메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 106, Issue 2, 1996, Pages 297-326

Internalism and the good for a person

(1)  Rosati, Connie S a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0039088105     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233619     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (83)

References (88)
  • 1
    • 0039096265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • The label comes from Stephen Darwall, who distinguishes existence internalism from what he calls "judgment internalism." According to judgment internalism, a necessary connection exists between motivation and sincere avowal of a normative claim. See Stephen L. Darwall, Impartial Reason (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1983), pp. 54-55.
    • (1983) Impartial Reason , pp. 54-55
    • Darwall, S.L.1
  • 2
    • 0003687747 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • turn to the connection between existence and judgment internalism later. See David O. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), p. 40,
    • (1989) Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics , pp. 40
    • Brink, D.O.1
  • 3
    • 0345837111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Ought' and Motivation
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • for a related distinction between what he calls "agent internalism" and "appraiser internalism." For discussions of internalism with respect to obligation and morality, see W. D. Falk, "'Ought' and Motivation," in Ought, Reasons, and Morality (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1986), pp. 21-41;
    • (1986) Ought, Reasons, and Morality , pp. 21-41
    • Falk, W.D.1
  • 4
    • 0041409346 scopus 로고
    • Motivation and Obligation in Recent Moral Philosophy
    • ed. Kenneth E. Goodpaster Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press
    • William K. Frankena, "Motivation and Obligation in Recent Moral Philosophy," in Perspectives on Morality: Essays of William K. Frankena, ed. Kenneth E. Goodpaster (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1976), pp. 49-73;
    • (1976) Perspectives on Morality: Essays of William K. Frankena , pp. 49-73
    • Frankena, W.K.1
  • 5
    • 0345769926 scopus 로고
    • Moral Reasons and Reasons to be Moral
    • ed. Alvin I. Goldman and Jaegwon Kim Dordrecht: Reidel
    • Kurt Baier, "Moral Reasons and Reasons to be Moral," in Values and Morals, ed. Alvin I. Goldman and Jaegwon Kim (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978), pp. 231-56;
    • (1978) Values and Morals , pp. 231-256
    • Baier, K.1
  • 6
    • 85056559025 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Thomas Nagel, The Possibility of Altruism (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1970);
    • (1970) The Possibility of Altruism
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 7
    • 84930557608 scopus 로고
    • Internalism and Speaker Relativism
    • Brink, chap. 3; James Drier, "Internalism and Speaker Relativism," Ethics 101 (1990): 6-26;
    • (1990) Ethics , vol.101 , pp. 6-26
    • Drier, J.1
  • 8
    • 0040280001 scopus 로고
    • Autonomist Internalism and the Justification of Morals
    • and Stephen L. Darwall, "Autonomist Internalism and the Justification of Morals," Nous 24 (1990): 257-68 ,
    • (1990) Nous , vol.24 , pp. 257-268
    • Darwall, S.L.1
  • 9
    • 0346291964 scopus 로고
    • Internalism and Agency
    • "Internalism and Agency," Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 155-74,
    • (1992) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.6 , pp. 155-174
  • 10
    • 84974126689 scopus 로고
    • Motive and Obligation in the British Moralists
    • and "Motive and Obligation in the British Moralists," Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1989): 133-50.
    • (1989) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.7 , pp. 133-150
  • 12
    • 0003343064 scopus 로고
    • Internal and External Reasons
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • and Bernard Williams, "Internal and External Reasons," in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1981), pp. 101-13.
    • (1981) Moral Luck , pp. 101-113
    • Williams, B.1
  • 13
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • The relevant motivation is typically taken to be a desire (first or second order) or a preference for a given thing. Obviously, if internalism is to be a substantial thesis, ideal conditions cannot include those in which a person has the information that X is good for her. For recent proponents of accounts of a person's good that satisfy internalism see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 395-433;
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 395-433
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 15
  • 16
    • 0000186867 scopus 로고
    • Facts and Values
    • "Facts and Values," Philosophical Topics 14 (1986): 5-31,
    • (1986) Philosophical Topics , vol.14 , pp. 5-31
  • 17
    • 84974050699 scopus 로고
    • Naturalism and Prescriptivity
    • and "Naturalism and Prescriptivity," Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1990): 151-74;
    • (1990) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.7 , pp. 151-174
  • 18
    • 0004274311 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, chap. 2
    • David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), chap. 2;
    • (1986) Morals by Agreement
    • Gauthier, D.1
  • 19
    • 0003214842 scopus 로고
    • Morality and the Theory of Rational Behavior
    • ed. Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • John C. Harsanyi, "Morality and the Theory of Rational Behavior," in Utilitarianism and Beyond, ed. Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 39-62;
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and Beyond , pp. 39-62
    • Harsanyi, J.C.1
  • 21
    • 85033051756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Darwall endorses Rawls's account of a person's good in Impartial Reason, pt. 2.
    • Impartial Reason , Issue.2 PART
  • 22
    • 0003264088 scopus 로고
    • Dispositional Theories of Value
    • For a more recent dispositional theory of value that endorses internalism, see David Lewis, "Dispositional Theories of Value," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 63 (1989): 113-37.
    • (1989) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.63 SUPPL. VOL , pp. 113-137
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 24
    • 79954660624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is Motivation Internal to Value?
    • ed. Georg Meggle, Christoph Fehige, and Ulla Wessels (in press)
    • David Velleman finds a different intuitive basis for internalism in the subjectivist thought that value can exist only in virtue of beings for whom things can matter. See J. David Velleman, "Is Motivation Internal to Value?" in Preferences, ed. Georg Meggle, Christoph Fehige, and Ulla Wessels (in press). I prefer to treat this consideration as suggesting what I will latter describe as a metaphysical argument for internalism.
    • Preferences
    • Velleman, J.D.1
  • 25
    • 85033042667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By 'subjectivist theories', I mean theories according to which a person's good either consists in or crucially depends upon certain positive psychological states or proattitudes, such as pleasure or (actual or counterfactual) desires. Here I roughly follow Brink, pp. 220-21.
  • 27
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic, See, e.g., Griffin, pp. 9-10
    • Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic, 1974), p. 42. See, e.g., Griffin, pp. 9-10. Curiously, even some who seem to reject internalism make arguments that rely upon it. See Brink's use of Nozick's example to reject hedonism (Brink, pp. 223-24).
    • (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 42
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 28
    • 0141946657 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle and the Ideal Life
    • For example, a long tradition of scholarship criticizes Aristotle's intellectualist picture in book 10 of Nichomachean Ethics as too narrow an account of the human good. For a recent defense of Aristotle's conception(s) of happiness, see Gavin Lawrence, "Aristotle and the Ideal Life," Philosophical Review 102 (1993): 1-34.
    • (1993) Philosophical Review , vol.102 , pp. 1-34
    • Lawrence, G.1
  • 29
    • 0004264902 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Critics of internalism about a person's good fall into two camps. Those in the first camp reject internalism about goodness entirely. It includes externalists who, like Moore, hold a nonnaturalistic account of good, proponents of what Derek Parfit calls an "objective list theory," and certain perfectionists. See G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903), esp. pp. 81-85;
    • (1903) Principia Ethica , pp. 81-85
    • Moore, G.E.1
  • 30
    • 26444540036 scopus 로고
    • That Simple, Indefinable, Nonnatural Property 'Good'
    • Panayot Butchvarov, "That Simple, Indefinable, Nonnatural Property 'Good'," Review of Metaphysics 36 (1982): 51-75;
    • (1982) Review of Metaphysics , vol.36 , pp. 51-75
    • Butchvarov, P.1
  • 31
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon
    • Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon, 1984), pp. 499-500;
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons , pp. 499-500
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 32
    • 0038844615 scopus 로고
    • 'Good' and 'Good For'
    • Thomas Hurka, "'Good' and 'Good For'," Mind 96 (1987): 71-73,
    • (1987) Mind , vol.96 , pp. 71-73
    • Hurka, T.1
  • 33
    • 0003478473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • and Perfectionism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), see pp. 17, 27.
    • (1993) Perfectionism , pp. 17
  • 34
    • 0003478473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The second camp includes objectivists and perfectionists who may accept internalism about the good for humans while rejecting internalism about an individual's good. Some perfectionists might hold, for instance, that something can be good for human beings only if it can motivate or matter to most (normal) humans, given their essential nature, while rejecting that something can be good for an individual only if it can motivate or matter to her. On the latter view, the person who cannot care about the human good is simply someone who will miss out on her good. For a discussion of the various forms that perfectionism can take, see Hurka, Perfectionism.
    • Perfectionism
    • Hurka1
  • 36
    • 85033036921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I here follow an idea of Velleman's. He construes internalism, however, as requiring a relation to affect. I talk in terms of motivation broadly construed and proattitudes, because the term 'affect' may have connotations of emotion or feeling that are unnecessary to the relationship between a person and her good that internalism seeks to capture. Moreover, 'affect' suggests a passive state and so may not capture the range of relevant attitudes.
  • 37
    • 85033044648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Velleman characterizes internalism along basically these lines. See his discussion for a distinction between two senses of a person's good and two corresponding versions of internalism.
  • 38
    • 85033063858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I talk in terms of what a person would want under appropriate conditions, rather than what she could want, since the canonical way of testing whether a person could want X under C is to put her in C and see if she would want it.
  • 39
    • 0040622644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n. 15; and Griffin, pp. 11-12
    • On the need for this distinction, see Railton, "Moral Realism," p. 174, n. 15; and Griffin, pp. 11-12.
    • Moral Realism , pp. 174
    • Railton1
  • 40
    • 85033039530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am indebted here to David Velleman, who originally suggested to me the need to incorporate something like ordinary optimal conditions. The qualification 'self-interestedly' does not preclude from a person's good concern for others or for larger projects, but merely distinguishes between a person's moral concerns and her concerns from a personal standpoint. By 'rationally' I mean simply that she makes no errors in reasoning.
  • 41
    • 85033046139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As noted earlier, my specification of ordinary optimal conditions is not intended to be complete. Those conditions could, for instance, include attention to more information than is readily available. Even so, for reasons already given, the information required to assess counterfactual conditions is limited. The nature of the inquiry suggests as well that the conditions under which a person assesses remote counterfactual conditions need not be otherwise extraordinary. A person need not, for example, have phenomenal powers of reason, memory, or imagination.
  • 43
    • 0040622644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Moral Realism," pp. 177-78.
    • Moral Realism , pp. 177-178
  • 44
    • 26444563916 scopus 로고
    • Naturalism, Normativity, and the Open Question Argument
    • I have elsewhere raised difficulties for full information, dispositional theories of a person's good such as Railton's. See my "Naturalism, Normativity, and the Open Question Argument," Nous 29 (1995): 46-70,
    • (1995) Nous , vol.29 , pp. 46-70
  • 45
    • 84919475163 scopus 로고
    • Persons, Perspectives, and Full Information Accounts of the Good
    • and "Persons, Perspectives, and Full Information Accounts of the Good," Ethics 105 (1995): 296-325.
    • (1995) Ethics , vol.105 , pp. 296-325
  • 46
    • 0040067309 scopus 로고
    • Brandt's Definition of 'Good'
    • Also see J. David Velleman, "Brandt's Definition of 'Good'," Philosophical Review 97 (1988): 353-71. A theory of the good for a person need not be dispositional to satisfy internalism.
    • (1988) Philosophical Review , vol.97 , pp. 353-371
    • Velleman, J.D.1
  • 47
    • 85033059090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As far as I can tell, only the fourth argument has been explicitly offered as a defense of internalism about a person's good. The other arguments I here consider are suggested either by the approaches that theorists have taken to defending particular accounts of a person's good or by arguments given in support of internalism with respect to other areas of normative assessment.
  • 48
    • 0002037012 scopus 로고
    • Toward Fin de Siécle Ethics: Some Trends
    • For discussion, see Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton, "Toward Fin de Siécle Ethics: Some Trends," Philosophical Review 101 (1992): 115-89, pp. 116-20.
    • (1992) Philosophical Review , vol.101 , pp. 115-189
    • Darwall, S.1    Gibbard, A.2    Railton, P.3
  • 49
    • 85033059135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As Drier observes, judgment internalism can be stated in an implausibly strong form (pp. 9-14). He endorses "modest internalism," according to which necessarily "in normal contexts a person has some motivation to promote what he believes to be good" (p. 14). Whereas externalism holds that moral judgments typically motivate due to external factors, modest internalism holds that an internal connection exists between sincerely asserting a moral judgment and being motivated to act, though the necessary connection holds only for normal contexts (p. 11). I here add this qualification to my depiction of judgment internalism.
  • 52
    • 0039096265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arguments from judgment to existence internalism also surface with regard to other areas of normative assessment, although those who make them do not always clearly distinguish between these forms of internalism. Darwall seems to presuppose such an argument in constructing the second half of the Humean case for internalism about reasons (Impartial Reason, pp. 56-57). Nagel seems to suggest that existence internalism about morality can be supported by appeal to judgment internalism (p. 7). And Drier argues from judgment internalism to a form of speaker relativism about morality (p. 7).
    • Impartial Reason , pp. 56-57
  • 53
    • 85033034976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished paper, Rutgers University
    • I am indebted here to D. Gene Witmer's argument for an internalist connection akin to what I have called "two-tier internalism" in his "Normative Realism: An Eclectic Dispositional Analysis" (unpublished paper, Rutgers University). I had originally thought that the second link to motivation provides a necessary condition on counterfactual conditions because it is needed to capture recommending force. But Witmer's arguments convinced me that the need is more generally due to the action-guiding character of normative language. The argument I present here for the double link thus follows his argument in this regard. I am still inclined for various reasons, however, to emphasize recommending force and the guidance of attitude over that of action.
    • Normative Realism: An Eclectic Dispositional Analysis
    • Witmer, D.G.1
  • 55
    • 0007082151 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • R. B. Perry, General Theory of Value (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1954), p. 125.
    • (1954) General Theory of Value , pp. 125
    • Perry, R.B.1
  • 56
    • 0040067337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a strikingly similar, though more careful, passage which offers this same basic argument for subjectivism, see Railton, "Facts and Values," p. 9.
    • Facts and Values , pp. 9
    • Railton1
  • 57
    • 0039096265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The argument presented here follows an argument that Darwall has offered (and apparently endorsed) in explaining Hume's internalism about reasons (Impartial Reason, pp. 55-57). In "Internalism and Agency," however, Darwall distinguishes between "constitutive internalism" and "non-constitutive internalism." While both are forms of existence internalism, only constitutive internalism holds that "motivation is a constituent of ethical facts themselves" (p. 157). And so only constitutive internalism, Darwall argues, can explain how ethical knowledge necessarily motivates: such knowledge is itself of motives "deriving from the agent's practical reasoning" (p. 158). Also see Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, pp. 176-77.
    • Impartial Reason , pp. 55-57
  • 58
    • 85033047614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Some who reject internalism may agree that at least some value can exist only if there are creatures for whom things can matter, while denying that goodness must be a motivational property. On Moore's view, the organic unities that have the greatest intrinsic value require the existence of creatures who are capable of aesthetic appreciation and friendship. But even these wholes are made good by the presence of a nonnatural property.
  • 59
    • 0003746531 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth, England: Penguin, chap. 1
    • J. L. Mackie offers the classic criticisms of this picture of value in Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Harmondsworth, England: Penguin, 1978), chap. 1.
    • (1978) Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong
    • Mackie, J.L.1
  • 60
    • 0009386076 scopus 로고
    • Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?
    • Sensibility theories have been developed chiefly with respect to moral value. See John McDowell, "Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?" Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 52 (1978): 13-29,
    • (1978) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.52 SUPPL. VOL , pp. 13-29
    • McDowell, J.1
  • 61
    • 0009036844 scopus 로고
    • Values and Secondary Qualities
    • London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • "Values and Secondary Qualities," in Morality and Objectivity, ed. Ted Honderich (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1985),
    • (1985) Morality and Objectivity
    • Honderich, T.1
  • 62
    • 85033047064 scopus 로고
    • Truth and Projection in Ethics
    • University of Kansas
    • and "Truth and Projection in Ethics," Lindley Lecture (University of Kansas, 1987).
    • (1987) Lindley Lecture
  • 63
    • 24944436832 scopus 로고
    • "A Sensible Subjectivism," "Truth as Predicated of Moral Judgments," and "Truth, Invention, and the Meaning of Life"
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • Also see David Wiggins, "A Sensible Subjectivism," "Truth as Predicated of Moral Judgments," and "Truth, Invention, and the Meaning of Life," in Needs, Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987), pp. 185-214, 139-84, 87-138.
    • (1987) Needs, Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value , pp. 185-214
    • Wiggins, D.1
  • 64
    • 0003541293 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • For critical discussion of sensibility theories, see Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, pp. 152-65; and Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990), p. 186.
    • (1990) Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment , pp. 186
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 65
    • 0004247732 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Hackett
    • John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1979), p. 34.
    • (1979) Utilitarianism , pp. 34
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 66
    • 85033066274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill, p. 34
    • Mill, p. 34.
  • 67
    • 85033068566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Griffin sometimes talks as if he might endorse such an argument, though he does not formulate it explicitly (pp. 26-31).
  • 68
    • 85033056489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • One might try to support appeals to the experience of others by connecting them to an account of human nature together with an account of how our nature gives us a particular good. But surely even such an approach must take account of variations in individual natures.
  • 69
    • 85033055398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Brandt defines the notion 'good' rather than the notion 'good for a person', but since different persons may rationally desire different things, his definition is better understood as one of goodness for a person.
  • 70
    • 85033059291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Brandt does not say this explicitly, but see his defense of his reforming definition of 'morally right' (pp. 244-45).
  • 71
    • 85033054917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., pp. 154-60. Railton makes similar arguments. See n. 17.
  • 72
    • 0345837111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Falk's defense of internalism about the moral 'ought' similarly relies on internalism about practical reasons. See his "Ought' and Motivation";
    • Ought' and Motivation
  • 74
    • 85033053714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The way in which internalists about a person's good defend their accounts suggests that they have implicitly recognized this. See, again, Brandt, pp. 154-60. Also see Griffin, pp. 12-14.
  • 75
    • 79954660624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See his "Is Motivation Internal to Value?" More specifically, Velleman argues that simple internalism is derivable from the principle that 'ought' can imply 'can'. Velleman suggests that an implication of this derivation is that simple internalism may be the strongest version of internalism that is true.
    • Is Motivation Internal to Value?
  • 76
    • 85033045926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In this way, one of two things is possible: first, she may be able over time to induce in herself a direct concern for the thing itself; second, she may be motivated to submit to a procedure of the sort that would bring her to care about what she would care about under those conditions.
  • 77
    • 85033059565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This view can explain, in keeping with the principle that 'ought' implies 'can', why some nomologically realizable conditions are not candidates for assessing whether something can be a part of a person's good, whereas some nomologically unrealizable conditions may be relevant. No person can be fully informed and rational, yet what a person would care about for herself while under such conditions at least seems relevant.
  • 78
    • 85033036273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Darwall has argued that there is a distinct autonomist rationale for internalism about morality, though the rationale he considers differs from the one suggested here. See "Autonomist Internalism and the Justification of Morals," p. 263.
    • Autonomist Internalism and the Justification of Morals , pp. 263
  • 81
    • 0001501318 scopus 로고
    • Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory
    • Rawls, "Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory," Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 515-72, p. 525,
    • (1980) Journal of Philosophy , vol.77 , pp. 515-572
    • Rawls1
  • 83
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • and Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), pp. 72-77.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 72-77
  • 84
    • 0004187493 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • An autonomy-based rationale for internalism is also suggested by David Velleman's account of an agent's values in Practical Reflection (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1989). According to Velleman, agents have intellectual motives that incline them toward preferring and performing only those actions that they find intelligible. Agents are autonomous insofar as these intellectual motives enable them to "restrain, redirect, and reinforce [their] other motives for acting, in accordance with [their] own conception of those motives" (p. 173). The search for values consists in the search for intelligible desires, ones that can be part of a standing self-conception that enables us to act in ways that we can both anticipate and understand. This picture suggests that something can be a value for a person only if it can be intelligible to her and thereby enter into her self-governance. But presumably a person can find a desire intelligible only if she is capable of caring about having it.
    • (1989) Practical Reflection
    • Velleman, D.1
  • 85
    • 0004651070 scopus 로고
    • Moral Relativism
    • For efforts to derive moral relativism from internalism, see Drier; and Gilbert Harman, "Moral Relativism," Philosophical Review 85 (1975): 3-22,
    • (1975) Philosophical Review , vol.85 , pp. 3-22
    • Harman, G.1
  • 86
    • 26444433522 scopus 로고
    • Metaphysical Realism and Moral Relativism: Reflections on Hilary Putnam's Reason, Truth, and History
    • and "Metaphysical Realism and Moral Relativism: Reflections on Hilary Putnam's Reason, Truth, and History," Journal of Philosophy 79 (1982): 568-75.
    • (1982) Journal of Philosophy , vol.79 , pp. 568-575
  • 87
    • 85033034821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I borrow this way of expressing the point from Gibbard, p. 12.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.