메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 19, Issue 2, 2002, Pages 29-57

Pragmatism in bioethics: Been there, done that

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

ANALYTICAL APPROACH; ARTICLE; BIOETHICS; BIOETHICS AND PROFESSIONAL ETHICS; ETHICS; PHILOSOPHICAL APPROACH; PHILOSOPHY; POLITICAL SYSTEM; TECHNIQUE; UNITED STATES;

EID: 0037852111     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052502192028     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (17)

References (98)
  • 2
    • 85013969404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beauchamp is a professor of philosophy at Georgetown University, and Childress taught there during the 1970s while they were working on the first edition of their book
    • Beauchamp is a professor of philosophy at Georgetown University, and Childress taught there during the 1970s while they were working on the first edition of their book.
  • 3
    • 0026112334 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Casuistry in bioethics has been championed by Albert Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin as an alternative methodology to principlism, one that supposedly works from the "bottom up" by means of analogical case analyses-much like the common law-rather than "top down" by means of moral theories and theoretically derived principles. See Albert R. Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin, The Abuse of Casuistry (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988). See also John Arras, "Getting Down to Cases: The Revival of Casuistry in Bioethics, " Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16, no. 1 (1991): 29-51.
    • (1988) The Abuse of Casuistry
    • Jonsen, A.R.1    Toulmin, S.2
  • 4
    • 0026112334 scopus 로고
    • Getting down to cases: The revival of casuistry in bioethics
    • Casuistry in bioethics has been championed by Albert Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin as an alternative methodology to principlism, one that supposedly works from the "bottom up" by means of analogical case analyses-much like the common law-rather than "top down" by means of moral theories and theoretically derived principles. See Albert R. Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin, The Abuse of Casuistry (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988). See also John Arras, "Getting Down to Cases: The Revival of Casuistry in Bioethics, " Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16, no. 1 (1991): 29-51.
    • (1991) Journal of Medicine and Philosophy , vol.16 , Issue.1 , pp. 29-51
    • Arras, J.1
  • 5
    • 0004765296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nice story, but so what?: Narrative and justification in ethics
    • Hilde Lindemann Nelson, ed., New York: Routledge
    • Narrative ethics, like casuistry, gives pride of place to the particularities of persons and social contexts as these are articulated within personal narratives. The emphasis here is on the trajectory of the "patient's story" rather than on the abstractions of theory and principles. See John Arras, "Nice Story, But So What?: Narrative and Justification in Ethics, " in Hilde Lindemann Nelson, ed., Stories and Their Limits: Narrative Approaches to Bioethics (New York: Routledge, 1997).
    • (1997) Stories and Their Limits: Narrative Approaches to Bioethics
    • Arras, J.1
  • 6
    • 0004070687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Feminist criticism in bioethics has focused primarily on gender-related power imbalances in the health-care system. As contributors to the debate over method in bioethics, feminist critics of principlism have lamented the latter's alleged overemphasis on abstract principle and neglect of personal relations, the emotions, and power in the analysis of moral problems. Many feminists are also moral particularists, and thus have much in common with casuists and narrativists. See, e.g., Susan M. Wolf, ed., Feminism and Bioethics: Beyond Reproduction (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996); and Susan Sherwin, No Longer Patient (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1996) Feminism and Bioethics: Beyond Reproduction
    • Wolf, S.M.1
  • 7
    • 0004111392 scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press
    • Feminist criticism in bioethics has focused primarily on gender-related power imbalances in the health-care system. As contributors to the debate over method in bioethics, feminist critics of principlism have lamented the latter's alleged overemphasis on abstract principle and neglect of personal relations, the emotions, and power in the analysis of moral problems. Many feminists are also moral particularists, and thus have much in common with casuists and narrativists. See, e.g., Susan M. Wolf, ed., Feminism and Bioethics: Beyond Reproduction (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996); and Susan Sherwin, No Longer Patient (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1992) No Longer Patient
    • Sherwin, S.1
  • 8
    • 0034970045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming
    • In addition to the present essay, see John D. Arras, "Rorty's Pragmatism and Bioethics" (forthcoming); and John D. Arras, "Freestanding Pragmatism in Law and Bioethics, " Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 22, no. 2 (2001): 69-85.
    • Rorty's Pragmatism and Bioethics
    • Arras, J.D.1
  • 9
    • 0034970045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freestanding pragmatism in law and bioethics
    • In addition to the present essay, see John D. Arras, "Rorty's Pragmatism and Bioethics" (forthcoming); and John D. Arras, "Freestanding Pragmatism in Law and Bioethics, " Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 22, no. 2 (2001): 69-85.
    • (2001) Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics , vol.22 , Issue.2 , pp. 69-85
    • Arras, J.D.1
  • 10
    • 0028659237 scopus 로고
    • Shifting paradigms in bioethics and health law: The rise of a new pragmatism
    • Susan Wolf, "Shifting Paradigms in Bioethics and Health Law: The Rise of a New Pragmatism, " American Journal of Law and Medicine 20, no. 4 (1994): 395-415.
    • (1994) American Journal of Law and Medicine , vol.20 , Issue.4 , pp. 395-415
    • Wolf, S.1
  • 13
    • 0004253694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press
    • Glenn McGee, ed., Pragmatic Bioethics (Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) Pragmatic Bioethics
    • McGee, G.1
  • 15
    • 1642449226 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism without method
    • Rorty, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • As Rorty puts it: "It was as if pragmatism had been crushed between [Paul] Tillich and [Rudolph] Carnap, the upper and the nether millstones." See Richard Rorty, "Pragmatism without Method, " in Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 1:64. The collapse and recent rebirth of Dewey's influence in the United States is nicely chronicled in Alan Ryan, John Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism (New York: W. W. Norton, 1995), 350-71.
    • (1991) Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers , vol.1 , pp. 64
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 16
    • 0003780668 scopus 로고
    • New York: W. W. Norton
    • As Rorty puts it: "It was as if pragmatism had been crushed between [Paul] Tillich and [Rudolph] Carnap, the upper and the nether millstones." See Richard Rorty, "Pragmatism without Method, " in Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 1:64. The collapse and recent rebirth of Dewey's influence in the United States is nicely chronicled in Alan Ryan, John Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism (New York: W. W. Norton, 1995), 350-71.
    • (1995) John Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism , pp. 350-371
    • Ryan, A.1
  • 18
    • 0003839704 scopus 로고
    • Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • Rorty's many other publications include: The Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982); Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989); and Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers.
    • (1982) The Consequences of Pragmatism
  • 19
    • 0003967815 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Rorty's many other publications include: The Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982); Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989); and Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers.
    • (1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity
  • 20
    • 0039031665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rorty's many other publications include: The Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982); Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989); and Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers.
    • Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers
  • 21
    • 0040794111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • American pragmatism: The conflict of narratives
    • Herman J. Saatkamp, Jr., ed., (Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press)
    • For an alternative view that underscores the continuities between "old" and "new" pragmatisms, see Richard Bernstein, "American Pragmatism: The Conflict of Narratives, " in Herman J. Saatkamp, Jr., ed., Rorty and Pragmatism (Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press), 54-67.
    • Rorty and Pragmatism , pp. 54-67
    • Bernstein, R.1
  • 23
    • 0039031664 scopus 로고
    • The pragmatic acquiescence
    • Gail Kennedy, ed., Boston, MA: Heath
    • An early example of the charge that pragmatism subordinates values to "getting results" can be found in Lewis Mumford's attacks on Dewey. See Lewis Mumford, "The Pragmatic Acquiescence, " in Gail Kennedy, ed., Pragmatism and American Culture (Boston, MA: Heath, 1950). Legal philosopher Ronald Dworkin characterizes pragmatism as unprincipled and insouciant about individual rights. See Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986). For bioethical examples, see Leon Kass, Toward a More Natural Science (New York: Free Press, 1985); and Alta Charo, "Principles and Pragmatism, " Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6, no. 3 (1996): 321.
    • (1950) Pragmatism and American Culture
    • Mumford, L.1
  • 24
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • An early example of the charge that pragmatism subordinates values to "getting results" can be found in Lewis Mumford's attacks on Dewey. See Lewis Mumford, "The Pragmatic Acquiescence, " in Gail Kennedy, ed., Pragmatism and American Culture (Boston, MA: Heath, 1950). Legal philosopher Ronald Dworkin characterizes pragmatism as unprincipled and insouciant about individual rights. See Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986). For bioethical examples, see Leon Kass, Toward a More Natural Science (New York: Free Press, 1985); and Alta Charo, "Principles and Pragmatism, " Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6, no. 3 (1996): 321.
    • (1986) Law's Empire
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 25
    • 0003986469 scopus 로고
    • New York: Free Press
    • An early example of the charge that pragmatism subordinates values to "getting results" can be found in Lewis Mumford's attacks on Dewey. See Lewis Mumford, "The Pragmatic Acquiescence, " in Gail Kennedy, ed., Pragmatism and American Culture (Boston, MA: Heath, 1950). Legal philosopher Ronald Dworkin characterizes pragmatism as unprincipled and insouciant about individual rights. See Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986). For bioethical examples, see Leon Kass, Toward a More Natural Science (New York: Free Press, 1985); and Alta Charo, "Principles and Pragmatism, " Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6, no. 3 (1996): 321.
    • (1985) Toward a More Natural Science
    • Kass, L.1
  • 26
    • 85013931427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles and pragmatism
    • An early example of the charge that pragmatism subordinates values to "getting results" can be found in Lewis Mumford's attacks on Dewey. See Lewis Mumford, "The Pragmatic Acquiescence, " in Gail Kennedy, ed., Pragmatism and American Culture (Boston, MA: Heath, 1950). Legal philosopher Ronald Dworkin characterizes pragmatism as unprincipled and insouciant about individual rights. See Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986). For bioethical examples, see Leon Kass, Toward a More Natural Science (New York: Free Press, 1985); and Alta Charo, "Principles and Pragmatism, " Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6, no. 3 (1996): 321.
    • (1996) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.6 , Issue.3 , pp. 321
    • Charo, A.1
  • 28
    • 0002915663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freestanding legal pragmatism
    • Dickstein, ed
    • See, e.g., Thomas C. Grey, "Freestanding Legal Pragmatism, " in Dickstein, ed., The Revival of Pragmatism, 254-74; and Richard A. Posner, "Pragmatic Adjudication, " in Dickstem, ed., The Revival of Pragmatism, 235-53.
    • The Revival of Pragmatism , pp. 254-274
    • Grey, T.C.1
  • 29
    • 0002800411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatic adjudication
    • Dickstem, ed
    • See, e.g., Thomas C. Grey, "Freestanding Legal Pragmatism, " in Dickstein, ed., The Revival of Pragmatism, 254-74; and Richard A. Posner, "Pragmatic Adjudication, " in Dickstem, ed., The Revival of Pragmatism, 235-53.
    • The Revival of Pragmatism , pp. 235-253
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 31
    • 0039031617 scopus 로고
    • Nature in experience
    • Jo Ann Boydston, ed., Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, "Nature in Experience, " in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Later Works, 1925-1953 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1981-1997), 14:150, cited in James T. Kloppenberg, "An Old Name for Some New Ways of Thinking?" in Dickstein, ed., The Revival of Pragmatism, 105.
    • (1981) The Later Works, 1925-1953 , vol.14 , pp. 150
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 32
    • 85013903105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An old name for some new ways of thinking?
    • Dickstein, ed
    • John Dewey, "Nature in Experience, " in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Later Works, 1925-1953 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1981-1997), 14:150, cited in James T. Kloppenberg, "An Old Name for Some New Ways of Thinking?" in Dickstein, ed., The Revival of Pragmatism, 105.
    • The Revival of Pragmatism , pp. 105
    • Kloppenberg, J.T.1
  • 33
    • 33645110738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism: What pragmatism means
    • Goodman, ed
    • William James, "Pragmatism: What Pragmatism Means, " in Goodman, ed., Pragmatism, 60.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 60
    • James, W.1
  • 34
    • 84878140284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Many of these points are nicely summed up by James in ibid., 55-56: A pragmatist turns his back resolutely and once for all upon a lot of inveterate habits dear to professional philosophers. He turns away from abstraction., from verbal solutions, from bad a priori reasons, from fixed principles, closed systems, and pretended absolutes and origins. He turns towards concreteness and adequacy, towards facts, towards action and towards power. It means the open air and possibilities of nature, as against dogma, artificiality, and the pretence of finality in truth.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 55-56
    • James1
  • 35
    • 0039031582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism and the determination of death
    • McGee, ed
    • Martin Benjamin, "Pragmatism and the Determination of Death, " in McGee, ed., Pragmatic Bioethics, 191.
    • Pragmatic Bioethics , pp. 191
    • Benjamin, M.1
  • 36
    • 0003386206 scopus 로고
    • Reconstruction in philosophy
    • Jo Ann Boydston, ed
    • John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy, in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Middle Works, 1899-1924 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1982), 12:94.
    • (1982) The Middle Works, 1899-1924 , vol.12 , pp. 94
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 37
    • 0040810210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • Jennifer Welchman, Dewey's Ethical Thought (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1995), 193.
    • (1995) Dewey's Ethical Thought , pp. 193
    • Welchman, J.1
  • 39
    • 0040215762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism and law
    • Dickstein, ed
    • This contrast is nicely drawn in Richard Rorty, "Pragmatism and Law, " in Dickstein, ed., The Revival of Pragmatism, 310.
    • The Revival of Pragmatism , pp. 310
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 40
    • 0004187886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: United Hospital Fund of New York
    • Nancy Dubler and Leonard Marcus, Mediating Bioethical Disputes (New York: United Hospital Fund of New York, 1994); Moreno, Deciding Together.
    • (1994) Mediating Bioethical Disputes
    • Dubler, N.1    Marcus, L.2
  • 41
    • 0003648919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nancy Dubler and Leonard Marcus, Mediating Bioethical Disputes (New York: United Hospital Fund of New York, 1994); Moreno, Deciding Together.
    • Deciding Together
    • Moreno1
  • 42
    • 0039623882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This collaborative and democratic model of contemporary bioethical practice contrasts sharply with H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr.'s characterization of bioethicists as moral experts and secular priests. See, in this volume, H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., "The Ordination of Bioethicists as Secular Moral Experts." Although Engelhardt tells a plausible story here about the rise of contemporary bioethics to public prominence against the backdrop of our society's loss of faith in technocratic expertise and the public pronouncements of church leaders, his account of the social function of bioethicists is based upon highly selective evidence and, thus, bears little resemblance to the everyday reality of most bioethicists.
    • The Ordination of Bioethicists As Secular Moral Experts
    • Engelhardt, H.T.1
  • 43
    • 0039031663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatic method and bioethics
    • McGee, ed
    • See Glenn McGee, "Pragmatic Method and Bioethics, " in McGee, ed., Pragmatic Bioethics, 19: "John Dewey produced perhaps the clearest account of how pragmatism can revolutionize bioethics in his book about method, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry."
    • Pragmatic Bioethics , pp. 19
    • McGee, G.1
  • 44
    • 0003673004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Glenn McGee, "Pragmatic Method and Bioethics, " in McGee, ed., Pragmatic Bioethics, 19: "John Dewey produced perhaps the clearest account of how pragmatism can revolutionize bioethics in his book about method, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry."
    • Logic: The Theory of Inquiry
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 46
    • 0003996797 scopus 로고
    • Boston: Heath
    • John Dewey, How We Think (Boston: Heath, 1910), 72, quoted in Miller et al., "Clinical Pragmatism, " 33.
    • (1910) How We Think , pp. 72
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 47
    • 85013970552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Dewey, How We Think (Boston: Heath, 1910), 72, quoted in Miller et al., "Clinical Pragmatism, " 33.
    • Clinical Pragmatism , pp. 33
    • Miller1
  • 48
    • 0028825863 scopus 로고
    • A controlled trial to improve care for seriously ill hospitalized patients: The Study to Understand Prognoses and Preferences for Outcomes and Risks of Treatments (SUPPORT)
    • See, e.g., Alfred F. Connors et al., "A Controlled Trial to Improve Care for Seriously Ill Hospitalized Patients: The Study to Understand Prognoses and Preferences for Outcomes and Risks of Treatments (SUPPORT), " Journal of the American Medical Association 274, no. 20 (1995): 1591ff.
    • (1995) Journal of the American Medical Association , vol.274 , Issue.20 , pp. 1591ff
    • Connors, A.F.1
  • 49
    • 85013923537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An analogous case of principlism failing to exploit its own latent resources has come to light through the feminist critique of bioethics. Although the principle of justice could, in theory, have provided principlists with ample resources with which to reveal and criticize various forms of gender-based inequities in medicine and research, it was not until the advent of the feminist critique that principlists began noticing the existence of a problem
    • An analogous case of principlism failing to exploit its own latent resources has come to light through the feminist critique of bioethics. Although the principle of justice could, in theory, have provided principlists with ample resources with which to reveal and criticize various forms of gender-based inequities in medicine and research, it was not until the advent of the feminist critique that principlists began noticing the existence of a problem.
  • 51
    • 0028885092 scopus 로고
    • The treatment of non-HIV-related conditions in newborns at risk for HIV: A survey of neonatologists
    • Typical examples of such empirical studies include the SUPPORT project (see note 34); Betty Wolder Levin et al., "The Treatment of Non-HIV-Related Conditions in Newborns at Risk for HIV: A Survey of Neonatologists, " American Journal of Public Health 85, no. 11 (1995): 1507-13; Susan E. Kelly et al., "Understanding the Practice of Ethics Consultation: Results of an Ethnographic Multi-Site Study, " Journal of Clinical Ethics 8, no. 2 (1997): 136-49; and Leslie J. Blackhall et al., "Ethnicity and Attitudes towards Life Sustaining Technology, " Social Science and Medicine 48, no. 12 (1999): 1779-89.
    • (1995) American Journal of Public Health , vol.85 , Issue.11 , pp. 1507-1513
    • Levin, B.W.1
  • 52
    • 0031157713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding the practice of ethics consultation: Results of an ethnographic multi-site study
    • Typical examples of such empirical studies include the SUPPORT project (see note 34); Betty Wolder Levin et al., "The Treatment of Non-HIV-Related Conditions in Newborns at Risk for HIV: A Survey of Neonatologists, " American Journal of Public Health 85, no. 11 (1995): 1507-13; Susan E. Kelly et al., "Understanding the Practice of Ethics Consultation: Results of an Ethnographic Multi-Site Study, " Journal of Clinical Ethics 8, no. 2 (1997): 136-49; and Leslie J. Blackhall et al., "Ethnicity and Attitudes towards Life Sustaining Technology, " Social Science and Medicine 48, no. 12 (1999): 1779-89.
    • (1997) Journal of Clinical Ethics , vol.8 , Issue.2 , pp. 136-149
    • Kelly, S.E.1
  • 53
    • 0033041886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethnicity and attitudes towards life sustaining technology
    • Typical examples of such empirical studies include the SUPPORT project (see note 34); Betty Wolder Levin et al., "The Treatment of Non-HIV-Related Conditions in Newborns at Risk for HIV: A Survey of Neonatologists, " American Journal of Public Health 85, no. 11 (1995): 1507-13; Susan E. Kelly et al., "Understanding the Practice of Ethics Consultation: Results of an Ethnographic Multi-Site Study, " Journal of Clinical Ethics 8, no. 2 (1997): 136-49; and Leslie J. Blackhall et al., "Ethnicity and Attitudes towards Life Sustaining Technology, " Social Science and Medicine 48, no. 12 (1999): 1779-89.
    • (1999) Social Science and Medicine , vol.48 , Issue.12 , pp. 1779-1789
    • Blackhall, L.J.1
  • 54
    • 85013980106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dewey's emphasis on understanding the social context of moral problems thus meshes nicely with Allen Buchanan's call, in this volume, for the development of a "Social Moral Epistemology."
    • Dewey's emphasis on understanding the social context of moral problems thus meshes nicely with Allen Buchanan's call, in this volume, for the development of a "Social Moral Epistemology."
  • 55
    • 0008808077 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Blackwell
    • Dewey's rejection of the kind of objectivity demanded by the spectator view did not lead him to reject any and all conceptions of moral objectivity. Rather, he sought objectivity in our capacity to resolve conflicts and achieve agreement on shared values. Dewey would have thus fully concurred with Hilary Putnam's dictum: "[A]ccess to a common reality does not require access to something preconceptual. It requires, rather, that we be able to form shared concepts." See Hilary Putnam, Pragmatism: An Open Question (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1995), 21. I thank Frances Kamm for requesting clarification of this point.
    • (1995) Pragmatism: An Open Question , pp. 21
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 56
    • 0025709602 scopus 로고
    • Two having a baby to save daughter
    • February 17
    • For more on the Ayala case, see "Two Having a Baby to Save Daughter, " New York Times, February 17, 1990, 10.
    • (1990) New York Times , pp. 10
  • 57
    • 0040215705 scopus 로고
    • New York: Henry Holt
    • John Dewey and James H. Tufts, Ethics, rev. ed. (New York: Henry Holt, 1932), 304. See also John Dewey, "Logical Method and Law, " Cornell Law Quarterly 10 (1925): 22 ("[G]eneral principles emerge as statements of generic ways in which it has been found helpful to treat concrete cases").
    • (1932) Ethics, Rev. Ed. , pp. 304
    • Dewey, J.1    Tufts, J.H.2
  • 58
    • 0009269563 scopus 로고
    • Logical method and law
    • John Dewey and James H. Tufts, Ethics, rev. ed. (New York: Henry Holt, 1932), 304. See also John Dewey, "Logical Method and Law, " Cornell Law Quarterly 10 (1925): 22 ("[G]eneral principles emerge as statements of generic ways in which it has been found helpful to treat concrete cases").
    • (1925) Cornell Law Quarterly , vol.10 , pp. 22
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 59
    • 0004288335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Bernard Gert et al. charge that Beauchamp and Childress's principles function as mere "chapter headings"-i.e., as categories of important values to consider as we make moral choices-as opposed to precise, action-guiding rules of conduct. See Bernard Gert, Charles Culver, and K. Danner Clouser, Bioethics: A Return to Fundamentals (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997). Interestingly, Dewey would side with Beauchamp and Childress in this debate, challenging the belittling qualifier "mere." Thus, even though contemporary pragmatists have opposed much in the method of principlism, the latter's principal exponents agree with Dewey that principles are initially framed at such a level of generality that they cannot be definitively action-guiding in the absence of additional specification, balancing, and good judgment.
    • (1997) Bioethics: A Return to Fundamentals
    • Gert, B.1    Culver, C.2    Clouser, K.D.3
  • 60
    • 0039031601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bioethics is a naturalism
    • McGee, ed
    • Note in this connection Moreno's claim that within a naturalistic or pragmatist approach to ethics, facts tend to overwhelm theory. See Jonathan Moreno, "Bioethics Is a Naturalism, " in McGee, ed., Pragmatic Bioethics, 13.
    • Pragmatic Bioethics , pp. 13
    • Moreno, J.1
  • 61
    • 0003403756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Modern Library
    • Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (New York: Modern Library, 1957), 221.
    • (1957) Human Nature and Conduct , pp. 221
    • Dewey1
  • 62
    • 84875351130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dewey and Tufts, Ethics, 313; and Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct, 221.
    • Ethics , pp. 313
    • Dewey1    Tufts2
  • 66
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • According to Rawls, principles are developed both to systematize our firmest intuitions about particular propositions and to extend our judgments in less clear cases. Importantly, however, he observes that principles can also be revised or rejected on the basis of particularly firm moral intuitions. The goal of moral reflection, he claims, is to continually adjust our principles, our firmest intuitions, and our background theories of persons and society until they harmonize in "reflective equilibrium." See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 20-22.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 20-22
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 67
    • 0025443879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to say that everyone operating within the field of bioethics always employs principles in this flexible way. Secular thinkers of a more traditional bent, such as Leon Kass, or conservative Roman Catholics, Protestants, and Jews, are far from embracing pragmatist modes of moral thought. See, e.g., Kass, Toward a More Natural Science; John J. O'Connor, "Abortion: Questions and Answers, " Human Life Review 16, no. 3 (1990): 65-96; Paul Ramsey, Ethics at the Edges of Life (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978); and David Bleich, Bioethical Dilemmas: A Jewish Perspective (Hoboken, NJ: Ktav Publishing House, 1998).
    • Toward a More Natural Science
    • Kass1
  • 68
    • 0025443879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abortion: Questions and answers
    • This is not to say that everyone operating within the field of bioethics always employs principles in this flexible way. Secular thinkers of a more traditional bent, such as Leon Kass, or conservative Roman Catholics, Protestants, and Jews, are far from embracing pragmatist modes of moral thought. See, e.g., Kass, Toward a More Natural Science; John J. O'Connor, "Abortion: Questions and Answers, " Human Life Review 16, no. 3 (1990): 65-96; Paul Ramsey, Ethics at the Edges of Life (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978); and David Bleich, Bioethical Dilemmas: A Jewish Perspective (Hoboken, NJ: Ktav Publishing House, 1998).
    • (1990) Human Life Review , vol.16 , Issue.3 , pp. 65-96
    • O'Connor, J.J.1
  • 69
    • 0025443879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • This is not to say that everyone operating within the field of bioethics always employs principles in this flexible way. Secular thinkers of a more traditional bent, such as Leon Kass, or conservative Roman Catholics, Protestants, and Jews, are far from embracing pragmatist modes of moral thought. See, e.g., Kass, Toward a More Natural Science; John J. O'Connor, "Abortion: Questions and Answers, " Human Life Review 16, no. 3 (1990): 65-96; Paul Ramsey, Ethics at the Edges of Life (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978); and David Bleich, Bioethical Dilemmas: A Jewish Perspective (Hoboken, NJ: Ktav Publishing House, 1998).
    • (1978) Ethics at the Edges of Life
    • Ramsey, P.1
  • 70
    • 0025443879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hoboken, NJ: Ktav Publishing House
    • This is not to say that everyone operating within the field of bioethics always employs principles in this flexible way. Secular thinkers of a more traditional bent, such as Leon Kass, or conservative Roman Catholics, Protestants, and Jews, are far from embracing pragmatist modes of moral thought. See, e.g., Kass, Toward a More Natural Science; John J. O'Connor, "Abortion: Questions and Answers, " Human Life Review 16, no. 3 (1990): 65-96; Paul Ramsey, Ethics at the Edges of Life (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978); and David Bleich, Bioethical Dilemmas: A Jewish Perspective (Hoboken, NJ: Ktav Publishing House, 1998).
    • (1998) Bioethical Dilemmas: A Jewish Perspective
    • Bleich, D.1
  • 71
    • 0004086530 scopus 로고
    • New York: Random House
    • Indeed, perhaps the most interesting link between pragmatism and a theory of practical reasoning in bioethics is to be found not in the writings of Dewey, but rather in the "pragmatic" writings of post-World War II Harvard philosophers W. V. O. Quine and John Rawls. Quine conceived of human knowledge as a "web of belief, " while Rawls eschewed foundationalism in moral theory in favor of reflective equilibrium. I thank Christopher Morris for this observation. See W. V. O. Quine and J. S. Ullian, The Web of Belief, 2d ed. (New York: Random House, 1978). I would emphasize, however, that acknowledging such a connection between contemporary versions of pragmatism and current methods of bioethics does not advance the claim under discussion-namely, that we need to develop a pragmatist bioethics in order to improve the way we currently do ethics.
    • (1978) The Web of Belief, 2d Ed.
    • Quine, W.V.O.1    Ullian, J.S.2
  • 72
    • 0032009377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Assessing clinical pragmatism
    • pursues this line of criticism in her helpful essay
    • Lynn A. Jansen pursues this line of criticism in her helpful essay, "Assessing Clinical Pragmatism, " Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 8, no. 1 (1998): 23-36.
    • (1998) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.8 , Issue.1 , pp. 23-36
    • Jansen, L.A.1
  • 74
    • 0007667329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clinical pragmatism: A model for problem solving
    • McGee, ed
    • Joseph Fins, Matthew Bacchetta, and Franklin Miller, "Clinical Pragmatism: A Model for Problem Solving, " in McGee, ed., Pragmatic Bioethics, 30.
    • Pragmatic Bioethics , pp. 30
    • Fins, J.1    Bacchetta, M.2    Miller, F.3
  • 76
    • 0003403756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although Dewey rejected traditional metaphysics, especially its attempt to ground human knowledge and behavior in an absolute, unchanging realm of being, he did develop a rival metaphysics of human nature based instead on our thoroughly contingent biological, social, and historical existence. See Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct.
    • Human Nature and Conduct
    • Dewey1
  • 79
    • 0004326964 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Dewey, Ethics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1908), 431, quoted in Matthew Festenstein, Pragmatism and Political Theory: From Dewey to Rorty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997), 59.
    • (1908) Ethics , pp. 431
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 83
    • 0004006101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Athens, OH: Ohio University Press
    • John Dewey, The Public and Its Problems (Athens, OH: Ohio University Press, 1927), 202-9.
    • (1927) The Public and Its Problems , pp. 202-209
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 87
    • 0009239610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A reconsideration of Deweyan democracy
    • reprinted in Goodman, ed
    • Hilary Putnam, "A Reconsideration of Deweyan Democracy, " reprinted in Goodman, ed., Pragmatism, 184-204.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 184-204
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 88
    • 85013883837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To squeeze Putnam into our grid of old versus new pragmatists, it would perhaps be best to label him a "new old pragmatist" - new, because he is our contemporary, and old, because unlike Rorty he is trying to forge a philosophical argument for the justification of democracy that Dewey himself could have endorsed
    • To squeeze Putnam into our grid of old versus new pragmatists, it would perhaps be best to label him a "new old pragmatist" - new, because he is our contemporary, and old, because unlike Rorty he is trying to forge a philosophical argument for the justification of democracy that Dewey himself could have endorsed.
  • 90
    • 0003464922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: MIT Press
    • See James Bohman and William Rehg, eds., Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997). It should be noted, however, that much of the current literature concerning the theory of deliberative democracy seems to owe a lot more to the influence of John Rawls's later work than it does to Dewey, whom it rarely mentions. See Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited, " reprinted in John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 129-80.
    • (1997) Deliberative Democracy
    • Bohman, J.1    Rehg, W.2
  • 91
    • 0039031609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea of public reason revisited
    • reprinted in John Rawls, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See James Bohman and William Rehg, eds., Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997). It should be noted, however, that much of the current literature concerning the theory of deliberative democracy seems to owe a lot more to the influence of John Rawls's later work than it does to Dewey, whom it rarely mentions. See Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited, " reprinted in John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 129-80.
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 129-180
    • Rawls1
  • 92
    • 0003648919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Moreno, Deciding Together; Susan Wolf, "Ethics Committees and Due Process: Nesting Rights in a Community of Care, " Maryland Law Review 50 (1991): 798-858; Susan Wolf, "Toward a Theory of Process, " Law, Medicine, and Health Care 20, no. 4 (1992): 278-90; Martin Benjamin, Splitting the Difference: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1990); Ruth Ellen Bulger et al., eds., Society's Choices: Social and Ethical Decision Making in Biomedicine (Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 1995); and Nancy Dubler and Leonard Marcus, Mediating Bioethical Disputes.
    • Deciding Together
    • Moreno1
  • 93
    • 0026365705 scopus 로고
    • Ethics committees and due process: Nesting rights in a community of care
    • See, e.g., Moreno, Deciding Together; Susan Wolf, "Ethics Committees and Due Process: Nesting Rights in a Community of Care, " Maryland Law Review 50 (1991): 798-858; Susan Wolf, "Toward a Theory of Process, " Law, Medicine, and Health Care 20, no. 4 (1992): 278-90; Martin Benjamin, Splitting the Difference: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1990); Ruth Ellen Bulger et al., eds., Society's Choices: Social and Ethical Decision Making in Biomedicine (Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 1995); and Nancy Dubler and Leonard Marcus, Mediating Bioethical Disputes.
    • (1991) Maryland Law Review , vol.50 , pp. 798-858
    • Wolf, S.1
  • 94
    • 84985294528 scopus 로고
    • Toward a theory of process
    • See, e.g., Moreno, Deciding Together; Susan Wolf, "Ethics Committees and Due Process: Nesting Rights in a Community of Care, " Maryland Law Review 50 (1991): 798-858; Susan Wolf, "Toward a Theory of Process, " Law, Medicine, and Health Care 20, no. 4 (1992): 278-90; Martin Benjamin, Splitting the Difference: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1990); Ruth Ellen Bulger et al., eds., Society's Choices: Social and Ethical Decision Making in Biomedicine (Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 1995); and Nancy Dubler and Leonard Marcus, Mediating Bioethical Disputes.
    • (1992) Law, Medicine, and Health Care , vol.20 , Issue.4 , pp. 278-290
    • Wolf, S.1
  • 95
    • 0003685162 scopus 로고
    • Lawrence: University Press of Kansas
    • See, e.g., Moreno, Deciding Together; Susan Wolf, "Ethics Committees and Due Process: Nesting Rights in a Community of Care, " Maryland Law Review 50 (1991): 798-858; Susan Wolf, "Toward a Theory of Process, " Law, Medicine, and Health Care 20, no. 4 (1992): 278-90; Martin Benjamin, Splitting the Difference: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1990); Ruth Ellen Bulger et al., eds., Society's Choices: Social and Ethical Decision Making in Biomedicine (Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 1995); and Nancy Dubler and Leonard Marcus, Mediating Bioethical Disputes.
    • (1990) Splitting the Difference: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics
    • Benjamin, M.1
  • 96
    • 0003662174 scopus 로고
    • Washington, DC: National Academy Press
    • See, e.g., Moreno, Deciding Together; Susan Wolf, "Ethics Committees and Due Process: Nesting Rights in a Community of Care, " Maryland Law Review 50 (1991): 798-858; Susan Wolf, "Toward a Theory of Process, " Law, Medicine, and Health Care 20, no. 4 (1992): 278-90; Martin Benjamin, Splitting the Difference: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1990); Ruth Ellen Bulger et al., eds., Society's Choices: Social and Ethical Decision Making in Biomedicine (Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 1995); and Nancy Dubler and Leonard Marcus, Mediating Bioethical Disputes.
    • (1995) Society's Choices: Social and Ethical Decision Making in Biomedicine
    • Bulger, R.E.1
  • 97
    • 0004187886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Moreno, Deciding Together; Susan Wolf, "Ethics Committees and Due Process: Nesting Rights in a Community of Care, " Maryland Law Review 50 (1991): 798-858; Susan Wolf, "Toward a Theory of Process, " Law, Medicine, and Health Care 20, no. 4 (1992): 278-90; Martin Benjamin, Splitting the Difference: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1990); Ruth Ellen Bulger et al., eds., Society's Choices: Social and Ethical Decision Making in Biomedicine (Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 1995); and Nancy Dubler and Leonard Marcus, Mediating Bioethical Disputes.
    • Mediating Bioethical Disputes
    • Dubler, N.1    Marcus, L.2
  • 98
    • 85013909260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evidence for this hypothesis can be found on the back cover of my edition of Dewey's The Public and Its Problems, which features a blurb from The Whole Earth Catalogue: "[I]n this book, the dazzlement [?] [of Dewey's ideas] is fully let loose in a series of far-out proposals for experimenting with altered life styles!" Far out, indeed
    • Evidence for this hypothesis can be found on the back cover of my edition of Dewey's The Public and Its Problems, which features a blurb from The Whole Earth Catalogue: "[I]n this book, the dazzlement [?] [of Dewey's ideas] is fully let loose in a series of far-out proposals for experimenting with altered life styles!" Far out, indeed.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.