메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 23, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 135-152

How to interfere with nature

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0037932124     PISSN: 01634275     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/enviroethics200123224     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (8)

References (31)
  • 1
    • 0001024823 scopus 로고
    • A Defense of the Deep Ecology Movement
    • "A Defense of the Deep Ecology Movement," Environmental Ethics 6 (1984): 266. See also Arne Naess, "The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary," Inquiry 16 (1973): 95-100.
    • (1984) Environmental Ethics , vol.6 , pp. 266
  • 2
    • 84951419547 scopus 로고
    • The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary
    • "A Defense of the Deep Ecology Movement," Environmental Ethics 6 (1984): 266. See also Arne Naess, "The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary," Inquiry 16 (1973): 95-100.
    • (1973) Inquiry , vol.16 , pp. 95-100
    • Naess, A.1
  • 3
    • 0002118077 scopus 로고
    • The Nature and Possibility of an Environmental Ethic
    • Tom Regan, "The Nature and Possibility of an Environmental Ethic," Environmental Ethics 3 (1981): 31-32. Regan makes it clear that this principle need not be restricted just to individual living things, since immediately after stating the principle he explains how it might be applied to the Colorado River.
    • (1981) Environmental Ethics , vol.3 , pp. 31-32
    • Regan, T.1
  • 4
    • 7444252284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The admonition to act naturally, to follow nature, or to allow nature to take its course can be understood as the positive expression of the principle of noninterference and is sometimes offered as an answer to these questions. This is not very helpful, however, since the idea of acting naturally is at least as obscure as the concept of interference. I discuss the idea of naturalness below, pp. 147-53.
  • 5
    • 8544238883 scopus 로고
    • A Critique of Deep Ecology: Part II
    • Fall
    • Richard Sylvan, "A Critique of Deep Ecology: Part II," Radical Philosophy 41 (Fall 1985): 14.
    • (1985) Radical Philosophy , vol.41 , pp. 14
    • Sylvan, R.1
  • 6
    • 0026829211 scopus 로고
    • Ethical Responsibilities toward Wildlife
    • Interesting examples of many of these scenarios can be found in Holmes Rolston, III's "Ethical Responsibilities toward Wildlife," Journal of the American Veterinary Medicine Association 200, no. 5 (1992): 618-22. Also see Robert Loftin's "The Medical Treatment of Wild Animals," Environmental Ethics 7 (1985): 231-39. The Niagara Falls example is suggested by Martin H. Krieger in "What's Wrong with Plastic Trees?" Science 179 (1973): 446-55.
    • (1992) Journal of the American Veterinary Medicine Association , vol.200 , Issue.5 , pp. 618-622
    • Rolston III, H.1
  • 7
    • 0026829211 scopus 로고
    • The Medical Treatment of Wild Animals
    • Interesting examples of many of these scenarios can be found in Holmes Rolston, III's "Ethical Responsibilities toward Wildlife," Journal of the American Veterinary Medicine Association 200, no. 5 (1992): 618-22. Also see Robert Loftin's "The Medical Treatment of Wild Animals," Environmental Ethics 7 (1985): 231-39. The Niagara Falls example is suggested by Martin H. Krieger in "What's Wrong with Plastic Trees?" Science 179 (1973): 446-55.
    • (1985) Environmental Ethics , vol.7 , pp. 231-239
    • Loftin'S, R.1
  • 8
    • 0007285459 scopus 로고
    • What's Wrong with Plastic Trees?
    • Interesting examples of many of these scenarios can be found in Holmes Rolston, III's "Ethical Responsibilities toward Wildlife," Journal of the American Veterinary Medicine Association 200, no. 5 (1992): 618-22. Also see Robert Loftin's "The Medical Treatment of Wild Animals," Environmental Ethics 7 (1985): 231-39. The Niagara Falls example is suggested by Martin H. Krieger in "What's Wrong with Plastic Trees?" Science 179 (1973): 446-55.
    • (1973) Science , vol.179 , pp. 446-455
    • Krieger, M.H.1
  • 9
    • 0011231180 scopus 로고
    • Duties to Endangered Species
    • Holmes Rolston, III, "Duties to Endangered Species," Bioscience 35, no. 11 (1985): 723.
    • (1985) Bioscience , vol.35 , Issue.11 , pp. 723
    • Rolston III, H.1
  • 10
    • 0002744268 scopus 로고
    • The Liberation of Nature?
    • John Rodman, "The Liberation of Nature?" Inquiry 20 (1977): 115.
    • (1977) Inquiry , vol.20 , pp. 115
    • Rodman, J.1
  • 11
    • 0004037962 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Such an analysis can be found in J. L. Mackie, The Cement of the Universe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980).
    • (1980) The Cement of the Universe
    • Mackie, J.L.1
  • 12
    • 84947619641 scopus 로고
    • Faking Nature
    • For a discussion of some of the moral issues surrounding restoration, see Robert Elliot, "Faking Nature," Inquiry 25 (1982): 81-93; Alistair Gunn "The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments," Environmental Ethics 13 (1991): 291-310; Eric Katz, "The Big Lie: Human Restoration of Nature," Research in Philosophy and Technology 12 (1992): 231-41.
    • (1982) Inquiry , vol.25 , pp. 81-93
    • Elliot, R.1
  • 13
    • 84947619641 scopus 로고
    • The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments
    • For a discussion of some of the moral issues surrounding restoration, see Robert Elliot, "Faking Nature," Inquiry 25 (1982): 81-93; Alistair Gunn "The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments," Environmental Ethics 13 (1991): 291-310; Eric Katz, "The Big Lie: Human Restoration of Nature," Research in Philosophy and Technology 12 (1992): 231-41.
    • (1991) Environmental Ethics , vol.13 , pp. 291-310
    • Gunn, A.1
  • 14
    • 84947619641 scopus 로고
    • The Big Lie: Human Restoration of Nature
    • For a discussion of some of the moral issues surrounding restoration, see Robert Elliot, "Faking Nature," Inquiry 25 (1982): 81-93; Alistair Gunn "The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments," Environmental Ethics 13 (1991): 291-310; Eric Katz, "The Big Lie: Human Restoration of Nature," Research in Philosophy and Technology 12 (1992): 231-41.
    • (1992) Research in Philosophy and Technology , vol.12 , pp. 231-241
    • Katz, E.1
  • 15
    • 0000892779 scopus 로고
    • Alternative Ideas of Wilderness
    • A number of writers have made similar points. For example, J. Baird Callicott says, "If man is a natural, a wild, an evolving species not essentially different in this respect from all the others, as Snyder reminds us, then the works of man, however precocious, are as natural as those of beavers, or termites, or any of the other species that dramatically modify their habitats," in "Alternative Ideas of Wilderness," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991): 241. For other examples of this concern, see Richard Watson, "A Critique of Anti-Anthropocentric Biocentrism," Environmental Ethics 5 (1983): esp. 251-56, and Alistair Gunn's "The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments," pp. 296-98. For a response see Holmes Rolston, III, "The Wilderness Idea Reaffirmed," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991): 370-77. I briefly discuss Rolston's response in n. 17 below.
    • (1991) The Environmental Professional , vol.13 , pp. 241
    • Baird Callicott, J.1
  • 16
    • 0001520388 scopus 로고
    • A Critique of Anti-Anthropocentric Biocentrism
    • A number of writers have made similar points. For example, J. Baird Callicott says, "If man is a natural, a wild, an evolving species not essentially different in this respect from all the others, as Snyder reminds us, then the works of man, however precocious, are as natural as those of beavers, or termites, or any of the other species that dramatically modify their habitats," in "Alternative Ideas of Wilderness," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991): 241. For other examples of this concern, see Richard Watson, "A Critique of Anti-Anthropocentric Biocentrism," Environmental Ethics 5 (1983): esp. 251-56, and Alistair Gunn's "The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments," pp. 296-98. For a response see Holmes Rolston, III, "The Wilderness Idea Reaffirmed," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991): 370-77. I briefly discuss Rolston's response in n. 17 below.
    • (1983) Environmental Ethics , vol.5 , pp. 251-256
    • Watson, R.1
  • 17
    • 7444221883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A number of writers have made similar points. For example, J. Baird Callicott says, "If man is a natural, a wild, an evolving species not essentially different in this respect from all the others, as Snyder reminds us, then the works of man, however precocious, are as natural as those of beavers, or termites, or any of the other species that dramatically modify their habitats," in "Alternative Ideas of Wilderness," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991): 241. For other examples of this concern, see Richard Watson, "A Critique of Anti-Anthropocentric Biocentrism," Environmental Ethics 5 (1983): esp. 251-56, and Alistair Gunn's "The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments," pp. 296-98. For a response see Holmes Rolston, III, "The Wilderness Idea Reaffirmed," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991): 370-77. I briefly discuss Rolston's response in n. 17 below.
    • The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments , pp. 296-298
    • Gunn'S, A.1
  • 18
    • 0013166502 scopus 로고
    • The Wilderness Idea Reaffirmed
    • A number of writers have made similar points. For example, J. Baird Callicott says, "If man is a natural, a wild, an evolving species not essentially different in this respect from all the others, as Snyder reminds us, then the works of man, however precocious, are as natural as those of beavers, or termites, or any of the other species that dramatically modify their habitats," in "Alternative Ideas of Wilderness," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991): 241. For other examples of this concern, see Richard Watson, "A Critique of Anti-Anthropocentric Biocentrism," Environmental Ethics 5 (1983): esp. 251-56, and Alistair Gunn's "The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments," pp. 296-98. For a response see Holmes Rolston, III, "The Wilderness Idea Reaffirmed," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991): 370-77. I briefly discuss Rolston's response in n. 17 below.
    • (1991) The Environmental Professional , vol.13 , pp. 370-377
    • Rolston III, H.1
  • 19
    • 7444250851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Assuming that the destructive or harmful act is performed by amoral agent. Of course, if it isn't, then while the behavior counts as interference, since it is harmful, it cannot be morally wrong. But that does not affect the point I am making here, that on this account whenever a moral agent interferes it will turn out to be wrong just because of the way in which interference has been characterized.
  • 20
    • 84925921013 scopus 로고
    • Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism
    • Elliot Sober, "Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism," Philosophy of Science 47 (1980): 350-83. Also see Daniel Simberloff, "A Succession of Paradigms in Ecology: Essentialism to Materialism and Probabilism," Synthese 43 (1980): 3-39.
    • (1980) Philosophy of Science , vol.47 , pp. 350-383
    • Sober, E.1
  • 21
    • 0011125621 scopus 로고
    • A Succession of Paradigms in Ecology: Essentialism to Materialism and Probabilism
    • Elliot Sober, "Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism," Philosophy of Science 47 (1980): 350-83. Also see Daniel Simberloff, "A Succession of Paradigms in Ecology: Essentialism to Materialism and Probabilism," Synthese 43 (1980): 3-39.
    • (1980) Synthese , vol.43 , pp. 3-39
    • Simberloff, D.1
  • 24
    • 6944245919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Artifacts and Functions
    • Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield
    • Eric Katz, "Artifacts and Functions," in Nature as Subject : Human Obligations and Natural Communities (Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1997), p. 122. He makes a number of similar points in "The Call of The Wild: The Struggle against Domination and the Technological Fix of Nature," Nature as Subject, especially pp. 114-16.
    • (1997) Nature As Subject : Human Obligations and Natural Communities , pp. 122
    • Katz, E.1
  • 25
    • 7444232264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Call of the Wild: The Struggle against Domination and the Technological Fix of Nature
    • Eric Katz, "Artifacts and Functions," in Nature as Subject : Human Obligations and Natural Communities (Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1997), p. 122. He makes a number of similar points in "The Call of The Wild: The Struggle against Domination and the Technological Fix of Nature," Nature as Subject, especially pp. 114-16.
    • Nature As Subject, Especially , pp. 114-116
  • 27
    • 0013166502 scopus 로고
    • The Wilderness Idea Reaffirmed
    • In some of his work Holmes Rolston contrasts the natural with the cultural. His distinction appears to be very closely related to Katz's even if it is not identical to it. For example, he says, "But, continuing the analysis, surely the fallacy is to think that a nature allegedly improved by humans is anymore real nature at all. The values intrinsic to wilderness cannot, on pain of both logical and empirical contradiction, be 'improved' by deliberate human management, because deliberation is the antithesis of wildness. . . . On the meaning of 'natural' at issue here, that of nature proceeding by evolutionary and ecological processes, any deliberated human agency, however well-intended, is intention nevertheless and interrupts these spontaneous processes and is inevitably artificial, unnatural." Holmes Rolston, III, "The Wilderness Idea Reaffirmed," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991), p. 371. Also see his "Treating Animals Naturally?" Between the Species 5 (Summer 1989): 131-37.
    • (1991) The Environmental Professional , vol.13 , pp. 371
    • Rolston III, H.1
  • 28
    • 7044284358 scopus 로고
    • Treating Animals Naturally?
    • Summer
    • In some of his work Holmes Rolston contrasts the natural with the cultural. His distinction appears to be very closely related to Katz's even if it is not identical to it. For example, he says, "But, continuing the analysis, surely the fallacy is to think that a nature allegedly improved by humans is anymore real nature at all. The values intrinsic to wilderness cannot, on pain of both logical and empirical contradiction, be 'improved' by deliberate human management, because deliberation is the antithesis of wildness. . . . On the meaning of 'natural' at issue here, that of nature proceeding by evolutionary and ecological processes, any deliberated human agency, however well-intended, is intention nevertheless and interrupts these spontaneous processes and is inevitably artificial, unnatural." Holmes Rolston, III, "The Wilderness Idea Reaffirmed," The Environmental Professional 13 (1991), p. 371. Also see his "Treating Animals Naturally?" Between the Species 5 (Summer 1989): 131-37.
    • (1989) Between the Species , vol.5 , pp. 131-137
  • 29
    • 6944245919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most arguments against interference focus on the negative effects of interference on either humans or the ecosystem itself. But Katz's line of argument is broadly Kantian rather than utilitarian. See for example, Katz, "Artifacts and Functions," pp. 129-31, and Katz, "The Big Lie," pp. 239-40.
    • Artifacts and Functions , pp. 129-131
    • Katz1
  • 30
    • 6944247295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most arguments against interference focus on the negative effects of interference on either humans or the ecosystem itself. But Katz's line of argument is broadly Kantian rather than utilitarian. See for example, Katz, "Artifacts and Functions," pp. 129-31, and Katz, "The Big Lie," pp. 239-40.
    • The Big Lie , pp. 239-240
    • Katz1
  • 31
    • 7444240360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Katz discusses the domination of nature in the articles cited in n. 18.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.