메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 44-59

Thinking about cases

(1)  Kagan, Shelly a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0038845228     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0265052500002892     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (40)

References (7)
  • 1
    • 0004156723 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • This is similar to an example of Judith Jarvis Thomson's, offered while making a similar point; see Thomson, Rights, Restitution, and Risk (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), 257.
    • (1986) Rights, Restitution, and Risk , pp. 257
    • Thomson1
  • 2
    • 0004068219 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See, especially, Shelly Kagan, The Limits of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989).
    • (1989) The Limits of Morality
    • Kagan, S.1
  • 3
    • 0040866644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Killing, letting die, and the trolley problem
    • Thomson
    • In the basic case, a runaway trolley will hit and kill five children, unless you throw a switch which will divert the trolley onto a side track, saving the five, but killing a sixth child trapped on that side track (who would otherwise be safe). A large number of variants of this basic case have been discussed. See, e.g., Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem," in Thomson, Rights, Restitution, and Risk 78-93; and Frances Kamm, "Harming Some to Save Others," Philosophical Studies 57, no. 3 (1989): 227-60.
    • Rights, Restitution, and Risk , pp. 78-93
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 4
    • 0040866644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harming some to save others
    • In the basic case, a runaway trolley will hit and kill five children, unless you throw a switch which will divert the trolley onto a side track, saving the five, but killing a sixth child trapped on that side track (who would otherwise be safe). A large number of variants of this basic case have been discussed. See, e.g., Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem," in Thomson, Rights, Restitution, and Risk 78-93; and Frances Kamm, "Harming Some to Save Others," Philosophical Studies 57, no. 3 (1989): 227-60.
    • (1989) Philosophical Studies , vol.57 , Issue.3 , pp. 227-260
    • Kamm, F.1
  • 5
    • 0010135219 scopus 로고
    • Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium
    • See, for example, Peter Singer, "Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium," The Monist 58, no. 3 (1974): 516.
    • (1974) The Monist , vol.58 , Issue.3 , pp. 516
    • Singer, P.1
  • 6
    • 0004192384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • See for example Peter Unger's discussion of protophysics and psychological grouping principles in his Living High and Letting Die (New York: Oxford University Press 1996).
    • (1996) Living High and Letting Die
    • Unger, P.1
  • 7
    • 0040866645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It might seem that an emotivist or expressivist account of moral claims would have an easy time accommodating these facts, since there is nothing especially surprising in the suggestion that people's emotional (and other) attitudes vary, and that they can be readily generated in response to never before considered cases. But even accounts of this kind, it seems to me, should be troubled by the ease and force with which intuitions can be generated in response to trolley problems (and the like) since it is not at all obvious why these should so readily engage our emotions or other pro-attitudes, nor why minor changes in the cases should elicit such drastically altered reactions.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.