible agents might usefully be praised or blamed for forward-looking (e.g., deterrent) reasons; but they do not deserve praise or blame. Moreover, in claiming that 'person' is a "forensic" concept, Locke means not only that only persons can be held responsible but also that holding P2 responsible for P1's actions only makes sense if P2 = P1. I am here appealing to the former claim. I doubt the latter claim is true; I suspect responsibility presupposes deliberative control, rather than identity.
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
0346292013
-
-
note
-
However, Brownson does have one very important part of Brown's body, viz., his brain. There is, therefore, a kind of physical criterion of identity - one that defines personal identity in terms of continuity of the brain - that can accommodate the kind of body swap in Brownson's case. But this is an implausible form of the physical criterion. The obvious question is "Why is the brain especially important?" No one thinks that the foot, the nose, or even the heart is necessary or sufficient for personal identity. The brain is a candidate only because in this case, and most others, continuity of the brain is what secures continuity of mental life. But then the reason for focusing on the brain is psychological, not physical. This supports a psychological criterion, however, not a physical one.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
0347553192
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Similar mentalistic views are defended by Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), part III; and Sydney Shoemaker, "Personal Identity: A Materialist's Account," in Sydney Shoemaker and Richard Swinburne, Personal Identity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984).
-
(1984)
Reasons and Persons
, Issue.3 PART
-
-
Parfit, D.1
-
35
-
-
0010940601
-
Personal Identity: A Materialist's Account
-
Sydney Shoemaker and Richard Swinburne, Oxford: Blackwell
-
Similar mentalistic views are defended by Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), part III; and Sydney Shoemaker, "Personal Identity: A Materialist's Account," in Sydney Shoemaker and Richard Swinburne, Personal Identity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984).
-
(1984)
Personal Identity
-
-
Shoemaker, S.1
-
36
-
-
0346292021
-
-
note
-
Some kinds of psychological connections may seem more central or important than others. For instance, my career goals and plans and the actions that depend upon them seem more central to my psychological profile than my preference about what shirt to wear on a particular morning and the actions that depend on that preference. But my career aims seem more central than my fashion preferences largely because more of my beliefs, desires, intentions, and actions depend on the former than on the latter. If so, perhaps qualitative differences among psychological connections can be cashed out in purely quantitative terms.
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
0346292012
-
-
ed. Baruch Brody (Cambridge: MIT Press)
-
The problem of fission for mentalistic views about personal identity was first raised, I believe, by Thomas Reid; see Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, ed. Baruch Brody (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1969), p. 357. Fission and its significance are discussed by David Wiggins, Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1967); Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1981), ch. 1; Parfit, Reasons and Persons, ch. 12; and Shoemaker, "Personal Identity," sections 12-13.
-
(1969)
Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man
, pp. 357
-
-
Reid1
-
38
-
-
0010107446
-
-
Oxford: Blackwell
-
The problem of fission for mentalistic views about personal identity was first raised, I believe, by Thomas Reid; see Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, ed. Baruch Brody (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1969), p. 357. Fission and its significance are discussed by David Wiggins, Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1967); Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1981), ch. 1; Parfit, Reasons and Persons, ch. 12; and Shoemaker, "Personal Identity," sections 12-13.
-
(1967)
Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity
-
-
Wiggins, D.1
-
39
-
-
0004071138
-
-
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, ch. 1
-
The problem of fission for mentalistic views about personal identity was first raised, I believe, by Thomas Reid; see Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, ed. Baruch Brody (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1969), p. 357. Fission and its significance are discussed by David Wiggins, Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1967); Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1981), ch. 1; Parfit, Reasons and Persons, ch. 12; and Shoemaker, "Personal Identity," sections 12-13.
-
(1981)
Philosophical Explanations
-
-
Nozick, R.1
-
40
-
-
0003740191
-
-
ch. 12
-
The problem of fission for mentalistic views about personal identity was first raised, I believe, by Thomas Reid; see Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, ed. Baruch Brody (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1969), p. 357. Fission and its significance are discussed by David Wiggins, Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1967); Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1981), ch. 1; Parfit, Reasons and Persons, ch. 12; and Shoemaker, "Personal Identity," sections 12-13.
-
Reasons and Persons
-
-
Parfit1
-
41
-
-
0003393508
-
-
sections 12-13
-
The problem of fission for mentalistic views about personal identity was first raised, I believe, by Thomas Reid; see Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, ed. Baruch Brody (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1969), p. 357. Fission and its significance are discussed by David Wiggins, Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1967); Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1981), ch. 1; Parfit, Reasons and Persons, ch. 12; and Shoemaker, "Personal Identity," sections 12-13.
-
Personal Identity
-
-
Shoemaker1
-
42
-
-
0002436663
-
The Great Cerebral Commissure
-
There is clinical evidence that suggests that severing the corpus callosum can produce two distinct spheres of consciousness, corresponding to the right and left hemispheres of the brain. See, for example, R. W. Perry, "The Great Cerebral Commissure," Scientific American, vol. 210 (1964); and Thomas Nagel, "Brain Bisection and the Unity of Consciousness," in Personal Identity, ed. John Perry (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1975). When hemispheres are severed, dividing consciousness, each hemisphere can "learn" to perform some functions that the other had performed for the united brain, and in some patients various capacities usually found in only one hemisphere are found in both. Insofar as this is true, the possibility of dividing the brain and preserving two qualitatively identical but distinct streams of consciousness is not so fantastic. A residual empirical obstacle is that the functionality of a single hemisphere of the brain seems to depend upon the integrity of the brain stem, which does not admit of division. But these empirical obstacles to dividing the brain are not important, I think. What we would or should say about personal identity in merely counterfactual circumstances can constrain what we think personal identity consists in and what its significance is, and this can affect what we can or should say about personal identity and its significance in actual circumstances.
-
(1964)
Scientific American
, vol.210
-
-
Perry, R.W.1
-
43
-
-
0002436663
-
Brain Bisection and the Unity of Consciousness
-
ed. John Perry (Los Angeles: University of California Press)
-
There is clinical evidence that suggests that severing the corpus callosum can produce two distinct spheres of consciousness, corresponding to the right and left hemispheres of the brain. See, for example, R. W. Perry, "The Great Cerebral Commissure," Scientific American, vol. 210 (1964); and Thomas Nagel, "Brain Bisection and the Unity of Consciousness," in Personal Identity, ed. John Perry (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1975). When hemispheres are severed, dividing consciousness, each hemisphere can "learn" to perform some functions that the other had performed for the united brain, and in some patients various capacities usually found in only one hemisphere are found in both. Insofar as this is true, the possibility of dividing the brain and preserving two qualitatively identical but distinct streams of consciousness is not so fantastic. A residual empirical obstacle is that the functionality of a single hemisphere of the brain seems to depend upon the integrity of the brain stem, which does not admit of division. But these empirical obstacles to dividing the brain are not important, I think. What we would or should say about personal identity in merely counterfactual circumstances can constrain what we think personal identity consists in and what its significance is, and this can affect what we can or should say about personal identity and its significance in actual circumstances.
-
(1975)
Personal Identity
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
45
-
-
84880401083
-
-
If so, Parfit is wrong to claim (as he does in Reasons and Persons, pp. 259-60, 278-79) that it is an "empty question" which answer is right because they all describe the same outcome. I am unsure myself whether psychological continuity, rather than identity, is all that matters; if it can matter, in the relevant way, that psychological continuity takes a unique or nonbranching form, then identity will have some independent value. However, it is enough for present purposes that psychological continuity has significant independent value.
-
Reasons and Persons
, pp. 259-260
-
-
-
46
-
-
84880401083
-
-
chs. 14 and 15
-
In this way, I agree with Parfit, who thinks that personal identity is "less deep" and normatively less significant on the psychological reductionist view; see Reasons and Persons, chs. 14 and 15. Unlike Parfit, however, I do not think that this follows from considerations about the metaphysical depth of a reductionist view per se; it follows from seeing that there is interpersonal, as well as intrapersonal, psychological continuity and that the difference between the two is at most a matter of degree. discuss this issue somewhat more fully in "Rational Egoism and the Separateness of Persons," in Parfit and His Critics, ed. Jonathan Dancy (Oxford; Blackwell, forthcoming).
-
Reasons and Persons
-
-
-
47
-
-
0348182719
-
Rational Egoism and the Separateness of Persons
-
Oxford; Blackwell, forthcoming
-
In this way, I agree with Parfit, who thinks that personal identity is "less deep" and normatively less significant on the psychological reductionist view; see Reasons and Persons, chs. 14 and 15. Unlike Parfit, however, I do not think that this follows from considerations about the metaphysical depth of a reductionist view per se; it follows from seeing that there is interpersonal, as well as intrapersonal, psychological continuity and that the difference between the two is at most a matter of degree. discuss this issue somewhat more fully in "Rational Egoism and the Separateness of Persons," in Parfit and His Critics, ed. Jonathan Dancy (Oxford; Blackwell, forthcoming).
-
Parfit and His Critics
-
-
Dancy, J.1
-
48
-
-
0346922085
-
-
note
-
Even parental concern for a newborn is preceded by decisions, plans, and actions on the parent's part on which the newborn's existence and condition depend.
-
-
-
-
49
-
-
0346292015
-
-
note
-
Insofar as the metaphysical-egoist attempt to reconcile self-interest and other-regarding moral demands depends upon the fact that people are not individually sufficient for a complete deliberative good, the reconciliation depends upon contingent facts, and the resulting defense of the authority of other-regarding demands will not hold in all possible worlds. But this sort of counterfactual instability is very different from that which afflicts strategic egoism (cf. note 7); for the worlds in which strategic egoism fails are very similar to the actual world (indeed, they include the actual world), whereas the worlds in which metaphysical egoism fails are very different from the actual world. As a result, it is not clear that the sort of counterfactual instability that afflicts metaphysical egoism is a problem.
-
-
-
-
50
-
-
60950034217
-
Objectivity and Coercion in Plato's Dialectic
-
This is a latent theme in Plato's early and transitional dialogues; it comes closer to the surface in the Gorgias, where greater probative value is attached to discussion with diverse and more radical interlocutors. Cf. Terence Irwin, "Objectivity and Coercion in Plato's Dialectic," Revue Internationale de Philosophie, no. 156/157 (1986), pp. 49-74. The deliberative value of freedom of expression and diversity of opinion and lifestyle is an important strand in John Stuart Mill's arguments against censorship, moral legislation, and paternalism, especially in On Liberty; see my "Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism," Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 21 (1992), pp. 67-103.
-
(1986)
Revue Internationale de Philosophie
, vol.156-157
, pp. 49-74
-
-
Irwin, T.1
-
51
-
-
84885739661
-
Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism
-
This is a latent theme in Plato's early and transitional dialogues; it comes closer to the surface in the Gorgias, where greater probative value is attached to discussion with diverse and more radical interlocutors. Cf. Terence Irwin, "Objectivity and Coercion in Plato's Dialectic," Revue Internationale de Philosophie, no. 156/157 (1986), pp. 49-74. The deliberative value of freedom of expression and diversity of opinion and lifestyle is an important strand in John Stuart Mill's arguments against censorship, moral legislation, and paternalism, especially in On Liberty; see my "Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism," Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 21 (1992), pp. 67-103.
-
(1992)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.21
, pp. 67-103
-
-
-
53
-
-
0040816097
-
Impersonal Friends
-
Jennifer Whiting objects to the colonial or imperial perspective that she thinks the egoist must impose on interpersonal concern; see Whiting, "Impersonal Friends," The Monist, vol. 74 (1991), pp. 9-10. Purely instrumental concern for another, of the sort to which Socrates seems to be committed, is colonial or imperial in some straightforwardly objectionable way. But where the egoist can justify derivative but noninstrumental concern for others, it is unclear what the moral objection to the egocentric perspective is.
-
(1991)
The Monist
, vol.74
, pp. 9-10
-
-
Whiting1
-
55
-
-
0346922084
-
-
note
-
In discussing the puzzle about whether to wish one's friend the good of divinity, Aristotle claims that one who cares about the friend for the friend's own sake would not wish this good on the friend, because the friend would not survive the transformation (NE 1159a5-11). This seems right. But persistence does not require fixity of character over time. Thus, while it is plausible that one should not wish on oneself or others the good of divinity, it is not plausible that one should not wish on oneself or others significant improvement of character; rather, this is just what friendship toward oneself and others requires. If so, then concern for someone, whether oneself or another, for his own sake requires neither similarity nor fixity of character. Insofar as Aristotle disagrees (esp. 1165b17-30), his claims seem problematic.
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
0003667667
-
-
supra note 28
-
Continuity must figure in a mentalistic account of identity if only to meet Reid's demand that any criterion of identity be transitive; see Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man (supra note 28), p. 358.
-
Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man
, pp. 358
-
-
Reid1
-
58
-
-
0348182699
-
-
Insofar as he conceives the common good universally, Green's view is perhaps closer to the Stoic than to the Aristotelian view. See Cicero, De Finibus iii 63. This aspect of the Stoic view is emphasized in Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), ch. 12.
-
De Finibus
, vol.3
, pp. 63
-
-
Cicero1
-
59
-
-
0003409985
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press, ch. 12
-
Insofar as he conceives the common good universally, Green's view is perhaps closer to the Stoic than to the Aristotelian view. See Cicero, De Finibus iii 63. This aspect of the Stoic view is emphasized in Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), ch. 12.
-
(1993)
The Morality of Happiness
-
-
Annas, J.1
-
60
-
-
0348182700
-
-
note
-
Part of Aristotle's justification for restricting citizenship assumes that manual labor is inimical to deliberation and virtue (Politics 1329a35-38). Dull and repetitive labor over which the worker has no control is menial and can only be instrumentally valuable to the extent that it furnishes life's necessities. But manual labor need not be menial in this way. As long as the farmer or artisan has responsibility for and control over production, distribution, and the organization of his labor process, manual labor can and will involve the exercise of important deliberative capacities. By Aristotelian criteria, meaningful manual labor ought to be an intrinsic good.
-
-
-
-
61
-
-
0003409985
-
-
ch. 12
-
The introduction of the proverbial remotest Mysian into discussions of the scope of ethical concern is discussed by Annas, The Morality of Happiness, ch. 12.
-
The Morality of Happiness
-
-
Annas1
-
62
-
-
0040622443
-
Self and Others
-
ed. David R. Cheney (London: George Allen and Unwin)
-
C. D. Broad calls this interpretation of common-sense morality "self-referential altruism"; see Broad, "Self and Others," in Broad's Critical Essays in Moral Philosophy, ed. David R. Cheney (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1971).
-
(1971)
Broad's Critical Essays in Moral Philosophy
-
-
Broad1
-
63
-
-
0346292010
-
-
note
-
I am not sure that this strong thesis can be reached from recognizably individualist premises; it may require fundamentally anti-individualist metaphysical claims, according to which persons are merely parts of an interpersonal organic whole and must view their own well-being in terms of the proper functioning of the whole of which they are a part.
-
-
-
-
64
-
-
0003437941
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press
-
The claims I sketch in this section for a principled accommodation of self-confined and other-regarding aspects of self-interest bear some resemblance (I'm not sure how much) to claims that Thomas Nagel and Samuel Scheffler make about the reconciliation of personal and impersonal moral demands; see Nagel, Equality and Partiality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), and Scheffler, Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), esp. ch. 8. One difference is that whereas Nagel and Scheffler are concerned about the accommodation of different aspects of morality, I am concerned about the accommodation of different aspects of self-interest. It is also worth noting apparent similarities between my claims and claims Hegel makes in The Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952), and Introduction to the Philosophy of History, trans. Leo Rauch (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988). My claim that proper self-realization requires partitioning one's life into differentially regulated spheres is like the Hegelian claim that it is only by participating in the three very differently organized spheres of family, civil society, and the state that one is able fully to realize oneself in the modern world. My claim that accommodation of these two aspects of self-interest is not always possible and would be a political accomplishment is like the Hegelian claim that reconciliation is a possibility only in the modern world. Unlike Hegel, however, I am not confident that full accommodation is yet possible.
-
(1991)
Equality and Partiality
-
-
Nagel1
-
65
-
-
0004256881
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press, esp. ch. 8
-
The claims I sketch in this section for a principled accommodation of self-confined and other-regarding aspects of self-interest bear some resemblance (I'm not sure how much) to claims that Thomas Nagel and Samuel Scheffler make about the reconciliation of personal and impersonal moral demands; see Nagel, Equality and Partiality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), and Scheffler, Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), esp. ch. 8. One difference is that whereas Nagel and Scheffler are concerned about the accommodation of different aspects of morality, I am concerned about the accommodation of different aspects of self-interest. It is also worth noting apparent similarities between my claims and claims Hegel makes in The Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952), and Introduction to the Philosophy of History, trans. Leo Rauch (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988). My claim that proper self-realization requires partitioning one's life into differentially regulated spheres is like the Hegelian claim that it is only by participating in the three very differently organized spheres of family, civil society, and the state that one is able fully to realize oneself in the modern world. My claim that accommodation of these two aspects of self-interest is not always possible and would be a political accomplishment is like the Hegelian claim that reconciliation is a possibility only in the modern world. Unlike Hegel, however, I am not confident that full accommodation is yet possible.
-
(1992)
Human Morality
-
-
Scheffler1
-
66
-
-
0004260323
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
The claims I sketch in this section for a principled accommodation of self-confined and other-regarding aspects of self-interest bear some resemblance (I'm not sure how much) to claims that Thomas Nagel and Samuel Scheffler make about the reconciliation of personal and impersonal moral demands; see Nagel, Equality and Partiality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), and Scheffler, Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), esp. ch. 8. One difference is that whereas Nagel and Scheffler are concerned about the accommodation of different aspects of morality, I am concerned about the accommodation of different aspects of self-interest. It is also worth noting apparent similarities between my claims and claims Hegel makes in The Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952), and Introduction to the Philosophy of History, trans. Leo Rauch (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988). My claim that proper self-realization requires partitioning one's life into differentially regulated spheres is like the Hegelian claim that it is only by participating in the three very differently organized spheres of family, civil society, and the state that one is able fully to realize oneself in the modern world. My claim that accommodation of these two aspects of self-interest is not always possible and would be a political accomplishment is like the Hegelian claim that reconciliation is a possibility only in the modern world. Unlike Hegel, however, I am not confident that full accommodation is yet possible.
-
(1952)
The Philosophy of Right
-
-
Knox, T.M.1
-
67
-
-
2042432797
-
-
Indianapolis: Hackett
-
The claims I sketch in this section for a principled accommodation of self-confined and other-regarding aspects of self-interest bear some resemblance (I'm not sure how much) to claims that Thomas Nagel and Samuel Scheffler make about the reconciliation of personal and impersonal moral demands; see Nagel, Equality and Partiality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), and Scheffler, Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), esp. ch. 8. One difference is that whereas Nagel and Scheffler are concerned about the accommodation of different aspects of morality, I am concerned about the accommodation of different aspects of self-interest. It is also worth noting apparent similarities between my claims and claims Hegel makes in The Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952), and Introduction to the Philosophy of History, trans. Leo Rauch (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988). My claim that proper self-realization requires partitioning one's life into differentially regulated spheres is like the Hegelian claim that it is only by participating in the three very differently organized spheres of family, civil society, and the state that one is able fully to realize oneself in the modern world. My claim that accommodation of these two aspects of self-interest is not always possible and would be a political accomplishment is like the Hegelian claim that reconciliation is a possibility only in the modern world. Unlike Hegel, however, I am not confident that full accommodation is yet possible.
-
(1988)
Introduction to the Philosophy of History
-
-
Rauch, L.1
|