메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 3, 1996, Pages 322-347

Russell's Power

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0039110089     PISSN: 00483931     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/004839319602600302     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (3)

References (47)
  • 1
    • 0003813131 scopus 로고
    • London: Unwin Books, The book was first published in 1938 with different pagination
    • References in parentheses in the text are to Bertrand Russell, Power: A New Social Analysis (London: Unwin Books, 1962). The book was first published in 1938 with different pagination.
    • (1962) Power: A New Social Analysis
    • Russell, B.1
  • 2
    • 1542691461 scopus 로고
    • London: Allen and Unwin
    • This psychological twist may be a peculiar projection of Russell's own psychology. He seems often to have been concerned with his own urges to power. For example, in his journal entry of 14 January 1905, he wrote, "I am in danger of getting a love of power - the power of the father confessor" (Bertrand Russell, Collected Papers, vol. 12 [London: Allen and Unwin, 1985], 27).
    • (1985) Collected Papers , vol.12 , pp. 27
    • Russell, B.1
  • 3
    • 1542796656 scopus 로고
    • Russell's Political and Economic Philosophy
    • Paul Arthur Schilpp, New York: Harper
    • McGill holds that, in Russell's account, the power drive is "an unnecessary and supernumerary assumption" (V. J. McGill, "Russell's Political and Economic Philosophy," in Paul Arthur Schilpp, The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, 3rd ed. [New York: Harper, [1944] 1963, 581-617, at 587).
    • (1944) The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, 3rd Ed. , pp. 581-617
    • McGill, V.J.1
  • 4
    • 0004295760 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper
    • Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, 3rd ed. (New York: Harper, [1942] 1950); Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper, 1957). Downs works out the implications of Russell's insight at book length. The implications are many and diverse. The insight pervades the works of Gaetano Mosca, Vilfredo Pareto, Robert Michels, and James Burnham. Pareto dismissed the "fiction" of popular representation with the guttural remark that "poppycock grinds no flour" ( Vilfredo Pareto, The Mind and Society, vol. 4 [New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1935 {translated by Andrew Bongiomo and Arthur Livingston}], 1569, §2244). Russell took credit for some of Burnham's views (Bertrand Russell, The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell, vol. 2 [Boston: Atlantic/Little, Brown, {1951} 1968], 302).
    • (1942) Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, 3rd Ed.
    • Schumpeter, J.A.1
  • 5
    • 0004157554 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper
    • Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, 3rd ed. (New York: Harper, [1942] 1950); Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper, 1957). Downs works out the implications of Russell's insight at book length. The implications are many and diverse. The insight pervades the works of Gaetano Mosca, Vilfredo Pareto, Robert Michels, and James Burnham. Pareto dismissed the "fiction" of popular representation with the guttural remark that "poppycock grinds no flour" ( Vilfredo Pareto, The Mind and Society, vol. 4 [New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1935 {translated by Andrew Bongiomo and Arthur Livingston}], 1569, §2244). Russell took credit for some of Burnham's views (Bertrand Russell, The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell, vol. 2 [Boston: Atlantic/Little, Brown, {1951} 1968], 302).
    • (1957) An Economic Theory of Democracy
    • Downs, A.1
  • 6
    • 85033753471 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harcourt, Brace, {translated by Andrew Bongiomo and Arthur Livingston}, §2244
    • Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, 3rd ed. (New York: Harper, [1942] 1950); Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper, 1957). Downs works out the implications of Russell's insight at book length. The implications are many and diverse. The insight pervades the works of Gaetano Mosca, Vilfredo Pareto, Robert Michels, and James Burnham. Pareto dismissed the "fiction" of popular representation with the guttural remark that "poppycock grinds no flour" ( Vilfredo Pareto, The Mind and Society, vol. 4 [New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1935 {translated by Andrew Bongiomo and Arthur Livingston}], 1569, §2244). Russell took credit for some of Burnham's views (Bertrand Russell, The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell, vol. 2 [Boston: Atlantic/Little, Brown, {1951} 1968], 302).
    • (1935) The Mind and Society , vol.4 , pp. 1569
    • Pareto, V.1
  • 7
    • 1542691462 scopus 로고
    • Boston: Atlantic/Little, Brown
    • Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, 3rd ed. (New York: Harper, [1942] 1950); Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper, 1957). Downs works out the implications of Russell's insight at book length. The implications are many and diverse. The insight pervades the works of Gaetano Mosca, Vilfredo Pareto, Robert Michels, and James Burnham. Pareto dismissed the "fiction" of popular representation with the guttural remark that "poppycock grinds no flour" ( Vilfredo Pareto, The Mind and Society, vol. 4 [New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1935 {translated by Andrew Bongiomo and Arthur Livingston}], 1569, §2244). Russell took credit for some of Burnham's views (Bertrand Russell, The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell, vol. 2 [Boston: Atlantic/Little, Brown, {1951} 1968], 302).
    • (1951) The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell , vol.2 , pp. 302
    • Russell, B.1
  • 8
    • 0004305444 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Mancur Olson, Jr., The Logic of Collective Action (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1965); Russell Hardin, Collective Action (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982).
    • (1965) The Logic of Collective Action
    • Olson Jr., M.1
  • 9
    • 0004174070 scopus 로고
    • Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press
    • Mancur Olson, Jr., The Logic of Collective Action (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1965); Russell Hardin, Collective Action (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982).
    • (1982) Collective Action
    • Hardin, R.1
  • 10
    • 0010840477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Russell, Autobiography, 302. In his analysis of the problem of the equality of political power, Christiano generally seems to agree with Russell that equality of power is a more compelling concern of social justice than is equality of wealth and income ( Thomas Christiano, The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory [Boulder, CO: Westview, 1996]).
    • Autobiography , pp. 302
    • Russell1
  • 11
    • 0004108132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boulder, CO: Westview
    • Russell, Autobiography, 302. In his analysis of the problem of the equality of political power, Christiano generally seems to agree with Russell that equality of power is a more compelling concern of social justice than is equality of wealth and income ( Thomas Christiano, The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory [Boulder, CO: Westview, 1996]).
    • (1996) The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory
    • Christiano, T.1
  • 12
    • 64249122888 scopus 로고
    • London: Allen and Unwin
    • Bertrand Russell, Freedom and Organization (London: Allen and Unwin, 1934) (published as Freedom from Organization [New York: Norton], 144). This comment is in keeping with his view of Hitler before the writing of Power that Hitler was just another politician. See further discussion in the concluding section.
    • (1934) Freedom and Organization
    • Russell, B.1
  • 13
    • 85033752721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • published as [New York: Norton]
    • Bertrand Russell, Freedom and Organization (London: Allen and Unwin, 1934) (published as Freedom from Organization [New York: Norton], 144). This comment is in keeping with his view of Hitler before the writing of Power that Hitler was just another politician. See further discussion in the concluding section.
    • Freedom from Organization , pp. 144
  • 15
    • 1542691456 scopus 로고
    • Power, Political
    • edited by Edwin R. A. Seligman and Alvin Johnson New York: Macmillan
    • Hermann Heller, "Power, Political," in Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences, vol. 12, edited by Edwin R. A. Seligman and Alvin Johnson (New York: Macmillan, 1933), 300-5.
    • (1933) Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences , vol.12 , pp. 300-305
    • Heller, H.1
  • 18
    • 0039905471 scopus 로고
    • New York: Hill & Wang
    • Ryan remarks, "Like many writers of the 1930s, Russell was more than a little obsessed with the figure of the aviator" (Alan Ryan, Bertrand Russell: A Political Life [New York: Hill & Wang, 1988], 151).
    • (1988) Bertrand Russell: A Political Life , pp. 151
    • Ryan, A.1
  • 19
    • 0006294633 scopus 로고
    • The Ghosts of Mrs. Gandhi
    • 17 July
    • Amitav Ghosh, "The Ghosts of Mrs. Gandhi," The New Yorker (17 July 1995): 35-41.
    • (1995) The New Yorker , pp. 35-41
    • Ghosh, A.1
  • 20
    • 84972700447 scopus 로고
    • Hobbesian Political Order
    • May
    • See, further, Russell Hardin, "Hobbesian Political Order," Political Theory 19 (May 1991): 156-80, esp. 170-71.
    • (1991) Political Theory , vol.19 , pp. 156-180
    • Hardin, R.1
  • 21
    • 1542586576 scopus 로고
    • Sanction and Obligation
    • July
    • Russell Hardin, "Sanction and Obligation," The Monist 68 (July 1985): 403-18.
    • (1985) The Monist , vol.68 , pp. 403-418
    • Hardin, R.1
  • 22
    • 0004168676 scopus 로고
    • On the Concept of Political Power
    • edited by Roderick Bell, David V. Edwards, and R. Harrison Wagner New York: Free Press, [essay originally published 1963]
    • Talcott Parsons, "On the Concept of Political Power," in Political Power: A Reader in Theory and Research, edited by Roderick Bell, David V. Edwards, and R. Harrison Wagner (New York: Free Press, 1969 [essay originally published 1963]), 251-84, at 255-62.
    • (1969) Political Power: A Reader in Theory and Research , pp. 251-284
    • Parsons, T.1
  • 25
    • 85033756406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • published in England as with different pagination
    • Bertrand Russell, Why Men Fight: A Method of Abolishing the International Duel (New York: Century, 1916 [published in England as Principles of Social Reconstruction with different pagination]), 72-73.
    • Principles of Social Reconstruction , pp. 72-73
  • 26
    • 85033738530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The value of money can similarly be increased by our activities, but the quantity of it can only be increased by credible institutions, such as banks and governments.
  • 29
    • 84886358463 scopus 로고
    • A Free Man's Worship
    • Bertrand Russell, New York: Doubleday, n.d.
    • Bertrand Russell, "A Free Man's Worship," in Bertrand Russell, Mysticism and Logic (New York: Doubleday, [1917] n.d.), 44-54, at 46-48.
    • (1917) Mysticism and Logic , pp. 44-54
    • Russell, B.1
  • 31
    • 84959582296 scopus 로고
    • A Method for Evaluating the Distribution of Power in a Committee System
    • L. S. Shapley and Martin Shubik, "A Method for Evaluating the Distribution of Power in a Committee System," American Political Science Review 48 (1954): 787-92.
    • (1954) American Political Science Review , vol.48 , pp. 787-792
    • Shapley, L.S.1    Shubik, M.2
  • 32
    • 0003590499 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • The term "strategy" does not appear in the indexes of Alan Donagan, Choice: The Essential Element in Human Action (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1987); Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); or Ernest LePore and Brian McLaughlin, eds., Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell, 1985). Nor is there any term that is an apparent relative of strategic interaction. Davidson does discuss Mill's account of cause and problems in decision theory, including that of the ur-game theorists John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, but he does not address the problem of strategic interaction (Davidson, Essays, 149-62). Bratman discusses what one might call strategic interactions between one's present and one's future selves as the ground for making plans to constrain future actions ( Michael Bratman, "Davidson's Theory of Intention," in LePore and McLaughlin, Actions and Events, 14-28). Elster explicitly discusses strategic interaction but does not relate it to action theory ( Jon Elster, "The Nature and Scope of Rational Choice Explanation," in ibid., 60-72). I may do the injustice of oversight to one or more of these books. In any case, it need be seen as no criticism of them that they do not address social action in strategic contexts. Even the simplest of categories of action is hard to analyze.
    • (1987) Choice: The Essential Element in Human Action
    • Donagan, A.1
  • 33
    • 0004232285 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The term "strategy" does not appear in the indexes of Alan Donagan, Choice: The Essential Element in Human Action (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1987); Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); or Ernest LePore and Brian McLaughlin, eds., Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell, 1985). Nor is there any term that is an apparent relative of strategic interaction. Davidson does discuss Mill's account of cause and problems in decision theory, including that of the ur-game theorists John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, but he does not address the problem of strategic interaction (Davidson, Essays, 149-62). Bratman discusses what one might call strategic interactions between one's present and one's future selves as the ground for making plans to constrain future actions ( Michael Bratman, "Davidson's Theory of Intention," in LePore and McLaughlin, Actions and Events, 14-28). Elster explicitly discusses strategic interaction but does not relate it to action theory ( Jon Elster, "The Nature and Scope of Rational Choice Explanation," in ibid., 60-72). I may do the injustice of oversight to one or more of these books. In any case, it need be seen as no criticism of them that they do not address social action in strategic contexts. Even the simplest of categories of action is hard to analyze.
    • (1980) Essays on Actions and Events
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 34
    • 0039378818 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • The term "strategy" does not appear in the indexes of Alan Donagan, Choice: The Essential Element in Human Action (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1987); Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); or Ernest LePore and Brian McLaughlin, eds., Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell, 1985). Nor is there any term that is an apparent relative of strategic interaction. Davidson does discuss Mill's account of cause and problems in decision theory, including that of the ur-game theorists John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, but he does not address the problem of strategic interaction (Davidson, Essays, 149-62). Bratman discusses what one might call strategic interactions between one's present and one's future selves as the ground for making plans to constrain future actions ( Michael Bratman, "Davidson's Theory of Intention," in LePore and McLaughlin, Actions and Events, 14-28). Elster explicitly discusses strategic interaction but does not relate it to action theory ( Jon Elster, "The Nature and Scope of Rational Choice Explanation," in ibid., 60-72). I may do the injustice of oversight to one or more of these books. In any case, it need be seen as no criticism of them that they do not address social action in strategic contexts. Even the simplest of categories of action is hard to analyze.
    • (1985) Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson
    • LePore, E.1    McLaughlin, B.2
  • 35
    • 84880427516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The term "strategy" does not appear in the indexes of Alan Donagan, Choice: The Essential Element in Human Action (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1987); Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); or Ernest LePore and Brian McLaughlin, eds., Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell, 1985). Nor is there any term that is an apparent relative of strategic interaction. Davidson does discuss Mill's account of cause and problems in decision theory, including that of the ur-game theorists John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, but he does not address the problem of strategic interaction (Davidson, Essays, 149-62). Bratman discusses what one might call strategic interactions between one's present and one's future selves as the ground for making plans to constrain future actions ( Michael Bratman, "Davidson's Theory of Intention," in LePore and McLaughlin, Actions and Events, 14-28). Elster explicitly discusses strategic interaction but does not relate it to action theory ( Jon Elster, "The Nature and Scope of Rational Choice Explanation," in ibid., 60-72). I may do the injustice of oversight to one or more of these books. In any case, it need be seen as no criticism of them that they do not address social action in strategic contexts. Even the simplest of categories of action is hard to analyze.
    • Essays , pp. 149-162
    • Davidson1
  • 36
    • 61049317120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Davidson's Theory of Intention
    • LePore and McLaughlin
    • The term "strategy" does not appear in the indexes of Alan Donagan, Choice: The Essential Element in Human Action (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1987); Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); or Ernest LePore and Brian McLaughlin, eds., Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell, 1985). Nor is there any term that is an apparent relative of strategic interaction. Davidson does discuss Mill's account of cause and problems in decision theory, including that of the ur-game theorists John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, but he does not address the problem of strategic interaction (Davidson, Essays, 149-62). Bratman discusses what one might call strategic interactions between one's present and one's future selves as the ground for making plans to constrain future actions ( Michael Bratman, "Davidson's Theory of Intention," in LePore and McLaughlin, Actions and Events, 14-28). Elster explicitly discusses strategic interaction but does not relate it to action theory ( Jon Elster, "The Nature and Scope of Rational Choice Explanation," in ibid., 60-72). I may do the injustice of oversight to one or more of these books. In any case, it need be seen as no criticism of them that they do not address social action in strategic contexts. Even the simplest of categories of action is hard to analyze.
    • Actions and Events , pp. 14-28
    • Bratman, M.1
  • 37
    • 0001776316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Nature and Scope of Rational Choice Explanation
    • The term "strategy" does not appear in the indexes of Alan Donagan, Choice: The Essential Element in Human Action (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1987); Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); or Ernest LePore and Brian McLaughlin, eds., Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell, 1985). Nor is there any term that is an apparent relative of strategic interaction. Davidson does discuss Mill's account of cause and problems in decision theory, including that of the ur-game theorists John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, but he does not address the problem of strategic interaction (Davidson, Essays, 149-62). Bratman discusses what one might call strategic interactions between one's present and one's future selves as the ground for making plans to constrain future actions ( Michael Bratman, "Davidson's Theory of Intention," in LePore and McLaughlin, Actions and Events, 14-28). Elster explicitly discusses strategic interaction but does not relate it to action theory ( Jon Elster, "The Nature and Scope of Rational Choice Explanation," in ibid., 60-72). I may do the injustice of oversight to one or more of these books. In any case, it need be seen as no criticism of them that they do not address social action in strategic contexts. Even the simplest of categories of action is hard to analyze.
    • Actions and Events , pp. 60-72
    • Elster, J.1
  • 38
    • 1542586577 scopus 로고
    • Bertrand Russell on Power
    • Frank H. Knight, "Bertrand Russell on Power," Ethics 49 (1939): 253-85, at 262.
    • (1939) Ethics , vol.49 , pp. 253-285
    • Knight, F.H.1
  • 39
    • 0001356448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Olson, Logic of Collective Action; Russell Hardin, "Collective Action as an Agreeable n-Prisoner's Dilemma," Behavioral Science 16 (September 1971): 472-81.
    • Logic of Collective Action
    • Olson1
  • 40
    • 0001356448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Collective Action as an Agreeable n-Prisoner's Dilemma
    • September
    • Olson, Logic of Collective Action; Russell Hardin, "Collective Action as an Agreeable n-Prisoner's Dilemma," Behavioral Science 16 (September 1971): 472-81.
    • (1971) Behavioral Science , vol.16 , pp. 472-481
    • Hardin, R.1
  • 42
    • 0004228162 scopus 로고
    • New York: Liveright
    • Bertrand Russell, Marriage and Morals (New York: Liveright, [1929] 1970), 298.
    • (1929) Marriage and Morals , pp. 298
    • Russell, B.1
  • 44
    • 0001981344 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • He presumably would have approved the omission of his social criticism from the volume on his philosophy for the series, "The Arguments of the Philosophers" (R. M. Sainsbury, Russell [London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979]).
    • (1979) Russell
    • Sainsbury, R.M.1
  • 47
    • 1542586553 scopus 로고
    • Engaged Philosopher
    • 2 February
    • Stuart Hampshire, "Engaged Philosopher," New York Review of Books (2 February 1989): 7-9, at 9.
    • (1989) New York Review of Books , pp. 7-9
    • Hampshire, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.