-
1
-
-
0006548125
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
On these characteristic liberal arguments, see Uday Singh Mehta, Liberalism and Empire (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 46-76.
-
(1999)
Liberalism and Empire
, pp. 46-76
-
-
Mehta, U.S.1
-
2
-
-
77953953163
-
Introduction: Tocqueville et la doctrine coloniale
-
Paris: Editions complexe
-
Tzevetan Todorov rather implausibly argues that Tocqueville projected the classic liberal notion of individual sovereignty into the international arena and hence single-mindedly pursued the French national interest without inconsistency. "Introduction: Tocqueville et la doctrine coloniale," in De la colonie en Algérie, ed. T. Todorov (Paris: Editions complexe, 1988), 24-27. For a similar argument see Stéphane Dion, "Durham et Tocqueville sur la colonisation libérale," Revue d'études canadiennes/Review of Canadian Studies 25, no. 1 (Spring 1990): 60-77. The best discussions of Tocqueville on Algeria are the classic article by Melvin Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," Review of Politics 25 (July 1963): 362-99, and recent work by Jennifer Pitts. Both present Tocqueville as an inconsistent universalist, although they differ on the nature of his inconsistencies and the best way to contextualize these "lapses." Pitts has published an excellent English translation of Tocqueville's writings on Algeria, Writings on Empire and Slavery (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001), from which I have cited throughout this article. See also her "Empire and Democracy: Tocqueville and the Algeria Question," Journal of Political Philosophy 8, no. 3 (2000): 295-318. For an analysis that links Tocqueville's position on Algeria to the weakness of his concept of political reason, see Michael Hereth, Alexis de Tocqueville: Threats to Freedom in Democracy, trans. George Bogardus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1986), 145-65.
-
(1988)
De la Colonie en Algérie
, pp. 24-27
-
-
Todorov, T.1
-
3
-
-
0038759384
-
Durham et tocqueville sur la colonisation libérale
-
Spring
-
Tzevetan Todorov rather implausibly argues that Tocqueville projected the classic liberal notion of individual sovereignty into the international arena and hence single-mindedly pursued the French national interest without inconsistency. "Introduction: Tocqueville et la doctrine coloniale," in De la colonie en Algérie, ed. T. Todorov (Paris: Editions complexe, 1988), 24-27. For a similar argument see Stéphane Dion, "Durham et Tocqueville sur la colonisation libérale," Revue d'études canadiennes/Review of Canadian Studies 25, no. 1 (Spring 1990): 60-77. The best discussions of Tocqueville on Algeria are the classic article by Melvin Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," Review of Politics 25 (July 1963): 362-99, and recent work by Jennifer Pitts. Both present Tocqueville as an inconsistent universalist, although they differ on the nature of his inconsistencies and the best way to contextualize these "lapses." Pitts has published an excellent English translation of Tocqueville's writings on Algeria, Writings on Empire and Slavery (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001), from which I have cited throughout this article. See also her "Empire and Democracy: Tocqueville and the Algeria Question," Journal of Political Philosophy 8, no. 3 (2000): 295-318. For an analysis that links Tocqueville's position on Algeria to the weakness of his concept of political reason, see Michael Hereth, Alexis de Tocqueville: Threats to Freedom in Democracy, trans. George Bogardus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1986), 145-65.
-
(1990)
Revue D'Études Canadiennes/Review of Canadian Studies
, vol.25
, Issue.1
, pp. 60-77
-
-
Dion, S.1
-
4
-
-
0009221061
-
Tocqueville on Algeria
-
July
-
Tzevetan Todorov rather implausibly argues that Tocqueville projected the classic liberal notion of individual sovereignty into the international arena and hence single-mindedly pursued the French national interest without inconsistency. "Introduction: Tocqueville et la doctrine coloniale," in De la colonie en Algérie, ed. T. Todorov (Paris: Editions complexe, 1988), 24-27. For a similar argument see Stéphane Dion, "Durham et Tocqueville sur la colonisation libérale," Revue d'études canadiennes/Review of Canadian Studies 25, no. 1 (Spring 1990): 60-77. The best discussions of Tocqueville on Algeria are the classic article by Melvin Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," Review of Politics 25 (July 1963): 362-99, and recent work by Jennifer Pitts. Both present Tocqueville as an inconsistent universalist, although they differ on the nature of his inconsistencies and the best way to contextualize these "lapses." Pitts has published an excellent English translation of Tocqueville's writings on Algeria, Writings on Empire and Slavery (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001), from which I have cited throughout this article. See also her "Empire and Democracy: Tocqueville and the Algeria Question," Journal of Political Philosophy 8, no. 3 (2000): 295-318. For an analysis that links Tocqueville's position on Algeria to the weakness of his concept of political reason, see Michael Hereth, Alexis de Tocqueville: Threats to Freedom in Democracy, trans. George Bogardus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1986), 145-65.
-
(1963)
Review of Politics
, vol.25
, pp. 362-399
-
-
Richter, M.1
-
5
-
-
0013006943
-
-
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press
-
Tzevetan Todorov rather implausibly argues that Tocqueville projected the classic liberal notion of individual sovereignty into the international arena and hence single-mindedly pursued the French national interest without inconsistency. "Introduction: Tocqueville et la doctrine coloniale," in De la colonie en Algérie, ed. T. Todorov (Paris: Editions complexe, 1988), 24-27. For a similar argument see Stéphane Dion, "Durham et Tocqueville sur la colonisation libérale," Revue d'études canadiennes/Review of Canadian Studies 25, no. 1 (Spring 1990): 60-77. The best discussions of Tocqueville on Algeria are the classic article by Melvin Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," Review of Politics 25 (July 1963): 362-99, and recent work by Jennifer Pitts. Both present Tocqueville as an inconsistent universalist, although they differ on the nature of his inconsistencies and the best way to contextualize these "lapses." Pitts has published an excellent English translation of Tocqueville's writings on Algeria, Writings on Empire and Slavery (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001), from which I have cited throughout this article. See also her "Empire and Democracy: Tocqueville and the Algeria Question," Journal of Political Philosophy 8, no. 3 (2000): 295-318. For an analysis that links Tocqueville's position on Algeria to the weakness of his concept of political reason, see Michael Hereth, Alexis de Tocqueville: Threats to Freedom in Democracy, trans. George Bogardus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1986), 145-65.
-
(2001)
Writings on Empire and Slavery
-
-
-
6
-
-
0034391730
-
Empire and democracy: Tocqueville and the Algeria question
-
Tzevetan Todorov rather implausibly argues that Tocqueville projected the classic liberal notion of individual sovereignty into the international arena and hence single-mindedly pursued the French national interest without inconsistency. "Introduction: Tocqueville et la doctrine coloniale," in De la colonie en Algérie, ed. T. Todorov (Paris: Editions complexe, 1988), 24-27. For a similar argument see Stéphane Dion, "Durham et Tocqueville sur la colonisation libérale," Revue d'études canadiennes/Review of Canadian Studies 25, no. 1 (Spring 1990): 60-77. The best discussions of Tocqueville on Algeria are the classic article by Melvin Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," Review of Politics 25 (July 1963): 362-99, and recent work by Jennifer Pitts. Both present Tocqueville as an inconsistent universalist, although they differ on the nature of his inconsistencies and the best way to contextualize these "lapses." Pitts has published an excellent English translation of Tocqueville's writings on Algeria, Writings on Empire and Slavery (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001), from which I have cited throughout this article. See also her "Empire and Democracy: Tocqueville and the Algeria Question," Journal of Political Philosophy 8, no. 3 (2000): 295-318. For an analysis that links Tocqueville's position on Algeria to the weakness of his concept of political reason, see Michael Hereth, Alexis de Tocqueville: Threats to Freedom in Democracy, trans. George Bogardus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1986), 145-65.
-
(2000)
Journal of Political Philosophy
, vol.8
, Issue.3
, pp. 295-318
-
-
-
7
-
-
0005084726
-
-
trans. George Bogardus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press
-
Tzevetan Todorov rather implausibly argues that Tocqueville projected the classic liberal notion of individual sovereignty into the international arena and hence single-mindedly pursued the French national interest without inconsistency. "Introduction: Tocqueville et la doctrine coloniale," in De la colonie en Algérie, ed. T. Todorov (Paris: Editions complexe, 1988), 24-27. For a similar argument see Stéphane Dion, "Durham et Tocqueville sur la colonisation libérale," Revue d'études canadiennes/Review of Canadian Studies 25, no. 1 (Spring 1990): 60-77. The best discussions of Tocqueville on Algeria are the classic article by Melvin Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," Review of Politics 25 (July 1963): 362-99, and recent work by Jennifer Pitts. Both present Tocqueville as an inconsistent universalist, although they differ on the nature of his inconsistencies and the best way to contextualize these "lapses." Pitts has published an excellent English translation of Tocqueville's writings on Algeria, Writings on Empire and Slavery (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001), from which I have cited throughout this article. See also her "Empire and Democracy: Tocqueville and the Algeria Question," Journal of Political Philosophy 8, no. 3 (2000): 295-318. For an analysis that links Tocqueville's position on Algeria to the weakness of his concept of political reason, see Michael Hereth, Alexis de Tocqueville: Threats to Freedom in Democracy, trans. George Bogardus (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1986), 145-65.
-
(1986)
Alexis de Tocqueville: Threats to Freedom in Democracy
, pp. 145-165
-
-
Hereth, M.1
-
8
-
-
0013006945
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
For my view of the place of ethical argument in Tocqueville, see De Tocqueville (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 32-42, 165-216.
-
(2001)
De Tocqueville
, pp. 32-42
-
-
-
9
-
-
0003624191
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press
-
I borrow this phrase from John Rawls's Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), xviii. Rawls uses it to characterize a political situation in which differing transcendent notions of the good are introduced into politics, producing conflicts that can be moderated only by serendipity, exhaustive conflict, or "reasonable" accommodations based on public recognition of equality and liberty. I am using it here in a loose analogy to suggest the internal psychological conflict produced by simultaneous commitments to apparently conflicting ultimate ends.
-
(1996)
Political Liberalism
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
10
-
-
0038082725
-
Fragments et notes inédites sur la révolution
-
(Paris: Gallimard
-
Tocqueville referred to the normative limits exceeded by terrorists in the French Revolution as "maximes humaines." "Fragments et notes inédites sur la révolution," in Oeuvres complètes, ed. J. P. Mayer (Paris: Gallimard, 1954-), 2:2, 227 (hereafter cited as OC).
-
(1954)
Oeuvres Complètes
, vol.2
, Issue.2
, pp. 227
-
-
Mayer, J.P.1
-
11
-
-
0009154225
-
-
Paris: P. Dufart
-
Other reasons proposed for the French desire to control North Africa include the influence of commercial elements in Marseilles. See Amedée Desjobert, La question d'Alger: politique, colonisation, commerce (Paris: P. Dufart, 1837), 161-64. For a later historical judgment, see André Jardin and André-Jean Tudesq, Restoration and Reaction: 1815-1848, trans. Elborg Forster (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983). 159-60.
-
(1837)
La Question D'Alger: Politique, Colonisation, Commerce
, pp. 161-164
-
-
Desjobert, A.1
-
12
-
-
0012649104
-
-
trans. Elborg Forster (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Other reasons proposed for the French desire to control North Africa include the influence of commercial elements in Marseilles. See Amedée Desjobert, La question d'Alger: politique, colonisation, commerce (Paris: P. Dufart, 1837), 161-64. For a later historical judgment, see André Jardin and André-Jean Tudesq, Restoration and Reaction: 1815-1848, trans. Elborg Forster (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983). 159-60.
-
(1983)
Restoration and Reaction: 1815-1848
, pp. 159-160
-
-
Jardin, A.1
Tudesq, A.-J.2
-
13
-
-
79956148170
-
-
Tocqueville quoted General Bugeaud in a speech to the Chamber in 1846, "Intervention," 118. Chouans were royalist guerillas in the French Revolution; chouannerie was a neologism also employed to characterize Spanish resistance to Napoleon in the peninsular war.
-
Intervention
, pp. 118
-
-
-
14
-
-
0037744505
-
-
New York: Holmes & Meier
-
By 1848 it is estimated that more than a tenth of the Arab population had been killed and the economy was in ruins. Raphael Danziger, Abd al-Qadir and the Algerians: Resistance to the French and Internal Consolidation (New York: Holmes & Meier, 1977), xi. For subsequent judgments that only such destructive measures could have brought success, given the resistance encountered in North Africa, see Jean Gottman, "Bugeaud, Galliéni, Lyautey: The Development of French Colonial Warfare," in Makers of Modern Strategy: Military Thought from Machiavelli to Hitler, ed. E. M. Earle, G. A. Craig, and F. Gilbert (New York: Atheneum, 1967). 236-38; Jeremy Black, Western Warfare 1775-1882 (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 2001), 86-87.
-
(1977)
Abd Al-Qadir and the Algerians: Resistance to the French and Internal Consolidation
-
-
Danziger, R.1
-
15
-
-
17144363323
-
Bugeaud, galliéni, lyautey: The development of French colonial warfare
-
ed. E. M. Earle, G. A. Craig, and F. Gilbert (New York: Atheneum)
-
By 1848 it is estimated that more than a tenth of the Arab population had been killed and the economy was in ruins. Raphael Danziger, Abd al-Qadir and the Algerians: Resistance to the French and Internal Consolidation (New York: Holmes & Meier, 1977), xi. For subsequent judgments that only such destructive measures could have brought success, given the resistance encountered in North Africa, see Jean Gottman, "Bugeaud, Galliéni, Lyautey: The Development of French Colonial Warfare," in Makers of Modern Strategy: Military Thought from Machiavelli to Hitler, ed. E. M. Earle, G. A. Craig, and F. Gilbert (New York: Atheneum, 1967). 236-38; Jeremy Black, Western Warfare 1775-1882 (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 2001), 86-87.
-
(1967)
Makers of Modern Strategy: Military Thought from Machiavelli to Hitler
, pp. 236-238
-
-
Gottman, J.1
-
16
-
-
0038420629
-
-
Indianapolis: Indiana University Press
-
By 1848 it is estimated that more than a tenth of the Arab population had been killed and the economy was in ruins. Raphael Danziger, Abd al-Qadir and the Algerians: Resistance to the French and Internal Consolidation (New York: Holmes & Meier, 1977), xi. For subsequent judgments that only such destructive measures could have brought success, given the resistance encountered in North Africa, see Jean Gottman, "Bugeaud, Galliéni, Lyautey: The Development of French Colonial Warfare," in Makers of Modern Strategy: Military Thought from Machiavelli to Hitler, ed. E. M. Earle, G. A. Craig, and F. Gilbert (New York: Atheneum, 1967). 236-38; Jeremy Black, Western Warfare 1775-1882 (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 2001), 86-87.
-
(2001)
Western Warfare 1775-1882
, pp. 86-87
-
-
Black, J.1
-
18
-
-
0038081970
-
-
Paris: Fayard
-
General Bugeaud called the military policies alleged to be necessary in Algeria a different kind of legality, "brutal but logical." Quoted in Jean-Pierre Bois, Bugeaud (Paris: Fayard, 1999), 379. Indeed, observers in both France and Algeria recognized that French methods exceeded "the limits of common morality." See Charles-Henri Favrod, Le FLN et l'Algérie (Paris: Plon, 1962), 30-31.
-
(1999)
Bugeaud
, pp. 379
-
-
Bois, J.-P.1
-
19
-
-
0038758650
-
-
Paris: Plon
-
General Bugeaud called the military policies alleged to be necessary in Algeria a different kind of legality, "brutal but logical." Quoted in Jean-Pierre Bois, Bugeaud (Paris: Fayard, 1999), 379. Indeed, observers in both France and Algeria recognized that French methods exceeded "the limits of common morality." See Charles-Henri Favrod, Le FLN et l'Algérie (Paris: Plon, 1962), 30-31.
-
(1962)
Le FLN et L'Algérie
, pp. 30-31
-
-
Favrod, C.-H.1
-
20
-
-
84905090387
-
-
Bois, Bugeaud, 455-56. Saint-Arnaud later killed hundreds of members of the Sbéah tribe in a similar way: "I hermetically sealed all the exits and I made a vast cemetery." Saint-Arnaud to A. M. Leroy de Saint-Arnaud, August 15, 1845, Lettres du Maréchal de Saint-Arnaud 1832-1854 (Paris: Michel Lévy Frères, 1864), 2:26.
-
Bugeaud
, pp. 455-456
-
-
Bois1
-
21
-
-
0038758665
-
-
Paris: Michel Lévy Frères
-
Bois, Bugeaud, 455-56. Saint-Arnaud later killed hundreds of members of the Sbéah tribe in a similar way: "I hermetically sealed all the exits and I made a vast cemetery." Saint-Arnaud to A. M. Leroy de Saint-Arnaud, August 15, 1845, Lettres du Maréchal de Saint-Arnaud 1832-1854 (Paris: Michel Lévy Frères, 1864), 2:26.
-
(1864)
Lettres du Maréchal de Saint-Arnaud 1832-1854
, vol.2
, pp. 26
-
-
-
22
-
-
0038758649
-
-
Paris: Librairie militaire de Gaultier-Laguionie
-
Farriadis Fleurus Duvivier, Solution de la question de l'Algérie (Paris: Librairie militaire de Gaultier-Laguionie, 1841), 285.
-
(1841)
Solution de la Question de L'Algérie
, pp. 285
-
-
Duvivier, F.F.1
-
23
-
-
0004172672
-
-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
-
Jules Cambon, Governor General in Algeria, reporting to the French Senate in 1894. Quoted in William B. Quandt, Revolution and Political Leadership: Algeria, 1954-1968 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1969), 5.
-
(1969)
Revolution and Political Leadership: Algeria, 1954-1968
, pp. 5
-
-
Quandt, W.B.1
-
24
-
-
0004234953
-
-
Paris: Gallimard
-
In a recent study of the use of torture by the French army during the 1954 to 1962 Algerian war, Raphaëlle Branche points out disturbing parallels between this conflict and the original conquest. In both periods, "it is less law that guides war than war that dictates to the law." La torture et l'armée pendant la guerre d'Algérie, 1954-62 (Paris: Gallimard, 2001), 22.
-
(2001)
La Torture et L'Armée Pendant la Guerre D'Algérie, 1954-62
, pp. 22
-
-
-
26
-
-
0038081983
-
-
note
-
Possibly a first sketch for a journal article that was never completed, this essay remained unpublished until 1962.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
0038758682
-
-
Though Tocqueville was writing for the committee as a whole, these reports largely restate the opinions of his 1841 essay and are included in his collected works. Richter argues that the "edifying tone" of the later reports was adopted for public consumption. "Tocqueville on Algeria," 365. Pitts adds that Tocqueville might also have allowed his moral concerns greater play once French domination was secure. Writings, xxvi.
-
Tocqueville on Algeria
, pp. 365
-
-
-
28
-
-
79957425059
-
-
Though Tocqueville was writing for the committee as a whole, these reports largely restate the opinions of his 1841 essay and are included in his collected works. Richter argues that the "edifying tone" of the later reports was adopted for public consumption. "Tocqueville on Algeria," 365. Pitts adds that Tocqueville might also have allowed his moral concerns greater play once French domination was secure. Writings, xxvi.
-
Writings
-
-
-
29
-
-
0038420631
-
-
London: Peter Halban
-
Tocqueville: A Biography (1805-59), trans. Lydia Davis with Robert Hemenway (London: Peter Halban, 1988), 333. While Jardin's account of Tocqueville on Algeria is important, he dismisses any moral difficulty by seeing Tocqueville rather unproblematically as a defender of French interests "faithful to the traditions of his ancestors Malesherbes and Vauban" (p. 342).
-
(1988)
Tocqueville: A Biography (1805-59)
, pp. 333
-
-
Davis, L.1
Hemenway, R.2
-
30
-
-
0038758662
-
-
trans. George Lawrence (New York: Harper and Row) hereafter cited as DAI or DAII
-
Democracy in America, ed. Max Lerner and J.-P. Mayer, trans. George Lawrence (New York: Harper and Row, 1966), II: 617 (hereafter cited as DAI or DAII).
-
(1966)
Democracy in America
, vol.2
, pp. 617
-
-
Lerner, M.1
Mayer, J.-P.2
-
31
-
-
0038420639
-
-
20. DAI, 339, n. 29.
-
DAI
, vol.29
, pp. 339
-
-
-
32
-
-
0038758660
-
Tocqueville as historian
-
New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press
-
Unpublished draft for the 1840 "Preface" to Democracy in America, quoted in James T. Schleifer, "Tocqueville as Historian," in Reconsidering Tocqueville's "Democracy in America," ed. Abraham Eisenstadt (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1988), 151. See also a similar passage in his unpublished notes on the revolution, OC, 2:2, 346-47.
-
(1988)
Reconsidering Tocqueville's "Democracy in America"
, pp. 151
-
-
Eisenstadt, A.1
-
33
-
-
0037745281
-
-
Unpublished draft for the 1840 "Preface" to Democracy in America, quoted in James T. Schleifer, "Tocqueville as Historian," in Reconsidering Tocqueville's "Democracy in America," ed. Abraham Eisenstadt (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1988), 151. See also a similar passage in his unpublished notes on the revolution, OC, 2:2, 346-47.
-
OC
, vol.2
, Issue.2
, pp. 346-347
-
-
-
34
-
-
0038758664
-
-
trans. George Lawrence, Garden City, NY: Anchor
-
Recollections, trans. George Lawrence, ed. J. P. Mayer and A. P. Kerr (Garden City, NY: Anchor, 1971), 104.
-
(1971)
Recollections
, pp. 104
-
-
Mayer, J.P.1
Kerr, A.P.2
-
35
-
-
0038081984
-
-
DAI, 193.
-
DAI
, pp. 193
-
-
-
36
-
-
0038759386
-
-
DAI, 250.
-
DAI
, pp. 250
-
-
-
37
-
-
0038081978
-
État social et politique de la France
-
"État social et politique de la France," OC, 2:1, 62.
-
OC
, vol.2
, Issue.1
, pp. 62
-
-
-
38
-
-
0038081979
-
-
Ibid., 62-63. Pitts reads too much into this passage, interpreting it as a "commitment in principle to the ability of all peoples to rule themselves" or as a "theoretical denunciation of imperialism." "Empire and Democracy," 314. Cf. a similar ambiguous contrast between aristocratic and modern liberty in "Sur la morale," OC. 16, 223-24.
-
OC
, pp. 62-63
-
-
-
39
-
-
0037744518
-
-
Ibid., 62-63. Pitts reads too much into this passage, interpreting it as a "commitment in principle to the ability of all peoples to rule themselves" or as a "theoretical denunciation of imperialism." "Empire and Democracy," 314. Cf. a similar ambiguous contrast between aristocratic and modern liberty in "Sur la morale," OC. 16, 223-24.
-
Empire and Democracy
, pp. 314
-
-
-
40
-
-
0037744519
-
Sur la morale
-
Ibid., 62-63. Pitts reads too much into this passage, interpreting it as a "commitment in principle to the ability of all peoples to rule themselves" or as a "theoretical denunciation of imperialism." "Empire and Democracy," 314. Cf. a similar ambiguous contrast between aristocratic and modern liberty in "Sur la morale," OC. 16, 223-24.
-
OC
, vol.16
, pp. 223-224
-
-
-
41
-
-
0038081978
-
État social et politique de la France
-
"État social et politique de la France," OC. 2:1, 42.
-
OC
, vol.2
, Issue.1
, pp. 42
-
-
-
42
-
-
0038421443
-
-
Unpublished letter from Tocqueville to Freslon, September 20, 1856, quoted in Jardin, Tocqueville, 514.
-
Tocqueville
, pp. 514
-
-
Jardin1
-
43
-
-
0004282536
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Jon Elster, Political Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1993), 101.
-
(1993)
Political Psychology
, pp. 101
-
-
Elster, J.1
-
44
-
-
0038420649
-
-
DAII, 695.
-
DAII
, pp. 695
-
-
-
46
-
-
0038758680
-
-
OC, 3:1, 443-553.
-
OC
, vol.3
, Issue.1
, pp. 443-553
-
-
-
47
-
-
0038081988
-
-
OC, 3:1, 505.
-
OC
, vol.3
, Issue.1
, pp. 505
-
-
-
49
-
-
0038081991
-
-
60
-
"Essay," 60. Tocqueville clearly fears English domination of the strategically important Mediterranean.
-
Essay
-
-
-
50
-
-
0038081987
-
De la situation intérieure de l'Irlande
-
October 2
-
The closest he comes to such a claim is in his analysis of the Irish situation, where the subjugation of a European Catholic people by a Protestant nobility engaged his strongest sympathies. See "De la situation Intérieure de l'Irlande," Le Commerce, October 2, 1844, OC, 3:2, 472-77, and "L'Irlande et l'Angleterre," Le Commerce, October 20, 1844, Ibid., 478-82. Cf. also "Voyage d'Irlande," OC, 5:2, 93-169. But even here he does not directly assert that the Irish have a right to self-determination, or that the English had no right to conquer Ireland. Rather he points to the devastation that may happen when there is no community of interest between ruler and ruled, and when a social class is permitted to exploit without any effective restraints.
-
(1844)
Le Commerce
-
-
-
51
-
-
0038420661
-
-
The closest he comes to such a claim is in his analysis of the Irish situation, where the subjugation of a European Catholic people by a Protestant nobility engaged his strongest sympathies. See "De la situation Intérieure de l'Irlande," Le Commerce, October 2, 1844, OC, 3:2, 472-77, and "L'Irlande et l'Angleterre," Le Commerce, October 20, 1844, Ibid., 478-82. Cf. also "Voyage d'Irlande," OC, 5:2, 93-169. But even here he does not directly assert that the Irish have a right to self-determination, or that the English had no right to conquer Ireland. Rather he points to the devastation that may happen when there is no community of interest between ruler and ruled, and when a social class is permitted to exploit without any effective restraints.
-
OC
, vol.3
, Issue.2
, pp. 472-477
-
-
-
52
-
-
0037744520
-
L'Irlande et l'angleterre
-
October 20
-
The closest he comes to such a claim is in his analysis of the Irish situation, where the subjugation of a European Catholic people by a Protestant nobility engaged his strongest sympathies. See "De la situation Intérieure de l'Irlande," Le Commerce, October 2, 1844, OC, 3:2, 472-77, and "L'Irlande et l'Angleterre," Le Commerce, October 20, 1844, Ibid., 478-82. Cf. also "Voyage d'Irlande," OC, 5:2, 93-169. But even here he does not directly assert that the Irish have a right to self-determination, or that the English had no right to conquer Ireland. Rather he points to the devastation that may happen when there is no community of interest between ruler and ruled, and when a social class is permitted to exploit without any effective restraints.
-
(1844)
Le Commerce
-
-
-
53
-
-
84972939010
-
-
The closest he comes to such a claim is in his analysis of the Irish situation, where the subjugation of a European Catholic people by a Protestant nobility engaged his strongest sympathies. See "De la situation Intérieure de l'Irlande," Le Commerce, October 2, 1844, OC, 3:2, 472-77, and "L'Irlande et l'Angleterre," Le Commerce, October 20, 1844, Ibid., 478-82. Cf. also "Voyage d'Irlande," OC, 5:2, 93-169. But even here he does not directly assert that the Irish have a right to self-determination, or that the English had no right to conquer Ireland. Rather he points to the devastation that may happen when there is no community of interest between ruler and ruled, and when a social class is permitted to exploit without any effective restraints.
-
Le Commerce
, pp. 478-482
-
-
-
54
-
-
0038759387
-
Voyage d'Irlande
-
The closest he comes to such a claim is in his analysis of the Irish situation, where the subjugation of a European Catholic people by a Protestant nobility engaged his strongest sympathies. See "De la situation Intérieure de l'Irlande," Le Commerce, October 2, 1844, OC, 3:2, 472-77, and "L'Irlande et l'Angleterre," Le Commerce, October 20, 1844, Ibid., 478-82. Cf. also "Voyage d'Irlande," OC, 5:2, 93-169. But even here he does not directly assert that the Irish have a right to self-determination, or that the English had no right to conquer Ireland. Rather he points to the devastation that may happen when there is no community of interest between ruler and ruled, and when a social class is permitted to exploit without any effective restraints.
-
OC
, vol.5
, Issue.2
, pp. 93-169
-
-
-
55
-
-
0038081988
-
-
OC, 3:1, 505. In the 1835 Democracy Tocqueville expresses similar disdain for the Anglo-Americans' self-justifications and manipulations of the language of justice in their official reports on Indian affairs. DAI, 339, n. 29.
-
OC
, vol.3
, Issue.1
, pp. 505
-
-
-
56
-
-
0038420639
-
-
OC, 3:1, 505. In the 1835 Democracy Tocqueville expresses similar disdain for the Anglo-Americans' self-justifications and manipulations of the language of justice in their official reports on Indian affairs. DAI, 339, n. 29.
-
DAI
, vol.29
, pp. 339
-
-
-
57
-
-
0038420657
-
-
Part of what interested Tocqueville about India was the "feeling of greatness and power that [British dominance in India] gives a whole people." OC, 3:1, 478. Seymour Drescher has shown how Tocqueville's growing fears about the entropy of French political culture under the July Monarchy preoccupied him during the composition of the 1840 Democracy. See "More than America: Comparison and Synthesis in Democracy in America," in Reconsidering Democracy, ed. Eisenstadt, 77-93.
-
OC
, vol.3
, Issue.1
, pp. 478
-
-
-
58
-
-
0038420662
-
More than America: Comparison and synthesis in democracy in America
-
Part of what interested Tocqueville about India was the "feeling of greatness and power that [British dominance in India] gives a whole people." OC, 3:1, 478. Seymour Drescher has shown how Tocqueville's growing fears about the entropy of French political culture under the July Monarchy preoccupied him during the composition of the 1840 Democracy. See "More than America: Comparison and Synthesis in Democracy in America," in Reconsidering Democracy, ed. Eisenstadt, 77-93.
-
Reconsidering Democracy
, pp. 77-93
-
-
Eisenstadt1
-
60
-
-
0038758682
-
-
On the empirical weakness and self-delusion of arguments connecting external aggression and internal renewal, see Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," 385, and Pitts, Writings, xxxiv.
-
Tocqueville on Algeria
, pp. 385
-
-
Richter1
-
61
-
-
0038758669
-
-
On the empirical weakness and self-delusion of arguments connecting external aggression and internal renewal, see Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," 385, and Pitts, Writings, xxxiv.
-
Writings
-
-
Pitts1
-
67
-
-
84898535959
-
-
"Second Letter," 24. In Democracy in America, Tocqueville himself recognizes the flaw in this analogy. "[W]then the side that has the physical force has intellectual superiority too, it is rare for the conquered to become civilized; they either withdraw or are destroyed." DAI, 331.
-
Second Letter
, pp. 24
-
-
-
68
-
-
0038421440
-
-
"Second Letter," 24. In Democracy in America, Tocqueville himself recognizes the flaw in this analogy. "[W]then the side that has the physical force has intellectual superiority too, it is rare for the conquered to become civilized; they either withdraw or are destroyed." DAI, 331.
-
DAI
, pp. 331
-
-
-
69
-
-
0038758605
-
-
"Essay," 111.
-
Essay
, pp. 111
-
-
-
70
-
-
0038420663
-
-
"First Report," 161-62
-
See "First Report," 161-62, for his final statement on this matter: "It is not a matter of creating a new people, with its own laws, its customs, its interests, and sooner or later its separate nationality, but of implanting in Africa a population that resembles us in everything." In both reports on Algeria the primary question is the establishment and internal administration of a European society. Relations with the indigenous inhabitants are secondary. See Tocqueville to Beaumont, October 28, 1846, OC, 8:1, 592.
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
0038421445
-
-
See "First Report," 161-62, for his final statement on this matter: "It is not a matter of creating a new people, with its own laws, its customs, its interests, and sooner or later its separate nationality, but of implanting in Africa a population that resembles us in everything." In both reports on Algeria the primary question is the establishment and internal administration of a European society. Relations with the indigenous inhabitants are secondary. See Tocqueville to Beaumont, October 28, 1846, OC, 8:1, 592.
-
OC
, vol.8
, Issue.1
, pp. 592
-
-
-
73
-
-
0038420591
-
-
"Essay," 59.
-
Essay
, pp. 59
-
-
-
74
-
-
0038420640
-
-
"Essay," 70. Tocqueville's belief that France could not abandon Algeria without dishonor never wavered; see his claim in the "First Report," 167-68: "Our preponderance in Europe, the order of our finances, the lives of part of our citizenry, and our national honor are engaged here in the most compelling manner."
-
Essay
, pp. 70
-
-
-
76
-
-
0038758646
-
-
"Essay," 123, 127. Cf. the social economist Eugène Buret, who argued that if France abandoned the conquest she would - like Spain earlier - leave only "humiliating traces of her own powerlessness" in Africa. Question d'Afrique (Paris: Ledoyen, 1842), 35.
-
Essay
, pp. 123
-
-
-
77
-
-
0038081957
-
"Humiliating traces of her own powerlessness" in Africa
-
Paris: Ledoyen
-
"Essay," 123, 127. Cf. the social economist Eugène Buret, who argued that if France abandoned the conquest she would - like Spain earlier - leave only "humiliating traces of her own powerlessness" in Africa. Question d'Afrique (Paris: Ledoyen, 1842), 35.
-
(1842)
Question d'Afrique
, pp. 35
-
-
Buret, E.1
-
78
-
-
84905090387
-
-
Quoted in Bois, Bugeaud, 320-21. Buret noted that French public opinion, by unreservedly supporting the conquest, had placed the retention of Algeria "under the protection of the national honor." Question d'Afrique, 6.
-
Bugeaud
, pp. 320-321
-
-
Bois1
-
79
-
-
0038082726
-
Under the protection of the national honor
-
Quoted in Bois, Bugeaud, 320-21. Buret noted that French public opinion, by unreservedly supporting the conquest, had placed the retention of Algeria "under the protection of the national honor." Question d'Afrique, 6.
-
Question d'Afrique
, pp. 6
-
-
Buret1
-
80
-
-
0038758666
-
-
Duvivier, Solution de la question, 285-86. The anti-imperialist critic Desjobert drew opposite conclusions. He believed there was no good argument for the original conquest, and that the costs of colonization were morally unacceptable. France, then, should limit herself to occupying a few coastal ports. La question d'Alger, 306-36. In effect, Desjobert argued that Algeria presented a case where considerations of jus ad bellum and jus in bello come together to make a war indefensible. See Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic Books, 1977), 195-96.
-
Solution de la Question
, pp. 285-286
-
-
Duvivier1
-
81
-
-
0004083066
-
-
New York: Basic Books
-
Duvivier, Solution de la question, 285-86. The anti-imperialist critic Desjobert drew opposite conclusions. He believed there was no good argument for the original conquest, and that the costs of colonization were morally unacceptable. France, then, should limit herself to occupying a few coastal ports. La question d'Alger, 306-36. In effect, Desjobert argued that Algeria presented a case where considerations of jus ad bellum and jus in bello come together to make a war indefensible. See Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic Books, 1977), 195-96.
-
(1977)
Just and Unjust Wars
, pp. 195-196
-
-
Walzer, M.1
-
84
-
-
0038420653
-
-
"Notes," 37.
-
Notes
, pp. 37
-
-
-
85
-
-
0038420641
-
-
Cf. "Notes," 53-55, and "Essay," 83-84.
-
Notes
, pp. 53-55
-
-
-
86
-
-
0038420642
-
-
Cf. "Notes," 53-55, and "Essay," 83-84.
-
Essay
, pp. 83-84
-
-
-
87
-
-
0037744511
-
-
"Essay," 83.
-
Essay
, pp. 83
-
-
-
88
-
-
0038758670
-
-
I b i d.
-
Essay
-
-
-
89
-
-
0038758661
-
-
"Notes," 41, 53.
-
Notes
, pp. 41
-
-
-
90
-
-
0037744469
-
-
"Essay," 50. Apparently the key dispute was not so much over the translation of "sovereignty" as over discrepancies in the Arabic and French versions of the provision that defined the eastern boundary of French territory. See Danziger, Abd al-Qadir, 143-44.
-
Essay
, pp. 50
-
-
-
91
-
-
0038759385
-
-
"Essay," 50. Apparently the key dispute was not so much over the translation of "sovereignty" as over discrepancies in the Arabic and French versions of the provision that defined the eastern boundary of French territory. See Danziger, Abd al-Qadir, 143-44.
-
Abd al-Qadir
, pp. 143-144
-
-
Danziger1
-
92
-
-
0345249386
-
-
"First Report," 140. Cf. an incident Tocqueville relates in the Souvenirs. In 1849, relying on false interpretations of preceding treaties, Austria and Russia demanded that Turkey turn over Polish rebels who had appealed to the Turkish sultan for protection. The Turks refused, invoking their honor, Islamic law, and the law of nations. Tocqueville ironically notes that they "modestly suggested that what was right on the left bank of the Danube should be so on the right bank too." Recollections, 317. Pitts sees in this discussion evidence of Tocqueville's theoretical support for the universal application of natural law principles. "Empire and Democracy," 314. In context, however, what emerges is less a claim that universal justice should bind everyone equally than a claim that "civilized" powers shame themselves when they break self-imposed rules.
-
First Report
, pp. 140
-
-
-
93
-
-
0037744522
-
-
note
-
"First Report," 140. Cf. an incident Tocqueville relates in the Souvenirs. In 1849, relying on false interpretations of preceding treaties, Austria and Russia demanded that Turkey turn over Polish rebels who had appealed to the Turkish sultan for protection. The Turks refused, invoking their honor, Islamic law, and the law of nations. Tocqueville ironically notes that they "modestly suggested that what was right on the left bank of the Danube should be so on the right bank too." Recollections, 317. Pitts sees in this discussion evidence of Tocqueville's theoretical support for the universal application of natural law principles. "Empire and Democracy," 314. In context, however, what emerges is less a claim that universal justice should bind everyone equally than a claim that "civilized" powers shame themselves when they break self-imposed rules.
-
-
-
-
94
-
-
0038081990
-
-
Lorcin, Imperial identities, 38-39. Desjobert, quoting Tocqueville from Democracy in America, argued that French policies would lead to extermination, even if no one explicitly intended this result, La question d'Alger. 63-65. It was this issue that most troubled Tocqueville's friend Corcelle about French policies in Algeria. See Tocqueville to Corcelle, December 1, 1846, OC, 15:1.
-
Imperial Identities
, pp. 38-39
-
-
Lorcin1
-
95
-
-
0038420655
-
-
Desjobert, quoting Tocqueville from Democracy in America, argued that French policies would lead to extermination, even if no one explicitly intended this result, La question d'Alger. 63-65. It was this issue that most troubled Tocqueville's friend Corcelle about French policies in Algeria. See Tocqueville to Corcelle, December 1, 1846, OC, 15:1.
-
Lorcin, Imperial identities, 38-39. Desjobert, quoting Tocqueville from Democracy in America, argued that French policies would lead to extermination, even if no one explicitly intended this result, La question d'Alger. 63-65. It was this issue that most troubled Tocqueville's friend Corcelle about French policies in Algeria. See Tocqueville to Corcelle, December 1, 1846, OC, 15:1.
-
-
-
-
96
-
-
0038421437
-
-
"Intervention" (1846), 118.
-
(1846)
Intervention
, pp. 118
-
-
-
97
-
-
0038420638
-
-
"Essay," 70.
-
Essay
, pp. 70
-
-
-
98
-
-
0038081973
-
-
"Essay," 78. Cf. his observation that the French public was willing to tolerate suspension of the rule of law in Algeria because "deep down [it] has a certain taste for violent and summary proceedings when it does not suffer itself." Ibid., 110.
-
Essay
, pp. 78
-
-
-
99
-
-
0038421435
-
-
"Essay," 78. Cf. his observation that the French public was willing to tolerate suspension of the rule of law in Algeria because "deep down [it] has a certain taste for violent and summary proceedings when it does not suffer itself." Ibid., 110.
-
Ibid.
, pp. 110
-
-
-
100
-
-
0038758681
-
A consequence of the general principle of democracy, applied to the most urgent needs of the nation (patrie)
-
Paris: Union Générale d'Editions
-
Robespierre defined terror as "a consequence of the general principle of democracy, applied to the most urgent needs of the nation (patrie)." Discours et Rapports à la Convention (Paris: Union Générale d'Editions, 1965), 222. Tocqueville's belief that an aggressive patriotic foreign policy was in some measure a prophylactic against the ascendancy of domestic revolutionaries who, he believed, also endangered property and the rule of law undoubtedly contributed to his ability to repress the dangers of lawlessness in Algeria. See his notes for his speech on the Eastern question (November 30, 1840), OC, 3:2, 304, and the speech itself, OC, 3:2, 299-301.
-
(1965)
Discours et Rapports à la Convention
, pp. 222
-
-
Robespierre1
-
101
-
-
0038758675
-
-
note
-
In 1846 Tocqueville wrote to Corcelle from Algiers of the wretchedness of the Arab tribes in a passage that in some ways recalls his descriptions in Democracy in America of the starving Choctaws. Yet the emotional register is different. Although Tocqueville takes no joy from Arab starvation, and distances himself from those army officers who hate Arabs and treat them like beasts, it is clear that his dominant reaction to this suffering is relief. Starvation interests him primarily as evidence that the French have prevailed and the war is over. December 1, 1846, OC, 15:1, 224-25.
-
-
-
-
102
-
-
0038758655
-
-
"Notes," 57.
-
Notes
, pp. 57
-
-
-
103
-
-
0003967815
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 73-95.
-
(1989)
Contingency, Irony and Solidarity
, pp. 73-95
-
-
Rorty, R.1
-
105
-
-
0038420654
-
-
"Essay," 70.
-
Essay
, pp. 70
-
-
-
106
-
-
0345249386
-
-
"First Report," 141. Cf. Tocqueville to his father, May 23, 1841, OC, 14, 218-19.
-
First Report
, pp. 141
-
-
-
107
-
-
0038082727
-
-
Cf. Tocqueville to his father, May 23, 1841, OC, 14, 218-19.
-
"First Report," 141. Cf. Tocqueville to his father, May 23, 1841, OC, 14, 218-19.
-
-
-
-
108
-
-
0004475853
-
Europe and the other in eighteenth-century thought
-
(Stuttgart: Verlag J. B. Metzler). See also endnote 63 above
-
For an analysis of these uses of ironic comparison with non-European societies in the eighteenth century, see Melvin Richter, "Europe and the Other in Eighteenth-Century Thought," Politisches Denken Jahrbuch 1997 (Stuttgart: Verlag J. B. Metzler), 25-47. See also endnote 63 above.
-
(1997)
Politisches Denken Jahrbuch 1997
, pp. 25-47
-
-
Richter, M.1
-
109
-
-
0038081961
-
-
DAI, 339.
-
DAI
, pp. 339
-
-
-
110
-
-
0038758682
-
-
See, for example, Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," 363, 372, and Wolin, Tocqueville between Two Worlds, 271. Pitts, on the other hand, suggests perceptively that Tocqueville's interest in American expansion into Amerindian territory and his refusal to condemn it (even as he sympathized with its victims) are analogous to his interest in British imperialism in India. Writings, xiv-vi.
-
Tocqueville on Algeria
, pp. 363
-
-
Richter1
-
111
-
-
0003974014
-
-
Pitts, on the other hand, suggests perceptively that Tocqueville's interest in American expansion into Amerindian territory and his refusal to condemn it (even as he sympathized with its victims) are analogous to his interest in British imperialism in India. Writings, xiv-vi.
-
See, for example, Richter, "Tocqueville on Algeria," 363, 372, and Wolin, Tocqueville between Two Worlds, 271. Pitts, on the other hand, suggests perceptively that Tocqueville's interest in American expansion into Amerindian territory and his refusal to condemn it (even as he sympathized with its victims) are analogous to his interest in British imperialism in India. Writings, xiv-vi.
-
Tocqueville between Two Worlds
, pp. 271
-
-
Wolin1
-
112
-
-
0038420601
-
-
Let us not, in the middle of the nineteenth century, begin the history of the conquest of America over again. Let us not imitate the bloody examples that the opinion of the human race has stigmatized
-
See, for example, his invocation of the Spanish example in the "First Report," 146: "Let us not, in the middle of the nineteenth century, begin the history of the conquest of America over again. Let us not imitate the bloody examples that the opinion of the human race has stigmatized."
-
First Report
, pp. 146
-
-
-
113
-
-
0345249386
-
-
"First Report," 130; see also Tocqueville to Henry Reeve, April 12, 1840, OC, 6:1, 58.
-
First Report
, pp. 130
-
-
-
114
-
-
0038758613
-
-
Tocqueville to Henry Reeve, April 12, 1840, OC, 6:1, 58.
-
"First Report," 130; see also Tocqueville to Henry Reeve, April 12, 1840, OC, 6:1, 58.
-
-
-
-
115
-
-
0038081905
-
-
"Essay," 85, 87.
-
Essay
, pp. 85
-
-
-
116
-
-
0038758601
-
-
"Essay," 111. In addressing Corcelle's fears that extermination will be the result of French policies, Tocqueville says that to "wish for" the disappearance of the Arabs is cruel, absurd, and impractical. But he adds, "But what should be done so that the two races enter into contact with one another? I confess with chagrin that here my mind is troubled and hesitates." Tocqueville to Corcelle, December 1, 1846, OC, 15:1, 224.
-
Essay
, pp. 111
-
-
-
118
-
-
0038758610
-
-
Tocqueville to Kergolay, May 23, 1841, OC, 13:2, 84.
-
Tocqueville to Kergolay, May 23, 1841, OC, 13:2, 84.
-
-
-
-
119
-
-
0345249386
-
-
"First Report," 135. Cf. "Essay," 68, where Tocqueville speaks of warfare as a controlled means to "dishearten and exhaust."
-
First Report
, pp. 135
-
-
-
120
-
-
0038081910
-
-
where Tocqueville speaks of warfare as a controlled means to "dishearten and exhaust.
-
"First Report," 135. Cf. "Essay," 68, where Tocqueville speaks of warfare as a controlled means to "dishearten and exhaust."
-
Essay
, pp. 68
-
-
-
121
-
-
0038420587
-
-
"Essay." 75-80.
-
Essay
, pp. 75-80
-
-
-
122
-
-
0038081915
-
-
"Essay," 88.
-
Essay
, pp. 88
-
-
-
125
-
-
84903117172
-
The prince
-
trans. Luigi Ricci, rev. E. R. P. Vincent, (New York: Modern Library)
-
Machiavelli, The Prince, trans. Luigi Ricci, rev. E. R. P. Vincent, in The Prince and the Discourses (New York: Modern Library, 1950), 34. Sheldon Wolin has an interesting discussion of the moral ambiguities of this "economy of violence" in Politics and Vision (Boston: Little, Brown. 1960), 220-24.
-
(1950)
The Prince and the Discourses
, pp. 34
-
-
Machiavelli1
-
126
-
-
84971712706
-
Economy of violence
-
Boston: Little, Brown
-
Machiavelli, The Prince, trans. Luigi Ricci, rev. E. R. P. Vincent, in The Prince and the Discourses (New York: Modern Library, 1950), 34. Sheldon Wolin has an interesting discussion of the moral ambiguities of this "economy of violence" in Politics and Vision (Boston: Little, Brown. 1960), 220-24.
-
(1960)
Politics and Vision
, pp. 220-224
-
-
-
128
-
-
0037744453
-
-
"Notes," 38-39; "Essay," 86-88.
-
Notes
, pp. 38-39
-
-
-
129
-
-
0038758606
-
-
"Notes," 38-39; "Essay," 86-88.
-
Essay
, pp. 86-88
-
-
-
130
-
-
84979385914
-
"Processes of moral exclusion" in susan opitow, "moral exclusion and injustice: An introduction."
-
See the table summarizing "Processes of Moral Exclusion" in Susan Opitow, "Moral Exclusion and Injustice: An Introduction." Journal of Social Issues 46, no. 1 (1990): 10-11.
-
(1990)
Journal of Social Issues
, vol.46
, Issue.1
, pp. 10-11
-
-
-
131
-
-
0038420583
-
-
"Essay," 67.
-
Essay
, pp. 67
-
-
-
133
-
-
0038081914
-
-
"Essay," 70.
-
Essay
, pp. 70
-
-
-
134
-
-
0038420586
-
-
"Essay," 70.
-
Essay
, pp. 70
-
-
-
135
-
-
0038758615
-
-
"Essay," 71. Cf. Ibid.: "I think that all means of desolating these tribes must be employed. I make an exception only of those condemned by humanity and by the law of nations." It is unclear what Tocqueville means substantively here, since he never explicitly discusses what he thinks the law of nations condemns, but he probably means to draw a line between necessary and unnecessary violence.
-
Essay
, pp. 71
-
-
-
136
-
-
0037744455
-
-
"Essay," 71. Cf. Ibid.: "I think that all means of desolating these tribes must be employed. I make an exception only of those condemned by humanity and by the law of nations." It is unclear what Tocqueville means substantively here, since he never explicitly discusses what he thinks the law of nations condemns, but he probably means to draw a line between necessary and unnecessary violence.
-
Essay
-
-
-
137
-
-
79956148170
-
-
"Intervention," 118-19.
-
Intervention
, pp. 118-119
-
-
-
138
-
-
0345249386
-
-
"First Report," 139-40.
-
First Report
, pp. 139-140
-
-
-
139
-
-
0037744474
-
-
Tocqueville to Corcelle, October 11, 1846, OC, 15:1, 219
-
Tocqueville to Corcelle, October 11, 1846, OC, 15:1, 219; "First Report." 141.
-
-
-
-
140
-
-
0345249386
-
-
Tocqueville to Corcelle, October 11, 1846, OC, 15:1, 219; "First Report." 141.
-
First Report
, pp. 141
-
-
-
141
-
-
0345249386
-
-
He may or may not mean to include such incidents in scattered vague references to "violent and tyrannical" behavior. See, for example, "First Report," 137. There is an oblique reference to a resistance leader "vainly having tried to resist our force" that may refer to Saint-Arnaud's smoking of members of the Sbéah tribe in the course of putting down a rebellion led by "Bu Maza" in 1845. Ibid., 129. On this matter see Pitts, Writings, 250, n. 5.
-
First Report
, pp. 137
-
-
-
142
-
-
0038420546
-
-
He may or may not mean to include such incidents in scattered vague references to "violent and tyrannical" behavior. See, for example, "First Report," 137. There is an oblique reference to a resistance leader "vainly having tried to resist our force" that may refer to Saint-Arnaud's smoking of members of the Sbéah tribe in the course of putting down a rebellion led by "Bu Maza" in 1845. Ibid., 129. On this matter see Pitts, Writings, 250, n. 5.
-
Writings
, vol.5
, pp. 250
-
-
Pitts1
-
144
-
-
0003841935
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Albert Hirschman, The Rhetoric of Reaction; Perversity, Futility, Jeopardy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), 153.
-
(1991)
The Rhetoric of Reaction; Perversity, Futility, Jeopardy
, pp. 153
-
-
Hirschman, A.1
-
146
-
-
84884077201
-
In the beginning was the deed
-
ed. Harold Hongju Koh and Ronald C. Slye (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
-
Bernard Williams, "In the Beginning Was the Deed," in Deliberative Democracy and Human Rights, ed. Harold Hongju Koh and Ronald C. Slye (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1999), 54.
-
(1999)
Deliberative Democracy and Human Rights
, pp. 54
-
-
Williams, B.1
-
147
-
-
33749178788
-
Personal rights and public space
-
Harold Hongju Koh and Ronald C. Slye
-
The flagrant violation of the most basic human rights is devoid of philosophical interest. The maintenance of power by the torture and execution of political dissidents or religious minorities, denial of civil rights to women, total censorship, and so forth demand denunciation and practical opposition, not theoretical discussion. "Personal Rights and Public Space," in Deliberative Democracy, ed. Harold Hongju Koh and Ronald C. Slye, 34. Or see August Richard Norton: "A detailed excursus into moral philosophy is hardly required to convince most members of the human race that the intentional slaughter of innocent people is morally indefensible." "Drawing the Line on Opprobrious Violence," in Ethics and International Affairs: A Reader, ed. Joel H. Rosenthal (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1995), 186. See also Michael Ignatieff's discussion of the necessarily "thin" philosophical grounding of human rights in Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 53-58.
-
Deliberative Democracy
, pp. 34
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
148
-
-
0038420590
-
A detailed excursus into moral philosophy is hardly required to convince most members of the human race that the intentional slaughter of innocent people is morally indefensible. "Drawing the Line on Opprobrious Violence"
-
Joel H. Rosenthal (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press)
-
The flagrant violation of the most basic human rights is devoid of philosophical interest. The maintenance of power by the torture and execution of political dissidents or religious minorities, denial of civil rights to women, total censorship, and so forth demand denunciation and practical opposition, not theoretical discussion. "Personal Rights and Public Space," in Deliberative Democracy, ed. Harold Hongju Koh and Ronald C. Slye, 34. Or see August Richard Norton: "A detailed excursus into moral philosophy is hardly required to convince most members of the human race that the intentional slaughter of innocent people is morally indefensible." "Drawing the Line on Opprobrious Violence," in Ethics and International Affairs: A Reader, ed. Joel H. Rosenthal (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1995), 186. See also Michael Ignatieff's discussion of the necessarily "thin" philosophical grounding of human rights in Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 53-58.
-
(1995)
Ethics and International Affairs: A Reader
, pp. 186
-
-
Norton, A.R.1
-
149
-
-
84884042444
-
-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
The flagrant violation of the most basic human rights is devoid of philosophical interest. The maintenance of power by the torture and execution of political dissidents or religious minorities, denial of civil rights to women, total censorship, and so forth demand denunciation and practical opposition, not theoretical discussion. "Personal Rights and Public Space," in Deliberative Democracy, ed. Harold Hongju Koh and Ronald C. Slye, 34. Or see August Richard Norton: "A detailed excursus into moral philosophy is hardly required to convince most members of the human race that the intentional slaughter of innocent people is morally indefensible." "Drawing the Line on Opprobrious Violence," in Ethics and International Affairs: A Reader, ed. Joel H. Rosenthal (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1995), 186. See also Michael Ignatieff's discussion of the necessarily "thin" philosophical grounding of human rights in Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 53-58.
-
(2001)
Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry
, pp. 53-58
-
-
Ignatieff, M.1
-
150
-
-
0003997207
-
-
New York: Basic Books
-
See the discussion of American policy towards genocide in the conclusion to Samantha Power, A Problem from Hell: America and the Age of Genocide (New York: Basic Books, 2002), 503-16.
-
(2002)
Problem from Hell: America and the Age of Genocide
, pp. 503-516
-
-
-
151
-
-
0037761950
-
Government responses to human rights reports: Claims, denials, and counterclaims
-
See, for example, Stanley Cohen, "Government Responses to Human Rights Reports: Claims, Denials, and Counterclaims," Human Rights Quarterly 18, no. 3 (1996): 517-43, and Albert Bandura, "Selective Activation and Disengagement of Moral Control," Journal of Social Issues 46, no. 1 (1990): 27-46.
-
(1996)
Human Rights Quarterly
, vol.18
, Issue.3
, pp. 517-543
-
-
Cohen, S.1
-
152
-
-
84979419328
-
Selective activation and disengagement of moral control
-
See, for example, Stanley Cohen, "Government Responses to Human Rights Reports: Claims, Denials, and Counterclaims," Human Rights Quarterly 18, no. 3 (1996): 517-43, and Albert Bandura, "Selective Activation and Disengagement of Moral Control," Journal of Social Issues 46, no. 1 (1990): 27-46.
-
(1990)
Journal of Social Issues
, vol.46
, Issue.1
, pp. 27-46
-
-
Bandura, A.1
-
153
-
-
0037783499
-
The Adequacy of the Canon
-
August
-
George Kateb, "The Adequacy of the Canon," Political Theory 30, no. 4 (August 2002): 486.
-
(2002)
Political Theory
, vol.30
, Issue.4
, pp. 486
-
-
Kateb, G.1
|