메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 53, Issue 1, 1999, Pages 99-128

Schelling's critique of Hegel's science of logic

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0038932640     PISSN: 00346632     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (30)

References (142)
  • 4
    • 0041149283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The most thorough English-language study of Schelling's Hegelkritik, besides Bowie's book, is Alan White's Absolute Knowledge (cited above, note 2). An important recent German study of Schelling's relation to Hegel is to be found in Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Die Grenzen der Vernunft. Eine Untersuchung zu Zielen und Motiven des Deutschen Idealismus (Frankfurt am Main: Anton Hain, 1991), 245-68 .
  • 5
    • 0040555108 scopus 로고
    • ed. K. F. A. Schelling, 10 vols.; Part II, 4 vols. Stuttgart: Cotta
    • See F. W. J. Schelling, Sämmtliche Werke (hereafter "SW"), ed. K. F. A. Schelling, Part I, 10 vols.; Part II, 4 vols. (Stuttgart: Cotta, 1856-61), 10:126-64. For the English translation of these lectures, see F. W. J. Schelling, On the History of Modern Philosophy (hereafter "OHMP"), trans. Andrew Bowie (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 134-63
    • (1856) Sämmtliche Werke (Hereafter "SW") , vol.10 , Issue.PART I , pp. 126-164
    • Schelling, F.W.J.1
  • 6
    • 0040263398 scopus 로고
    • trans. Andrew Bowie Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See F. W. J. Schelling, Sämmtliche Werke (hereafter "SW"), ed. K. F. A. Schelling, Part I, 10 vols.; Part II, 4 vols. (Stuttgart: Cotta, 1856-61), 10:126-64. For the English translation of these lectures, see F. W. J. Schelling, On the History of Modern Philosophy (hereafter "OHMP"), trans. Andrew Bowie (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 134-63
    • (1994) On the History of Modern Philosophy (Hereafter "OHMP") , pp. 134-163
    • Schelling, F.W.J.1
  • 7
    • 0039369778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See SW, II/3:1-174. All translations from the lectures on the introduction to the philosophy of revelation are my own. It might, of course, be possible to formulate alternative Schellingian criticisms of Hegel based on earlier texts of Schelling which do not address Hegel's philosophy explicitly. In this essay, however, I restrict myself to Schelling's own direct critique of Hegel and its background in the distinction he draws between negative and positive philosophy.
  • 8
    • 0039962100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:83: "nur das reine Was desselben enthält, nichts aber von dem Daβ, von der Existenz." See also SW, II/3:59.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 83
  • 9
    • 0039962114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:83: "nur das reine Was desselben enthält, nichts aber von dem Daβ, von der Existenz." See also SW, II/3:59.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 59
  • 10
    • 0040555126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:60 and 101-2.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 60
  • 11
    • 0041149256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:172.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 172
  • 12
    • 0041149282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Schelling's view that the existence of particular things in nature can only be confirmed a posteriori by sensuous experience or Vorstellung, see SW, II/3:61-2, 171, and 173. On his view that the existence of God (and of other minds) can only be confirmed a posteriori by pure, nonsensuous experience or Vorstellung, see SW, II/3:113, 169, 171, and 173, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 148 and 172. Note that alongside the more familiar sensuous empiricism, Schelling thus propounds a theory of metaphysical empiricism, according to which we can directly intuit that which is not given to the senses; see SW, II/3:114.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 61-62
  • 13
    • 0039962132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Schelling's view that the existence of particular things in nature can only be confirmed a posteriori by sensuous experience or Vorstellung, see SW, II/3:61-2, 171, and 173. On his view that the existence of God (and of other minds) can only be confirmed a posteriori by pure, nonsensuous experience or Vorstellung, see SW, II/3:113, 169, 171, and 173, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 148 and 172. Note that alongside the more familiar sensuous empiricism, Schelling thus propounds a theory of metaphysical empiricism, according to which we can directly intuit that which is not given to the senses; see SW, II/3:114.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 113
  • 14
    • 0040555109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Schelling's view that the existence of particular things in nature can only be confirmed a posteriori by sensuous experience or Vorstellung, see SW, II/3:61-2, 171, and 173. On his view that the existence of God (and of other minds) can only be confirmed a posteriori by pure, nonsensuous experience or Vorstellung, see SW, II/3:113, 169, 171, and 173, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 148 and 172. Note that alongside the more familiar sensuous empiricism, Schelling thus propounds a theory of metaphysical empiricism, according to which we can directly intuit that which is not given to the senses; see SW, II/3:114.
    • The Potencies of God(s) , pp. 148
    • Beach1
  • 15
    • 0039962133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Schelling's view that the existence of particular things in nature can only be confirmed a posteriori by sensuous experience or Vorstellung, see SW, II/3:61-2, 171, and 173. On his view that the existence of God (and of other minds) can only be confirmed a posteriori by pure, nonsensuous experience or Vorstellung, see SW, II/3:113, 169, 171, and 173, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 148 and 172. Note that alongside the more familiar sensuous empiricism, Schelling thus propounds a theory of metaphysical empiricism, according to which we can directly intuit that which is not given to the senses; see SW, II/3:114.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 114
  • 16
    • 0039962128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The appropriate translation of Vorstellung would thus be "presentation" rather than "representation." I have elected to leave the term untranslated in this essay, however, as the etymology of the German word itself provides the clearest indication of its meaning for Schelling.
  • 17
    • 0040555105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Das Denken hat eben nur mit der Möglichkeit, der Potenz zu tun
    • SW, II/3:161: "Das Denken hat eben nur mit der Möglichkeit, der Potenz zu tun."
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 161
  • 18
    • 0040555111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:165, 148.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 165
  • 19
    • 0040555109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a lucid account of Schelling's negative philosophy, see Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 95-146. See also John Burbidge, "Contraries and Contradictories: Reasoning in Schelling's Late Philosophy," The Owl of Minerva 16, no. 1 (fall 1984): 55-68.
    • The Potencies of God(s) , pp. 95-146
    • Beach1
  • 20
    • 0039962097 scopus 로고
    • Contraries and contradictories: Reasoning in Schelling's late philosophy
    • fall
    • For a lucid account of Schelling's negative philosophy, see Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 95-146. See also John Burbidge, "Contraries and Contradictories: Reasoning in Schelling's Late Philosophy," The Owl of Minerva 16, no. 1 (fall 1984): 55-68.
    • (1984) The Owl of Minerva , vol.16 , Issue.1 , pp. 55-68
    • Burbidge, J.1
  • 21
    • 0040555122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:104, 149, and 155.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 104
  • 22
    • 26844575824 scopus 로고
    • "Wissenschaft der Logik" (hereafter "WL")
    • ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel, 2 vols., Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, I
    • In this essay I will follow Schelling in using these terms interchangeably, whether I am discussing Schelling himself or Hegel. Distinctions will be drawn between necessary and contingent existence, and between the mere thought of existence and the Vorstellung of existence, but no significant distinctions will be drawn between existence, being and actuality. In the Science of Logic Hegel distinguishes these terms very carefully, but the logical distinctions he draws between them are not relevant to the topic of this essay. The terms "existence" and "actuality" should thus be understood here, not in their distinctive Hegelian sense, but rather as equivalent to "being itself" or "sheer being." (Schelling argues that Hegel's concept of sheer -or pure - being falls woefully short of what Schelling himself understands by "being itself." As will become apparent later, however, I believe, contra Schelling, that Hegel's concept of pure being comes much closer to what Schelling has in mind than Schelling allows.) For Hegel's own, highly nuanced account of pure being, existence and actuality, see G. W. F. Hegel, "Wissenschaft der Logik" (hereafter "WL"), ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel, 2 vols., Theorie Werkausgabe, Vols. 5 and 6 (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1969), I:82; II:125-47 and 200-17. English translations taken from Science of Logic (hereafter "SL"), trans. A. V. Miller (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), 82, 481-98, and 541-53.
    • (1969) Theorie Werkausgabe , vol.5-6 , pp. 82
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 23
    • 0039962125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this essay I will follow Schelling in using these terms interchangeably, whether I am discussing Schelling himself or Hegel. Distinctions will be drawn between necessary and contingent existence, and between the mere thought of existence and the Vorstellung of existence, but no significant distinctions will be drawn between existence, being and actuality. In the Science of Logic Hegel distinguishes these terms very carefully, but the logical distinctions he draws between them are not relevant to the topic of this essay. The terms "existence" and "actuality" should thus be understood here, not in their distinctive Hegelian sense, but rather as equivalent to "being itself" or "sheer being." (Schelling argues that Hegel's concept of sheer - or pure - being falls woefully short of what Schelling himself understands by "being itself." As will become apparent later, however, I believe, contra Schelling, that Hegel's concept of pure being comes much closer to what Schelling has in mind than Schelling allows.) For Hegel's own, highly nuanced account of pure being, existence and actuality, see G. W. F. Hegel, "Wissenschaft der Logik" (hereafter "WL"), ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel, 2 vols., Theorie Werkausgabe, Vols. 5 and 6 (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1969), I:82; II:125-47 and 200-17. English translations taken from Science of Logic (hereafter "SL"), trans. A. V. Miller (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), 82, 481-98, and 541-53.
    • Theorie Werkausgabe , vol.2 , pp. 125-147
  • 24
    • 0039369777 scopus 로고
    • trans. A. V. Miller Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International
    • In this essay I will follow Schelling in using these terms interchangeably, whether I am discussing Schelling himself or Hegel. Distinctions will be drawn between necessary and contingent existence, and between the mere thought of existence and the Vorstellung of existence, but no significant distinctions will be drawn between existence, being and actuality. In the Science of Logic Hegel distinguishes these terms very carefully, but the logical distinctions he draws between them are not relevant to the topic of this essay. The terms "existence" and "actuality" should thus be understood here, not in their distinctive Hegelian sense, but rather as equivalent to "being itself" or "sheer being." (Schelling argues that Hegel's concept of sheer - or pure - being falls woefully short of what Schelling himself understands by "being itself." As will become apparent later, however, I believe, contra Schelling, that Hegel's concept of pure being comes much closer to what Schelling has in mind than Schelling allows.) For Hegel's own, highly nuanced account of pure being, existence and actuality, see G. W. F. Hegel, "Wissenschaft der Logik" (hereafter "WL"), ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel, 2 vols., Theorie Werkausgabe, Vols. 5 and 6 (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1969), I:82; II:125-47 and 200-17. English translations taken from Science of Logic (hereafter "SL"), trans. A. V. Miller (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), 82, 481-98, and 541-53.
    • (1989) Science of Logic (Hereafter "SL") , vol.82 , pp. 481-498
  • 25
    • 0039962098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:149: "gar nichts von einem Nichtsein."
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 149
  • 26
    • 0039369807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:158-9.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 158-159
  • 27
    • 0040555125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:167.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 167
  • 29
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고
    • London: Macmillan
    • Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (hereafter "CPR," with references to pagination in the first [A] and second [B] German editions) ed. Raymond Schmidt (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1990), A122/B111; English translations taken from Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1929), 116.
    • (1929) Critique of Pure Reason , pp. 116
    • Smith, N.K.1
  • 30
    • 0039962115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:160: "eben darum . . . müssen wir von dem ausgehen, was ich das bloβ Existierende genannt habe, von dem unmittelbar, einfach notwendig Seienden, das notwendig ist, weil es aller Potenz, aller Möglichkeit zuvorkommt," 166: "Eben darum ist es das notwendig Existierende, weil es alle vorgängige Möglichkeit ausschlieβt, weil es allem Können zuvorkommt."
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 160
  • 31
    • 0040555111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:165: "das a priori Unbegreifliche."
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 165
  • 32
    • 0039369786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:168: "von selbst."
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 168
  • 33
    • 0041149275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:7. See also Bowie, Schelling and Modern European Philosophy, 162.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 7
  • 35
    • 0039369787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:166. This is not to say that nature or the human world is necessary, but only that existence as such is necessary. Insofar as nature and the human world are contingent (because they are freely created) and so do not have to exist, "there could exist nothing at all" (SW, II/3:59). There could not, however, be no existence whatsoever; there could not be absolutely nothing. On the contingency of nature, see notes 36 and 45 below.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 166
  • 36
    • 0039962114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:166. This is not to say that nature or the human world is necessary, but only that existence as such is necessary. Insofar as nature and the human world are contingent (because they are freely created) and so do not have to exist, "there could exist nothing at all" (SW, II/3:59). There could not, however, be no existence whatsoever; there could not be absolutely nothing. On the contingency of nature, see notes 36 and 45 below.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 59
  • 37
    • 0040555125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:167.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 167
  • 38
    • 0040555125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:167.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 167
  • 39
    • 0039369785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SW, I/10:17; OHMP, 51-2; SW, II/3:156.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 17
  • 40
    • 0040555110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SW, I/10:17; OHMP, 51-2; SW, II/3:156.
    • OHMP , pp. 51-52
  • 41
    • 0041149257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SW, I/10:17; OHMP, 51-2; SW, II/3:156.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 156
  • 42
    • 0039962119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Die Vernunft, wenn gleich ihr letztes Ziel und Absehen nur das Seiende ist, das Ist, kann es doch nicht anders bestimmen, sie hat keinen Begriff für dasselbe, als den des nicht nicht Seienden
    • SW, II/3-70: "Die Vernunft, wenn gleich ihr letztes Ziel und Absehen nur das Seiende ist, das Ist, kann es doch nicht anders bestimmen, sie hat keinen Begriff für dasselbe, als den des nicht nicht Seienden."
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 70
  • 43
    • 0039962119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:70, 160, and 171.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 70
  • 44
    • 0039369789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:153, 164, and 171. For a brief but helpful account of Schelling's positive philosophy, see Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 147-62.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 153
  • 45
    • 0040555109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:153, 164, and 171. For a brief but helpful account of Schelling's positive philosophy, see Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 147-62.
    • The Potencies of God(s) , pp. 147-162
    • Beach1
  • 46
    • 84857345885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Denn a priori ist das wovon sie ausgeht
    • SW, II/3:128: "Denn a priori ist das wovon sie ausgeht."
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 128
  • 47
    • 0040555119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:173.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 173
  • 48
    • 0040555115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:162-3: "ein absolutes Auβer-sich."
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 162-163
  • 49
    • 0039962124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:163.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 163
  • 50
    • 0041149273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that Schelling's belief that necessary existence can be shown to be the existence of God is quite compatible with his denial that we can prove the existence of God a priori by means of the ontological argument (or indeed any other argument). Schelling insists that we can know a priori that existence as such is necessary, because sheer existence is all that existence can be; it can never not be, nor can it merely be potential being. But he denies that we can prove a priori that the existence of God (as the perfect being) is necessary, because he rejects the idea that existence is necessarily entailed by perfection; see SW, I/10:15; OHMP, 50. Schelling accepts, however, that we can show a posteriori that sheer, necessary existence is in fact itself the existence of God; see SW, II/3:131, 157-9, and 169, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 107. This commits Schelling to the following position: what can be shown to be necessary is not God's existence as God - as the perfect creator of all things - but God's existence as sheer, necessary existence alone. For Schelling, God's Godhood or Divinity as such cannot be shown to be necessary, and cannot be necessary, because God freely raises himself into his Godhood as he creates the world; see SW, II/4:353. God must exist as sheer existence, as sheer Daβ, therefore; but qua this Daβ he freely makes himself into God as such, into God the creator - a fact that we discover a posteriori by coming to recognize nature and human history as the work of a free creator. See also note 44 below.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 15
  • 51
    • 0039369805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that Schelling's belief that necessary existence can be shown to be the existence of God is quite compatible with his denial that we can prove the existence of God a priori by means of the ontological argument (or indeed any other argument). Schelling insists that we can know a priori that existence as such is necessary, because sheer existence is all that existence can be; it can never not be, nor can it merely be potential being. But he denies that we can prove a priori that the existence of God (as the perfect being) is necessary, because he rejects the idea that existence is necessarily entailed by perfection; see SW, I/10:15; OHMP, 50. Schelling accepts, however, that we can show a posteriori that sheer, necessary existence is in fact itself the existence of God; see SW, II/3:131, 157-9, and 169, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 107. This commits Schelling to the following position: what can be shown to be necessary is not God's existence as God - as the perfect creator of all things - but God's existence as sheer, necessary existence alone. For Schelling, God's Godhood or Divinity as such cannot be shown to be necessary, and cannot be necessary, because God freely raises himself into his Godhood as he creates the world; see SW, II/4:353. God must exist as sheer existence, as sheer Daβ, therefore; but qua this Daβ he freely makes himself into God as such, into God the creator - a fact that we discover a posteriori by coming to recognize nature and human history as the work of a free creator. See also note 44 below.
    • OHMP , pp. 50
  • 52
    • 0040555120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that Schelling's belief that necessary existence can be shown to be the existence of God is quite compatible with his denial that we can prove the existence of God a priori by means of the ontological argument (or indeed any other argument). Schelling insists that we can know a priori that existence as such is necessary, because sheer existence is all that existence can be; it can never not be, nor can it merely be potential being. But he denies that we can prove a priori that the existence of God (as the perfect being) is necessary, because he rejects the idea that existence is necessarily entailed by perfection; see SW, I/10:15; OHMP, 50. Schelling accepts, however, that we can show a posteriori that sheer, necessary existence is in fact itself the existence of God; see SW, II/3:131, 157-9, and 169, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 107. This commits Schelling to the following position: what can be shown to be necessary is not God's existence as God - as the perfect creator of all things - but God's existence as sheer, necessary existence alone. For Schelling, God's Godhood or Divinity as such cannot be shown to be necessary, and cannot be necessary, because God freely raises himself into his Godhood as he creates the world; see SW, II/4:353. God must exist as sheer existence, as sheer Daβ, therefore; but qua this Daβ he freely makes himself into God as such, into God the creator - a fact that we discover a posteriori by coming to recognize nature and human history as the work of a free creator. See also note 44 below.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 131
  • 53
    • 0040555109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that Schelling's belief that necessary existence can be shown to be the existence of God is quite compatible with his denial that we can prove the existence of God a priori by means of the ontological argument (or indeed any other argument). Schelling insists that we can know a priori that existence as such is necessary, because sheer existence is all that existence can be; it can never not be, nor can it merely be potential being. But he denies that we can prove a priori that the existence of God (as the perfect being) is necessary, because he rejects the idea that existence is necessarily entailed by perfection; see SW, I/10:15; OHMP, 50. Schelling accepts, however, that we can show a posteriori that sheer, necessary existence is in fact itself the existence of God; see SW, II/3:131, 157-9, and 169, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 107. This commits Schelling to the following position: what can be shown to be necessary is not God's existence as God - as the perfect creator of all things - but God's existence as sheer, necessary existence alone. For Schelling, God's Godhood or Divinity as such cannot be shown to be necessary, and cannot be necessary, because God freely raises himself into his Godhood as he creates the world; see SW, II/4:353. God must exist as sheer existence, as sheer Daβ, therefore; but qua this Daβ he freely makes himself into God as such, into God the creator - a fact that we discover a posteriori by coming to recognize nature and human history as the work of a free creator. See also note 44 below.
    • The Potencies of God(s) , pp. 107
    • Beach1
  • 54
    • 0039369800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that Schelling's belief that necessary existence can be shown to be the existence of God is quite compatible with his denial that we can prove the existence of God a priori by means of the ontological argument (or indeed any other argument). Schelling insists that we can know a priori that existence as such is necessary, because sheer existence is all that existence can be; it can never not be, nor can it merely be potential being. But he denies that we can prove a priori that the existence of God (as the perfect being) is necessary, because he rejects the idea that existence is necessarily entailed by perfection; see SW, I/10:15; OHMP, 50. Schelling accepts, however, that we can show a posteriori that sheer, necessary existence is in fact itself the existence of God; see SW, II/3:131, 157-9, and 169, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 107. This commits Schelling to the following position: what can be shown to be necessary is not God's existence as God - as the perfect creator of all things - but God's existence as sheer, necessary existence alone. For Schelling, God's Godhood or Divinity as such cannot be shown to be necessary, and cannot be necessary, because God freely raises himself into his Godhood as he creates the world; see SW, II/4:353. God must exist as sheer existence, as sheer Daβ, therefore; but qua this Daβ he freely makes himself into God as such, into God the creator - a fact that we discover a posteriori by coming to recognize nature and human history as the work of a free creator. See also note 44 below.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.4 , pp. 353
  • 55
    • 0041149267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:164.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 164
  • 56
    • 0039369797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:127; OHMP, 134.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 127
  • 57
    • 0040555118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:127; OHMP, 134.
    • OHMP , pp. 134
  • 58
    • 84904976314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:126, 141; OHMP, 134, 145.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 126
  • 59
    • 0039962123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:126, 141; OHMP, 134, 145.
    • OHMP , pp. 134
  • 60
    • 0039369799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:143-4; OHMP, 147.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 143-144
  • 61
    • 0040555117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:143-4; OHMP, 147.
    • OHMP , pp. 147
  • 62
    • 0039369798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:126-7, 141; OHMP, 134, 146.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 126-127
  • 63
    • 0039962122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:126-7, 141; OHMP, 134, 146.
    • OHMP , pp. 134
  • 64
    • 0039369792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:80.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 80
  • 65
    • 0039962124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW; II/3:163.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 163
  • 66
    • 0039962121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:159-60; OHMP, 159-60 . For Schelling, existence as such - das Seiende selbst or the pure Daβ - is groundlessly necessary, but nature is not necessary in any sense, either rationally or groundlessly. Groundlessly necessary existence, in Schelling's view, is the primordial existence of God; that is to say, it is God insofar as he is sheer, irreducible existence, sheer that-ness, but not yet God as such. See SW, II/1:586-7; see also "On the Source of the Eternal Truths," trans. Edward Allen Beach, The Owl of Minerva 22, no. 1 (Fall 1990): 64-5. This pure Daβ freely creates nature and in the very same act freely raises itself to explicit Godhood. God as sheer Daβ thus raises itself (himself) to explicit Godhood precisely by becoming the free creator of nature. See SW, II/4:353, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 156: "Only in the execution of the world's creation does this Daβ reveal its true character. This is why Schelling insists that God in himself did not, properly speaking, exist prior to the creation, but simply had the status of the infinite Prius, or Überseiende." Hegel's reduction of God to the Concept blinds him, in Schelling's view, to this free activity whereby God both creates nature and becomes fully God at one and the same time. See also note 36 above.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 159-160
  • 67
    • 0041149266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:159-60; OHMP, 159-60 . For Schelling, existence as such -das Seiende selbst or the pure Daβ - is groundlessly necessary, but nature is not necessary in any sense, either rationally or groundlessly. Groundlessly necessary existence, in Schelling's view, is the primordial existence of God; that is to say, it is God insofar as he is sheer, irreducible existence, sheer that-ness, but not yet God as such. See SW, II/1:586-7; see also "On the Source of the Eternal Truths," trans. Edward Allen Beach, The Owl of Minerva 22, no. 1 (Fall 1990): 64-5. This pure Daβ freely creates nature and in the very same act freely raises itself to explicit Godhood. God as sheer Daβ thus raises itself (himself) to explicit Godhood precisely by becoming the free creator of nature. See SW, II/4:353, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 156: "Only in the execution of the world's creation does this Daβ reveal its true character. This is why Schelling insists that God in himself did not, properly speaking, exist prior to the creation, but simply had the status of the infinite Prius, or Überseiende." Hegel's reduction of God to the Concept blinds him, in Schelling's view, to this free activity whereby God both creates nature and becomes fully God at one and the same time. See also note 36 above.
    • OHMP , pp. 159-160
  • 68
    • 0041149269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:159-60; OHMP, 159-60 . For Schelling, existence as such - das Seiende selbst or the pure Daβ - is groundlessly necessary, but nature is not necessary in any sense, either rationally or groundlessly. Groundlessly necessary existence, in Schelling's view, is the primordial existence of God; that is to say, it is God insofar as he is sheer, irreducible existence, sheer that-ness, but not yet God as such. See SW, II/1:586-7; see also "On the Source of the Eternal Truths," trans. Edward Allen Beach, The Owl of Minerva 22, no. 1 (Fall 1990): 64-5. This pure Daβ freely creates nature and in the very same act freely raises itself to explicit Godhood. God as sheer Daβ thus raises itself (himself) to explicit Godhood precisely by becoming the free creator of nature. See SW, II/4:353, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 156: "Only in the execution of the world's creation does this Daβ reveal its true character. This is why Schelling insists that God in himself did not, properly speaking, exist prior to the creation, but simply had the status of the infinite Prius, or Überseiende." Hegel's reduction of God to the Concept blinds him, in Schelling's view, to this free activity whereby God both creates nature and becomes fully God at one and the same time. See also note 36 above.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.1 , pp. 586-587
  • 69
    • 84896575777 scopus 로고
    • On the source of the eternal truths
    • Fall
    • SW, I/10:159-60; OHMP, 159-60 . For Schelling, existence as such - das Seiende selbst or the pure Daβ - is groundlessly necessary, but nature is not necessary in any sense, either rationally or groundlessly. Groundlessly necessary existence, in Schelling's view, is the primordial existence of God; that is to say, it is God insofar as he is sheer, irreducible existence, sheer that-ness, but not yet God as such. See SW, II/1:586-7; see also "On the Source of the Eternal Truths," trans. Edward Allen Beach, The Owl of Minerva 22, no. 1 (Fall 1990): 64-5. This pure Daβ freely creates nature and in the very same act freely raises itself to explicit Godhood. God as sheer Daβ thus raises itself (himself) to explicit Godhood precisely by becoming the free creator of nature. See SW, II/4:353, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 156: "Only in the execution of the world's creation does this Daβ reveal its true character. This is why Schelling insists that God in himself did not, properly speaking, exist prior to the creation, but simply had the status of the infinite Prius, or Überseiende." Hegel's reduction of God to the Concept blinds him, in Schelling's view, to this free activity whereby God both creates nature and becomes fully God at one and the same time. See also note 36 above.
    • (1990) The Owl of Minerva , vol.22 , Issue.1 , pp. 64-65
    • Beach, E.A.1
  • 70
    • 0039369800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:159-60; OHMP, 159-60 . For Schelling, existence as such - das Seiende selbst or the pure Daβ - is groundlessly necessary, but nature is not necessary in any sense, either rationally or groundlessly. Groundlessly necessary existence, in Schelling's view, is the primordial existence of God; that is to say, it is God insofar as he is sheer, irreducible existence, sheer that-ness, but not yet God as such. See SW, II/1:586-7; see also "On the Source of the Eternal Truths," trans. Edward Allen Beach, The Owl of Minerva 22, no. 1 (Fall 1990): 64-5. This pure Daβ freely creates nature and in the very same act freely raises itself to explicit Godhood. God as sheer Daβ thus raises itself (himself) to explicit Godhood precisely by becoming the free creator of nature. See SW, II/4:353, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 156: "Only in the execution of the world's creation does this Daβ reveal its true character. This is why Schelling insists that God in himself did not, properly speaking, exist prior to the creation, but simply had the status of the infinite Prius, or Überseiende." Hegel's reduction of God to the Concept blinds him, in Schelling's view, to this free activity whereby God both creates nature and becomes fully God at one and the same time. See also note 36 above.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.4 , pp. 353
  • 71
    • 0040555109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:159-60; OHMP, 159-60 . For Schelling, existence as such - das Seiende selbst or the pure Daβ - is groundlessly necessary, but nature is not necessary in any sense, either rationally or groundlessly. Groundlessly necessary existence, in Schelling's view, is the primordial existence of God; that is to say, it is God insofar as he is sheer, irreducible existence, sheer that-ness, but not yet God as such. See SW, II/1:586-7; see also "On the Source of the Eternal Truths," trans. Edward Allen Beach, The Owl of Minerva 22, no. 1 (Fall 1990): 64-5. This pure Daβ freely creates nature and in the very same act freely raises itself to explicit Godhood. God as sheer Daβ thus raises itself (himself) to explicit Godhood precisely by becoming the free creator of nature. See SW, II/4:353, and Beach, The Potencies of God(s), 156: "Only in the execution of the world's creation does this Daβ reveal its true character. This is why Schelling insists that God in himself did not, properly speaking, exist prior to the creation, but simply had the status of the infinite Prius, or Überseiende." Hegel's reduction of God to the Concept blinds him, in Schelling's view, to this free activity whereby God both creates nature and becomes fully God at one and the same time. See also note 36 above.
    • The Potencies of God(s) , pp. 156
    • Beach1
  • 72
    • 0041149268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:129; OHMP, 136.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 129
  • 73
    • 0039962118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:129; OHMP, 136.
    • OHMP , pp. 136
  • 74
    • 0040555113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:137; OHMP, 143.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 137
  • 75
    • 0041149259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:137; OHMP, 143.
    • OHMP , pp. 143
  • 76
    • 0039369790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:133; OHMP, 140.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 133
  • 77
    • 0041149260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:133; OHMP, 140.
    • OHMP , pp. 140
  • 78
    • 0041149261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:132; OHMP, 138.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 132
  • 79
    • 0039962120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:132; OHMP, 138.
    • OHMP , pp. 138
  • 80
    • 84930885431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:131-2; OHMP, 138.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 131-132
  • 81
    • 0041149251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:131-2; OHMP, 138.
    • OHMP , pp. 138
  • 82
    • 0039369791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:135; OHMP, 141.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 135
  • 83
    • 0039369795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:135; OHMP, 141.
    • OHMP , pp. 141
  • 84
    • 0039369791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:135; OHMP, 141.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 135
  • 85
    • 0041149265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:135; OHMP, 141.
    • OHMP , pp. 141
  • 86
    • 0041149261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:132; OHMP, 138-9.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 132
  • 87
    • 0041149264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:132; OHMP, 138-9.
    • OHMP , pp. 138-139
  • 88
    • 0041149249 scopus 로고
    • Paris: Éditions Denoël/Gonthier
    • Jacques Derrida, Glas (Paris: Éditions Denoël/Gonthier, 1981), 281: "grâce au jeu du déjà et du pas-encore." For an English translation see Glas, trans. John P. Leavey, Jr. and Richard Rand (Lincoln, Nebr.: University of Nebraska Press, 1986), 201.
    • (1981) Glas , pp. 281
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 89
    • 23944453272 scopus 로고
    • Nebr.: University of Nebraska Press
    • Jacques Derrida, Glas (Paris: Éditions Denoël/Gonthier, 1981), 281: "grâce au jeu du déjà et du pas-encore." For an English translation see Glas, trans. John P. Leavey, Jr. and Richard Rand (Lincoln, Nebr.: University of Nebraska Press, 1986), 201.
    • (1986) Glas , pp. 201
    • Leavey J.P., Jr.1    Lincoln, R.R.2
  • 90
    • 0004129258 scopus 로고
    • trans. Alphonso Lingis Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press
    • See, for example, Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1969), 289: "The Hegelian dialectic is all powerful to reduce this individuality of the tode ti to the concept." See also, Emmanuel Levinas, "Ethics as First Philosophy," in The Levinas Reader, ed. Seán Hand (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 78: "The labor of thought wins out over the otherness of things and men."
    • (1969) Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority , pp. 289
    • Levinas, E.1
  • 91
    • 0002060851 scopus 로고
    • Ethics as first philosophy
    • ed. Seán Hand Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • See, for example, Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1969), 289: "The Hegelian dialectic is all powerful to reduce this individuality of the tode ti to the concept." See also, Emmanuel Levinas, "Ethics as First Philosophy," in The Levinas Reader, ed. Seán Hand (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 78: "The labor of thought wins out over the otherness of things and men."
    • (1989) The Levinas Reader , pp. 78
    • Levinas, E.1
  • 92
    • 0041149262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, for example, Søren Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, trans. David F. Swenson and Walter Lowrie (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1968), 75: "The speculative result is in so far illusory, as the existing subject proposes qua thinker to abstract from the fact that he is occupied in existing, in order to be sub specie aeterni." Kierkegaard is concerned to highlight the existence of the subject, rather than existence as such. Nevertheless, his interpretation of Hegel is similar to - and, indeed, in part indebted to - that of Schelling.
  • 93
    • 0041149267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:164.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 164
  • 94
    • 0039962116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Hegel's discussion of the absolute necessity of being as such, and of the contingency of finite things, see WL, II:200-17; SL, 541-53. See also Dieter Henrich, "Hegels Theorie über den Zufall," in Hegel im Kontext (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1971), 157-86, and Stephen Houlgate, "Necessity and Contingency in Hegel's Science of Logic," The Owl of Minerva 27, no. 1 (Fall 1995): 37-49.
    • WL , vol.2 , pp. 200-217
  • 95
    • 0039962109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Hegel's discussion of the absolute necessity of being as such, and of the contingency of finite things, see WL, II:200-17; SL, 541-53. See also Dieter Henrich, "Hegels Theorie über den Zufall," in Hegel im Kontext (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1971), 157-86, and Stephen Houlgate, "Necessity and Contingency in Hegel's Science of Logic," The Owl of Minerva 27, no. 1 (Fall 1995): 37-49.
    • SL , pp. 541-553
  • 96
    • 84922412781 scopus 로고
    • Hegels Theorie über den Zufall
    • Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag
    • For Hegel's discussion of the absolute necessity of being as such, and of the contingency of finite things, see WL, II:200-17; SL, 541-53. See also Dieter Henrich, "Hegels Theorie über den Zufall," in Hegel im Kontext (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1971), 157-86, and Stephen Houlgate, "Necessity and Contingency in Hegel's Science of Logic," The Owl of Minerva 27, no. 1 (Fall 1995): 37-49.
    • (1971) Hegel im Kontext , pp. 157-186
    • Henrich, D.1
  • 97
    • 0041149243 scopus 로고
    • Necessity and contingency in Hegel's science of logic
    • Fall
    • For Hegel's discussion of the absolute necessity of being as such, and of the contingency of finite things, see WL, II:200-17; SL, 541-53. See also Dieter Henrich, "Hegels Theorie über den Zufall," in Hegel im Kontext (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1971), 157-86, and Stephen Houlgate, "Necessity and Contingency in Hegel's Science of Logic," The Owl of Minerva 27, no. 1 (Fall 1995): 37-49.
    • (1995) The Owl of Minerva , vol.27 , Issue.1 , pp. 37-49
    • Houlgate, S.1
  • 98
    • 0039962094 scopus 로고
    • Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Dritter Teil: Die Philosophie des Geistes. Mit den mündlichen Zusätzen
    • §418; ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag
    • G. W. F. Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Dritter Teil: Die Philosophie des Geistes. Mit den mündlichen Zusätzen, §418; ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970), [Werke in zwanzig Bänden 10]; Philosophy of Mind: Being Part Three of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830), trans. William Wallace, together with the Zusätze in Boumann's text (1845), trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971), 159. I have amended the translation.
    • (1970) Werke in Zwanzig Bänden , vol.10
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 99
    • 0013541390 scopus 로고
    • together with the Zusätze in Boumann's text (1845), trans. A. V. Miller Oxford: Clarendon Press, I have amended the translation
    • G. W. F. Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Dritter Teil: Die Philosophie des Geistes. Mit den mündlichen Zusätzen, §418; ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970), [Werke in zwanzig Bänden 10]; Philosophy of Mind: Being Part Three of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830), trans. William Wallace, together with the Zusätze in Boumann's text (1845), trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971), 159. I have amended the translation.
    • (1830) Philosophy of Mind: Being Part Three of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences , pp. 159
    • Wallace, W.1
  • 100
    • 0040555102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Dritter Teil: Die Philosophie des Geistes
    • §465
    • Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Dritter Teil: Die Philosophie des Geistes, §465; Philosophy of Mind, 224.
    • (1830) Philosophy of Mind , pp. 224
    • Hegel1
  • 101
    • 0039962094 scopus 로고
    • Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Zweiter Teil: die Naturphilosophie. Mit den mündlichen Zusätzen
    • §254; ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag
    • See G. W. F. Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Zweiter Teil: Die Naturphilosophie. Mit den mündlichen Zusätzen, §254; ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970), [Werke in zwanzig Bänden 9]; Philosophy of Nature: Being Part Two of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830) with the Zusätze in Michelet's text (1847), trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970), 28.
    • (1970) Werke in Zwanzig Bänden , vol.9
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 102
    • 0004281176 scopus 로고
    • with the Zusätze in Michelet's text (1847), Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See G. W. F. Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Zweiter Teil: Die Naturphilosophie. Mit den mündlichen Zusätzen, §254; ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970), [Werke in zwanzig Bänden 9]; Philosophy of Nature: Being Part Two of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830) with the Zusätze in Michelet's text (1847), trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970), 28.
    • (1830) Philosophy of Nature: Being Part Two of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences , pp. 28
    • Miller, A.V.1
  • 103
    • 0040555102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Dritter Teil: Die Philosophie des Geistes
    • §§465-7
    • For Hegel's account of thought and its activity, see Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Dritter Teil: Die Philosophie des Geistes, §§465-7; Philosophy of Mind, 224-7.
    • Philosophy of Mind , pp. 224-227
    • Hegel1
  • 104
    • 26544442931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strictly speaking, Kant only identifies understanding (Verstand), not thought as a whole, with the faculty of judgment (Vermögen zu urteilen); see CPR, A108-9/B93-4; pp. 105-6. Theoretical reason (Vernunft) depends on the activity of judgment, however, insofar as it seeks "to discover the universal condition of its judgment[s];" see CPR, A345/B364; p. 306. Bowie confirms at various points in his book that Schelling understands thought to be primarily discursive and predicative; see, for example, Schelling and Modern European Philosophy, 26: "knowledge has a subject-object, prepositional structure"; and 63: "Manfred Frank suggests that Schelling conceives of being as the 'transitive relationship of a subject to its predicates.'" See also Peter Dews, The Limits of Disenchantment: Essays on Contemporary European Philosophy (London: Verso, 1995), 140-1.
    • CPR , vol.A108-9 , Issue.B93-4 , pp. 105-106
  • 105
    • 0039369783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strictly speaking, Kant only identifies understanding (Verstand), not thought as a whole, with the faculty of judgment (Vermögen zu urteilen); see CPR, A108-9/B93-4; pp. 105-6. Theoretical reason (Vernunft) depends on the activity of judgment, however, insofar as it seeks "to discover the universal condition of its judgment[s];" see CPR, A345/B364; p. 306. Bowie confirms at various points in his book that Schelling understands thought to be primarily discursive and predicative; see, for example, Schelling and Modern European Philosophy, 26: "knowledge has a subject-object, prepositional structure"; and 63: "Manfred Frank suggests that Schelling conceives of being as the 'transitive relationship of a subject to its predicates.'" See also Peter Dews, The Limits of Disenchantment: Essays on Contemporary European Philosophy (London: Verso, 1995), 140-1.
    • CPR , vol.A345 , Issue.B364 , pp. 306
  • 106
    • 0039369782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strictly speaking, Kant only identifies understanding (Verstand), not thought as a whole, with the faculty of judgment (Vermögen zu urteilen); see CPR, A108-9/B93-4; pp. 105-6. Theoretical reason (Vernunft) depends on the activity of judgment, however, insofar as it seeks "to discover the universal condition of its judgment[s];" see CPR, A345/B364; p. 306. Bowie confirms at various points in his book that Schelling understands thought to be primarily discursive and predicative; see, for example, Schelling and Modern European Philosophy, 26: "knowledge has a subject-object, prepositional structure"; and 63: "Manfred Frank suggests that Schelling conceives of being as the 'transitive relationship of a subject to its predicates.'" See also Peter Dews, The Limits of Disenchantment: Essays on Contemporary European Philosophy (London: Verso, 1995), 140-1.
    • Schelling and Modern European Philosophy , pp. 26
  • 107
    • 0009385207 scopus 로고
    • London: Verso
    • Strictly speaking, Kant only identifies understanding (Verstand), not thought as a whole, with the faculty of judgment (Vermögen zu urteilen); see CPR, A108-9/B93-4; pp. 105-6. Theoretical reason (Vernunft) depends on the activity of judgment, however, insofar as it seeks "to discover the universal condition of its judgment[s];" see CPR, A345/B364; p. 306. Bowie confirms at various points in his book that Schelling understands thought to be primarily discursive and predicative; see, for example, Schelling and Modern European Philosophy, 26: "knowledge has a subject-object, prepositional structure"; and 63: "Manfred Frank suggests that Schelling conceives of being as the 'transitive relationship of a subject to its predicates.'" See also Peter Dews, The Limits of Disenchantment: Essays on Contemporary European Philosophy (London: Verso, 1995), 140-1.
    • (1995) The Limits of Disenchantment: Essays on Contemporary European Philosophy , pp. 140-141
    • Dews, P.1
  • 108
    • 0040555107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CPR, A572/B626; p. 504.
    • CPR , vol.A572 , Issue.B626 , pp. 504
  • 109
    • 0040555107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CPR, A572/B626; p. 504.
    • CPR , vol.A572 , Issue.B626 , pp. 504
  • 110
    • 26544466913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CPR, A567-75/B620-30; pp. 500-7, and SW, II/3:156-7, 168-9. On the subtle differences between Kant and Schelling concerning the ontological argument, despite the similarity of their approaches, see SW, I/10:12-17; OHMP, 48-52.
    • CPR , vol.A567-75 , Issue.B620-30 , pp. 500-507
  • 111
    • 0039369780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CPR, A567-75/B620-30; pp. 500-7, and SW, II/3:156-7, 168-9. On the subtle differences between Kant and Schelling concerning the ontological argument, despite the similarity of their approaches, see SW, I/10:12-17; OHMP, 48-52.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 156-157
  • 112
    • 0041149254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CPR, A567-75/B620-30; pp. 500-7, and SW, II/3:156-7, 168-9. On the subtle differences between Kant and Schelling concerning the ontological argument, despite the similarity of their approaches, see SW, I/10:12-17; OHMP, 48-52.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 12-17
  • 113
    • 0040555106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CPR, A567-75/B620-30; pp. 500-7, and SW, II/3:156-7, 168-9. On the subtle differences between Kant and Schelling concerning the ontological argument, despite the similarity of their approaches, see SW, I/10:12-17; OHMP, 48-52.
    • OHMP , pp. 48-52
  • 114
    • 0039962124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:163.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 163
  • 115
    • 0039962094 scopus 로고
    • Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Erster Teil: Die Wissenschaft der Logik. Mit den mündlichen Zusätzen
    • §28; ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag
    • G. W. F. Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Erster Teil: Die Wissenschaft der Logik. Mit den mündlichen Zusätzen, §28; ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970), [Werke in zwanzig Bänden 8]; The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part One of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze, trans. T. F. Geraets, W. A. Suchting, and H. S. Harris (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1991), 66.
    • (1970) Werke in Zwanzig Bänden , vol.8
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 116
    • 10644228991 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company
    • G. W. F. Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830). Erster Teil: Die Wissenschaft der Logik. Mit den mündlichen Zusätzen, §28; ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl M. Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970), [Werke in zwanzig Bänden 8]; The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part One of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze, trans. T. F. Geraets, W. A. Suchting, and H. S. Harris (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1991), 66.
    • (1991) The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part One of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze , pp. 66
    • Geraets, T.F.1    Suchting, W.A.2    Harris, H.S.3
  • 117
    • 0040555103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WL, I:82-3; SL, 82.
    • WL , vol.1 , pp. 82-83
  • 118
    • 0040555104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WL, I:82-3; SL, 82.
    • SL , pp. 82
  • 122
    • 84927511949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:134; OHMP, 140.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 134
  • 123
    • 0039962108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:134; OHMP, 140.
    • OHMP , pp. 140
  • 124
    • 0039962098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:149.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 149
  • 125
    • 0040555125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:167: "das bloβ Existierende . . . , in dem noch nichts von einem Wesen, einem Was, zu begreifen ist." See also SW, II/3:162-3.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 167
  • 126
    • 0040555115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, II/3:167: "das bloβ Existierende . . . , in dem noch nichts von einem Wesen, einem Was, zu begreifen ist." See also SW, II/3:162-3.
    • SW , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 162-163
  • 127
    • 0041149250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WL, I:83, 113; SL, 83, 106.
    • WL , vol.1 , Issue.83 , pp. 113
  • 128
    • 0041149247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WL, I:83, 113; SL, 83, 106.
    • SL , vol.83 , pp. 106
  • 130
    • 0041149261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:132; OHMP, 139.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 132
  • 131
    • 0039962104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:132; OHMP, 139.
    • OHMP , pp. 139
  • 132
    • 0039369791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:135; OHMP, 141, and WL, I:112; SL, 106.
    • SW , vol.1 , Issue.10 , pp. 135
  • 133
    • 0039369781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:135; OHMP, 141, and WL, I:112; SL, 106.
    • OHMP , pp. 141
  • 134
    • 0041149248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:135; OHMP, 141, and WL, I:112; SL, 106.
    • WL , vol.1 , pp. 112
  • 135
    • 0039962099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SW, I/10:135; OHMP, 141, and WL, I:112; SL, 106.
    • SL , pp. 106
  • 136
    • 0041149244 scopus 로고
    • Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press
    • Apart from Alan White and myself, other English-speaking commentators on Hegel who accept that Hegel's dialectic develops immanently out of itself, without being, as it were, pulled forward by any presupposed goal, include Richard Dien Winfield and William Maker. See, for example, Richard Dien Winfield, Reason and Justice (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1988) and William Maker, Philosophy Without Foundations: Rethinking Hegel (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1994). See also Stephen Houlgate, Freedom, Truth and History: An Introduction to Hegel's Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1991), 41-76. It should be noted, however, that despite our broad agreement concerning Hegel's method, White, Winfield, Maker, and I do not agree about the relation between thought and being in Hegel. As I understand it, I am the only one of the four who maintains that Hegel's Logic provides an ontological account of the basic structure of being as such, rather than a mere category theory or theory of determinacy.
    • (1988) Reason and Justice
    • Winfield, R.D.1
  • 137
    • 60949485161 scopus 로고
    • Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press
    • Apart from Alan White and myself, other English-speaking commentators on Hegel who accept that Hegel's dialectic develops immanently out of itself, without being, as it were, pulled forward by any presupposed goal, include Richard Dien Winfield and William Maker. See, for example, Richard Dien Winfield, Reason and Justice (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1988) and William Maker, Philosophy Without Foundations: Rethinking Hegel (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1994). See also Stephen Houlgate, Freedom, Truth and History: An Introduction to Hegel's Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1991), 41-76. It should be noted, however, that despite our broad agreement concerning Hegel's method, White, Winfield, Maker, and I do not agree about the relation between thought and being in Hegel. As I understand it, I am the only one of the four who maintains that Hegel's Logic provides an ontological account of the basic structure of being as such, rather than a mere category theory or theory of determinacy.
    • (1994) Philosophy Without Foundations: Rethinking Hegel
    • Maker, W.1
  • 138
    • 0010787394 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • Apart from Alan White and myself, other English-speaking commentators on Hegel who accept that Hegel's dialectic develops immanently out of itself, without being, as it were, pulled forward by any presupposed goal, include Richard Dien Winfield and William Maker. See, for example, Richard Dien Winfield, Reason and Justice (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1988) and William Maker, Philosophy Without Foundations: Rethinking Hegel (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1994). See also Stephen Houlgate, Freedom, Truth and History: An Introduction to Hegel's Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1991), 41-76. It should be noted, however, that despite our broad agreement concerning Hegel's method, White, Winfield, Maker, and I do not agree about the relation between thought and being in Hegel. As I understand it, I am the only one of the four who maintains that Hegel's Logic provides an ontological account of the basic structure of being as such, rather than a mere category theory or theory of determinacy.
    • (1991) Freedom, Truth and History: An Introduction to Hegel's Philosophy , pp. 41-76
    • Houlgate, S.1
  • 139
    • 0039962105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See White, Absolute Knowledge, 57; and Martin Heidegger, Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988), 82.
    • Absolute Knowledge , pp. 57
    • White1
  • 140
    • 0039545426 scopus 로고
    • trans. Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly Bloomington: Indiana University Press
    • See White, Absolute Knowledge, 57; and Martin Heidegger, Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988), 82.
    • (1988) Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit , pp. 82
    • Heidegger, M.1
  • 141
    • 0039962096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hegel, Derrida, and restricted economy: The case of mechanical memory
    • January
    • For a critique of Derrida's reading of Hegel, see Stephen Houlgate, "Hegel, Derrida, and Restricted Economy: The Case of Mechanical Memory," Journal of the History of Philosophy 34, no. 1 (January 1996): 79-93.
    • (1996) Journal of the History of Philosophy , vol.34 , Issue.1 , pp. 79-93
    • Houlgate, S.1
  • 142
    • 0041149246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This paper was originally given at a conference entitled Schelling contra Hegel which was held at the University of Warwick on May 9, 1997. I should like to thank all those who commented on the paper at the conference, and to acknowledge a particular debt of gratitude to Edward Beach for the very helpful remarks he made both during the day's proceedings and in writing after the conference.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.