메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 31, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 355-388

Ideology, democracy and the limits of equilibrium: A Schumpeterian critique

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0035635716     PISSN: 00071234     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S000712340100014X     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (7)

References (174)
  • 2
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass:. Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass:. Harvard University Press, 1971).
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 4
    • 0039021995 scopus 로고
    • Political disequilibrium and scientific inquiry: A comment on William Riker's "implications for the disequilibrium of majority rule for the study of institutions"
    • P. C. Ordeshook and K. A. Shepsle, eds, Boston, Mass.: Kluwer-Nijhoff
    • Peter C. Ordeshook, 'Political Disequilibrium and Scientific Inquiry: A Comment on William Riker's "Implications for the Disequilibrium of Majority Rule for the Study of Institutions"', in P. C. Ordeshook and K. A. Shepsle, eds, Political Equilibrium (Boston, Mass.: Kluwer-Nijhoff, 1982), pp. 25-31, at p. 25.
    • (1982) Political Equilibrium , pp. 25-31
    • Ordeshook, P.C.1
  • 5
    • 53849106290 scopus 로고
    • New York: St Martin's Press
    • Tom Bottomore, Between Marginalism and Marxism: The Economic Sociology of J. A. Schumpeter (New York: St Martin's Press, 1992); John Medearis, 'Schumpeter, the New Deal, and Democracy', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 819-32, at p. 821; Joseph A. Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), pp. 12-21; Yuichi Shionoya, 'The Origin of the Schumpeterian Research Program: A Chapter Omitted from Schumpeter's Theory of Economic Development', Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 146 (1990), 314-27; Richard Swedberg, Joseph A. Schumpeter: His Life and Work (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991).
    • (1992) Between Marginalism and Marxism: The Economic Sociology of J. A. Schumpeter
    • Bottomore, T.1
  • 6
    • 0031286819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, the new deal, and democracy
    • Tom Bottomore, Between Marginalism and Marxism: The Economic Sociology of J. A. Schumpeter (New York: St Martin's Press, 1992); John Medearis, 'Schumpeter, the New Deal, and Democracy', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 819-32, at p. 821; Joseph A. Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), pp. 12-21; Yuichi Shionoya, 'The Origin of the Schumpeterian Research Program: A Chapter Omitted from Schumpeter's Theory of Economic Development', Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 146 (1990), 314-27; Richard Swedberg, Joseph A. Schumpeter: His Life and Work (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991).
    • (1997) American Political Science Review , vol.91 , pp. 819-832
    • Medearis, J.1
  • 7
    • 0004203360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Tom Bottomore, Between Marginalism and Marxism: The Economic Sociology of J. A. Schumpeter (New York: St Martin's Press, 1992); John Medearis, 'Schumpeter, the New Deal, and Democracy', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 819-32, at p. 821; Joseph A. Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), pp. 12-21; Yuichi Shionoya, 'The Origin of the Schumpeterian Research Program: A Chapter Omitted from Schumpeter's Theory of Economic Development', Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 146 (1990), 314-27; Richard Swedberg, Joseph A. Schumpeter: His Life and Work (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991).
    • (1954) History of Economic Analysis , pp. 12-21
    • Schumpeter, J.A.1
  • 8
    • 0001223066 scopus 로고
    • The origin of the Schumpeterian Research Program: A chapter omitted from Schumpeter's theory of economic development
    • Tom Bottomore, Between Marginalism and Marxism: The Economic Sociology of J. A. Schumpeter (New York: St Martin's Press, 1992); John Medearis, 'Schumpeter, the New Deal, and Democracy', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 819-32, at p. 821; Joseph A. Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), pp. 12-21; Yuichi Shionoya, 'The Origin of the Schumpeterian Research Program: A Chapter Omitted from Schumpeter's Theory of Economic Development', Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 146 (1990), 314-27; Richard Swedberg, Joseph A. Schumpeter: His Life and Work (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991).
    • (1990) Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics , vol.146 , pp. 314-327
    • Shionoya, Y.1
  • 9
    • 0003646580 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Polity Press
    • Tom Bottomore, Between Marginalism and Marxism: The Economic Sociology of J. A. Schumpeter (New York: St Martin's Press, 1992); John Medearis, 'Schumpeter, the New Deal, and Democracy', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 819-32, at p. 821; Joseph A. Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), pp. 12-21; Yuichi Shionoya, 'The Origin of the Schumpeterian Research Program: A Chapter Omitted from Schumpeter's Theory of Economic Development', Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 146 (1990), 314-27; Richard Swedberg, Joseph A. Schumpeter: His Life and Work (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991).
    • (1991) Joseph A. Schumpeter: His Life and Work
    • Swedberg, R.1
  • 11
    • 0000510833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional stability
    • Peter Ordeshook, 'Constitutional Stability', Constitutional Political Economy, 3 (1992), 137-75; Adam Przeworski, Democracy and the Market (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); Przeworski, 'Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense', in Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, eds, Democracy's Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 23-55; Barry R. Weingast, 'The Economic Role of Political Institutions: Federalism, Markets, and Economic Development', Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 11 (1995), 1-31; Weingast, 'The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of Law', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 245-63.
    • (1992) Constitutional Political Economy , vol.3 , pp. 137-175
    • Ordeshook, P.1
  • 12
    • 0000510833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Peter Ordeshook, 'Constitutional Stability', Constitutional Political Economy, 3 (1992), 137-75; Adam Przeworski, Democracy and the Market (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); Przeworski, 'Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense', in Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, eds, Democracy's Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 23-55; Barry R. Weingast, 'The Economic Role of Political Institutions: Federalism, Markets, and Economic Development', Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 11 (1995), 1-31; Weingast, 'The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of Law', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 245-63.
    • (1991) Democracy and the Market
    • Przeworski, A.1
  • 13
    • 0000510833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Minimalist conception of democracy: A defense
    • Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Peter Ordeshook, 'Constitutional Stability', Constitutional Political Economy, 3 (1992), 137-75; Adam Przeworski, Democracy and the Market (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); Przeworski, 'Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense', in Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, eds, Democracy's Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 23-55; Barry R. Weingast, 'The Economic Role of Political Institutions: Federalism, Markets, and Economic Development', Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 11 (1995), 1-31; Weingast, 'The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of Law', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 245-63.
    • (1999) Democracy's Value , pp. 23-55
    • Przeworski1
  • 14
    • 0039395559 scopus 로고
    • The economic role of political institutions: Federalism, markets, and economic development
    • Peter Ordeshook, 'Constitutional Stability', Constitutional Political Economy, 3 (1992), 137-75; Adam Przeworski, Democracy and the Market (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); Przeworski, 'Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense', in Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, eds, Democracy's Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 23-55; Barry R. Weingast, 'The Economic Role of Political Institutions: Federalism, Markets, and Economic Development', Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 11 (1995), 1-31; Weingast, 'The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of Law', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 245-63.
    • (1995) Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization , vol.11 , pp. 1-31
    • Weingast, B.R.1
  • 15
    • 0031507203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The political foundations of democracy and the rule of law
    • Peter Ordeshook, 'Constitutional Stability', Constitutional Political Economy, 3 (1992), 137-75; Adam Przeworski, Democracy and the Market (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); Przeworski, 'Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense', in Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, eds, Democracy's Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 23-55; Barry R. Weingast, 'The Economic Role of Political Institutions: Federalism, Markets, and Economic Development', Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 11 (1995), 1-31; Weingast, 'The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of Law', American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 245-63.
    • (1997) American Political Science Review , vol.91 , pp. 245-263
    • Weingast1
  • 16
    • 0002149826 scopus 로고
    • Selfishness and altruism
    • Jane J. Mansbridge, ed., Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Much critique of rational choice theory throws doubt on the idea that the model of a human agent as a rational maximizer is adequate for social science or philosophy. This article does not provide such a critique of rational choice theory. Such criticisms typically focus on the importance of the meaningful and communicative dimensions of conduct, on 'commitment', altruistic behaviour, and norm-or value-governed behaviour. The contributions to this discussion are too numerous to cite. But for some basic statements and the way in which such critiques have been viewed, answered and incorporated by some rational choice theorists, see Jon Elster, 'Selfishness and Altruism', in Jane J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), pp. 44-53; John Ferejohn, 'Rationality and Interpretation: Parliamentary Elections in Early Stuart England', in Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action (New York: Harper Collins, 1991), pp. 279-305; Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984), esp. pp. 75-101; Mansbridge, 'The Rise and Fall of Self-interest in the Explanation of Public Life', in Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest; Amartya K. Sen, 'Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory', in Frank Hahn and Martin Hollis, eds, Philosophy and Economic Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 87-109; Charles Taylor, 'Interpretation and the Sciences of Man', in Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan, eds, Interpretive Social Science: A Reader (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1979), pp. 25-71; Albert S. Yee, 'Thick Rationality and the Missing "Brute Fact": The Limits of Rationalist Incorporations of Norms and Ideas', Journal of Politics, 59 (1997), 1001-39. A different approach, reviewing the track record of rational choice approaches, is taken by Donald P. Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1994).
    • (1990) Beyond Self-interest , pp. 44-53
    • Elster, J.1
  • 17
    • 0000578655 scopus 로고
    • Rationality and interpretation: Parliamentary elections in early Stuart England
    • Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., New York: Harper Collins
    • Much critique of rational choice theory throws doubt on the idea that the model of a human agent as a rational maximizer is adequate for social science or philosophy. This article does not provide such a critique of rational choice theory. Such criticisms typically focus on the importance of the meaningful and communicative dimensions of conduct, on 'commitment', altruistic behaviour, and norm-or value-governed behaviour. The contributions to this discussion are too numerous to cite. But for some basic statements and the way in which such critiques have been viewed, answered and incorporated by some rational choice theorists, see Jon Elster, 'Selfishness and Altruism', in Jane J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), pp. 44-53; John Ferejohn, 'Rationality and Interpretation: Parliamentary Elections in Early Stuart England', in Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action (New York: Harper Collins, 1991), pp. 279-305; Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984), esp. pp. 75-101; Mansbridge, 'The Rise and Fall of Self-interest in the Explanation of Public Life', in Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest; Amartya K. Sen, 'Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory', in Frank Hahn and Martin Hollis, eds, Philosophy and Economic Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 87-109; Charles Taylor, 'Interpretation and the Sciences of Man', in Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan, eds, Interpretive Social Science: A Reader (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1979), pp. 25-71; Albert S. Yee, 'Thick Rationality and the Missing "Brute Fact": The Limits of Rationalist Incorporations of Norms and Ideas', Journal of Politics, 59 (1997), 1001-39. A different approach, reviewing the track record of rational choice approaches, is taken by Donald P. Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1994).
    • (1991) The Economic Approach to Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action , pp. 279-305
    • Ferejohn, J.1
  • 18
    • 0003651494 scopus 로고
    • Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press
    • Much critique of rational choice theory throws doubt on the idea that the model of a human agent as a rational maximizer is adequate for social science or philosophy. This article does not provide such a critique of rational choice theory. Such criticisms typically focus on the importance of the meaningful and communicative dimensions of conduct, on 'commitment', altruistic behaviour, and norm-or value-governed behaviour. The contributions to this discussion are too numerous to cite. But for some basic statements and the way in which such critiques have been viewed, answered and incorporated by some rational choice theorists, see Jon Elster, 'Selfishness and Altruism', in Jane J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), pp. 44-53; John Ferejohn, 'Rationality and Interpretation: Parliamentary Elections in Early Stuart England', in Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action (New York: Harper Collins, 1991), pp. 279-305; Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984), esp. pp. 75-101; Mansbridge, 'The Rise and Fall of Self-interest in the Explanation of Public Life', in Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest; Amartya K. Sen, 'Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory', in Frank Hahn and Martin Hollis, eds, Philosophy and Economic Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 87-109; Charles Taylor, 'Interpretation and the Sciences of Man', in Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan, eds, Interpretive Social Science: A Reader (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1979), pp. 25-71; Albert S. Yee, 'Thick Rationality and the Missing "Brute Fact": The Limits of Rationalist Incorporations of Norms and Ideas', Journal of Politics, 59 (1997), 1001-39. A different approach, reviewing the track record of rational choice approaches, is taken by Donald P. Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1994).
    • (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society , vol.1 , pp. 75-101
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 19
    • 0002650395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The rise and fall of self-interest in the explanation of public life
    • Mansbridge, ed.
    • Much critique of rational choice theory throws doubt on the idea that the model of a human agent as a rational maximizer is adequate for social science or philosophy. This article does not provide such a critique of rational choice theory. Such criticisms typically focus on the importance of the meaningful and communicative dimensions of conduct, on 'commitment', altruistic behaviour, and norm-or value-governed behaviour. The contributions to this discussion are too numerous to cite. But for some basic statements and the way in which such critiques have been viewed, answered and incorporated by some rational choice theorists, see Jon Elster, 'Selfishness and Altruism', in Jane J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), pp. 44-53; John Ferejohn, 'Rationality and Interpretation: Parliamentary Elections in Early Stuart England', in Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action (New York: Harper Collins, 1991), pp. 279-305; Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984), esp. pp. 75-101; Mansbridge, 'The Rise and Fall of Self-interest in the Explanation of Public Life', in Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest; Amartya K. Sen, 'Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory', in Frank Hahn and Martin Hollis, eds, Philosophy and Economic Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 87-109; Charles Taylor, 'Interpretation and the Sciences of Man', in Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan, eds, Interpretive Social Science: A Reader (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1979), pp. 25-71; Albert S. Yee, 'Thick Rationality and the Missing "Brute Fact": The Limits of Rationalist Incorporations of Norms and Ideas', Journal of Politics, 59 (1997), 1001-39. A different approach, reviewing the track record of rational choice approaches, is taken by Donald P. Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1994).
    • Beyond Self-interest
    • Mansbridge1
  • 20
    • 0003255167 scopus 로고
    • Rational fools: A critique of the behavioural foundations of economic theory
    • Frank Hahn and Martin Hollis, eds, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Much critique of rational choice theory throws doubt on the idea that the model of a human agent as a rational maximizer is adequate for social science or philosophy. This article does not provide such a critique of rational choice theory. Such criticisms typically focus on the importance of the meaningful and communicative dimensions of conduct, on 'commitment', altruistic behaviour, and norm-or value-governed behaviour. The contributions to this discussion are too numerous to cite. But for some basic statements and the way in which such critiques have been viewed, answered and incorporated by some rational choice theorists, see Jon Elster, 'Selfishness and Altruism', in Jane J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), pp. 44-53; John Ferejohn, 'Rationality and Interpretation: Parliamentary Elections in Early Stuart England', in Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action (New York: Harper Collins, 1991), pp. 279-305; Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984), esp. pp. 75-101; Mansbridge, 'The Rise and Fall of Self-interest in the Explanation of Public Life', in Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest; Amartya K. Sen, 'Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory', in Frank Hahn and Martin Hollis, eds, Philosophy and Economic Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 87-109; Charles Taylor, 'Interpretation and the Sciences of Man', in Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan, eds, Interpretive Social Science: A Reader (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1979), pp. 25-71; Albert S. Yee, 'Thick Rationality and the Missing "Brute Fact": The Limits of Rationalist Incorporations of Norms and Ideas', Journal of Politics, 59 (1997), 1001-39. A different approach, reviewing the track record of rational choice approaches, is taken by Donald P. Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1994).
    • (1979) Philosophy and Economic Theory , pp. 87-109
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 21
    • 0002600438 scopus 로고
    • Interpretation and the sciences of man
    • Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan, eds, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press
    • Much critique of rational choice theory throws doubt on the idea that the model of a human agent as a rational maximizer is adequate for social science or philosophy. This article does not provide such a critique of rational choice theory. Such criticisms typically focus on the importance of the meaningful and communicative dimensions of conduct, on 'commitment', altruistic behaviour, and norm-or value-governed behaviour. The contributions to this discussion are too numerous to cite. But for some basic statements and the way in which such critiques have been viewed, answered and incorporated by some rational choice theorists, see Jon Elster, 'Selfishness and Altruism', in Jane J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), pp. 44-53; John Ferejohn, 'Rationality and Interpretation: Parliamentary Elections in Early Stuart England', in Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action (New York: Harper Collins, 1991), pp. 279-305; Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984), esp. pp. 75-101; Mansbridge, 'The Rise and Fall of Self-interest in the Explanation of Public Life', in Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest; Amartya K. Sen, 'Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory', in Frank Hahn and Martin Hollis, eds, Philosophy and Economic Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 87-109; Charles Taylor, 'Interpretation and the Sciences of Man', in Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan, eds, Interpretive Social Science: A Reader (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1979), pp. 25-71; Albert S. Yee, 'Thick Rationality and the Missing "Brute Fact": The Limits of Rationalist Incorporations of Norms and Ideas', Journal of Politics, 59 (1997), 1001-39. A different approach, reviewing the track record of rational choice approaches, is taken by Donald P. Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1994).
    • (1979) Interpretive Social Science: A Reader , pp. 25-71
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 22
    • 0031260726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thick rationality and the missing "Brute fact": The limits of rationalist incorporations of norms and ideas
    • Much critique of rational choice theory throws doubt on the idea that the model of a human agent as a rational maximizer is adequate for social science or philosophy. This article does not provide such a critique of rational choice theory. Such criticisms typically focus on the importance of the meaningful and communicative dimensions of conduct, on 'commitment', altruistic behaviour, and norm-or value-governed behaviour. The contributions to this discussion are too numerous to cite. But for some basic statements and the way in which such critiques have been viewed, answered and incorporated by some rational choice theorists, see Jon Elster, 'Selfishness and Altruism', in Jane J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), pp. 44-53; John Ferejohn, 'Rationality and Interpretation: Parliamentary Elections in Early Stuart England', in Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action (New York: Harper Collins, 1991), pp. 279-305; Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984), esp. pp. 75-101; Mansbridge, 'The Rise and Fall of Self-interest in the Explanation of Public Life', in Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest; Amartya K. Sen, 'Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory', in Frank Hahn and Martin Hollis, eds, Philosophy and Economic Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 87-109; Charles Taylor, 'Interpretation and the Sciences of Man', in Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan, eds, Interpretive Social Science: A Reader (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1979), pp. 25-71; Albert S. Yee, 'Thick Rationality and the Missing "Brute Fact": The Limits of Rationalist Incorporations of Norms and Ideas', Journal of Politics, 59 (1997), 1001-39. A different approach, reviewing the track record of rational choice approaches, is taken by Donald P. Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1994).
    • (1997) Journal of Politics , vol.59 , pp. 1001-1039
    • Yee, A.S.1
  • 23
    • 0003436920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press
    • Much critique of rational choice theory throws doubt on the idea that the model of a human agent as a rational maximizer is adequate for social science or philosophy. This article does not provide such a critique of rational choice theory. Such criticisms typically focus on the importance of the meaningful and communicative dimensions of conduct, on 'commitment', altruistic behaviour, and norm-or value-governed behaviour. The contributions to this discussion are too numerous to cite. But for some basic statements and the way in which such critiques have been viewed, answered and incorporated by some rational choice theorists, see Jon Elster, 'Selfishness and Altruism', in Jane J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), pp. 44-53; John Ferejohn, 'Rationality and Interpretation: Parliamentary Elections in Early Stuart England', in Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action (New York: Harper Collins, 1991), pp. 279-305; Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984), esp. pp. 75-101; Mansbridge, 'The Rise and Fall of Self-interest in the Explanation of Public Life', in Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest; Amartya K. Sen, 'Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory', in Frank Hahn and Martin Hollis, eds, Philosophy and Economic Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 87-109; Charles Taylor, 'Interpretation and the Sciences of Man', in Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan, eds, Interpretive Social Science: A Reader (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1979), pp. 25-71; Albert S. Yee, 'Thick Rationality and the Missing "Brute Fact": The Limits of Rationalist Incorporations of Norms and Ideas', Journal of Politics, 59 (1997), 1001-39. A different approach, reviewing the track record of rational choice approaches, is taken by Donald P. Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1994).
    • (1994) Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science
    • Green, D.P.1    Shapiro, I.2
  • 25
    • 0010592203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arrow, 'Economic Equilibrium', p. 376; and see Mark Addleson, Equilibrium versus Understanding: Toward the Restoration of Economics as Social Theory (London: Routledge, 1995), pp. 22-3. Of course, equilibrium analysis may also attempt to show the absence of any equilibrium condition.
    • Economic Equilibrium , pp. 376
    • Arrow1
  • 26
    • 0010919838 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge, Of course, equilibrium analysis may also attempt to show the absence of any equilibrium condition
    • Arrow, 'Economic Equilibrium', p. 376; and see Mark Addleson, Equilibrium versus Understanding: Toward the Restoration of Economics as Social Theory (London: Routledge, 1995), pp. 22-3. Of course, equilibrium analysis may also attempt to show the absence of any equilibrium condition.
    • (1995) Equilibrium Versus Understanding: Toward the Restoration of Economics as Social Theory , pp. 22-23
    • Addleson, M.1
  • 28
    • 84865826821 scopus 로고
    • Preface to the Japanese edition of "theorie der wirtschaftlichen entwicklung"
    • R. V. Clemence, ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Addison-Wesley
    • Schumpeter, 'Preface to the Japanese Edition of "Theorie der Wirtschaftlichen Entwicklung"', in R. V. Clemence, ed., Essays of J. A. Schumpeter (Cambridge, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1951), pp. 158-63, at pp. 159-60; Schumpeter, 'The Instability of Capitalism', in Clemence, ed., Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 47-52, at p. 50; emphasis added.
    • (1951) Essays of J. A. Schumpeter , pp. 158-163
    • Schumpeter1
  • 29
    • 0000227488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The instability of capitalism
    • Clemence, ed., emphasis added
    • Schumpeter, 'Preface to the Japanese Edition of "Theorie der Wirtschaftlichen Entwicklung"', in R. V. Clemence, ed., Essays of J. A. Schumpeter (Cambridge, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1951), pp. 158-63, at pp. 159-60; Schumpeter, 'The Instability of Capitalism', in Clemence, ed., Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 47-52, at p. 50; emphasis added.
    • Essays of J. A. Schumpeter , pp. 47-52
    • Schumpeter1
  • 31
    • 0010592203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When Kenneth Arrow points out that completeness is a necessary condition for equilibrium, in 'Economic Equilibrium', at p. 376, he is obviously referring to the completeness of the relevant model. For it is not at all clear what meaning could be attached to the idea of the 'completeness' or 'incompleteness' of the social world. This reinforces my point about abstraction. The concept of completeness here also has a mathematical interpretation, referring to the possibility of solving a series of simultaneous equations.
    • Economic Equilibrium , pp. 376
    • Arrow, K.1
  • 35
    • 0039614306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • thus calls an equilibrium a 'prediction, for a pre-specified circumstance, about the choice of people and the corresponding outcomes'
    • Ordeshook, in 'Political Disequilibrium', at p. 26, thus calls an equilibrium a 'prediction, for a pre-specified circumstance, about the choice of people and the corresponding outcomes'; see also P. C. Ordeshook, ed., Game Theory and Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. xiii.
    • Political Disequilibrium , pp. 26
    • Ordeshook1
  • 36
    • 0003992635 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Ordeshook, in 'Political Disequilibrium', at p. 26, thus calls an equilibrium a 'prediction, for a pre-specified circumstance, about the choice of people and the corresponding outcomes'; see also P. C. Ordeshook, ed., Game Theory and Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. xiii.
    • (1986) Game Theory and Political Theory
    • Ordeshook, P.C.1
  • 37
    • 84971145641 scopus 로고
    • Implications from the disequilibrium of majority rule for the study of institutions
    • William H. Riker, 'Implications from the Disequilibrium of Majority Rule for the Study of Institutions', American Political Science Review, 74 (1980), 432-46, at p. 432.
    • (1980) American Political Science Review , vol.74 , pp. 432-446
    • Riker, W.H.1
  • 41
    • 0001915985 scopus 로고
    • Rational choice and social theory
    • Debra Satz and John Ferejohn, 'Rational Choice and Social Theory', Journal of Philosophy, 91 (1994), 71-87, at pp. 74, 87.
    • (1994) Journal of Philosophy , vol.91 , pp. 71-87
    • Satz, D.1    Ferejohn, J.2
  • 52
    • 84929745880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis added
    • Schumpeter, History, p. 21, emphasis added.
    • History , pp. 21
    • Schumpeter1
  • 64
    • 0003201390 scopus 로고
    • An economic interpretation of our time: The Lowell Lectures
    • R. Swedberg, ed., Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Schumpeter, 'An Economic Interpretation of Our Time: The Lowell Lectures', in R. Swedberg, ed., The Economics and Sociology of Capitalism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1991), pp. 339-400, at pp. 343, 360; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 214, 298-9; Schumpeter, 'The March into Socialism', in Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 415-25, at p. 417.
    • (1991) The Economics and Sociology of Capitalism , pp. 339-400
    • Schumpeter1
  • 65
    • 0004295760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, 'An Economic Interpretation of Our Time: The Lowell Lectures', in R. Swedberg, ed., The Economics and Sociology of Capitalism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1991), pp. 339-400, at pp. 343, 360; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 214, 298-9; Schumpeter, 'The March into Socialism', in Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 415-25, at p. 417.
    • Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy , pp. 214
    • Schumpeter1
  • 66
    • 1342282419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The march into socialism
    • Schumpeter, 'An Economic Interpretation of Our Time: The Lowell Lectures', in R. Swedberg, ed., The Economics and Sociology of Capitalism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1991), pp. 339-400, at pp. 343, 360; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 214, 298-9; Schumpeter, 'The March into Socialism', in Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 415-25, at p. 417.
    • Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy , pp. 415-425
    • Schumpeter1
  • 67
    • 0004203360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Schumpeter, The History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), p. 21; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 11, 12; Schumpeter, 'The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and Economics," in Clemence, ed. Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 282-95, at pp. 287, 289; Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology', in Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 267-81, at pp. 269-71; Schumpeter, 'Review: The Road to Serfdom', Journal of Political Economy, 54 (1946), 269-70, at p. 270.
    • (1954) The History of Economic Analysis , pp. 21
    • Schumpeter1
  • 68
    • 0004295760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, The History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), p. 21; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 11, 12; Schumpeter, 'The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and Economics," in Clemence, ed. Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 282-95, at pp. 287, 289; Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology', in Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 267-81, at pp. 269-71; Schumpeter, 'Review: The Road to Serfdom', Journal of Political Economy, 54 (1946), 269-70, at p. 270.
    • Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy , pp. 11
    • Schumpeter1
  • 69
    • 73149098578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The communist manifesto in sociology and economics
    • Clemence, ed.
    • Schumpeter, The History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), p. 21; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 11, 12; Schumpeter, 'The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and Economics," in Clemence, ed. Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 282-95, at pp. 287, 289; Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology', in Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 267-81, at pp. 269-71; Schumpeter, 'Review: The Road to Serfdom', Journal of Political Economy, 54 (1946), 269-70, at p. 270.
    • Essays of J. A. Schumpeter , pp. 282-295
    • Schumpeter1
  • 70
    • 0039614313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and ideology
    • Schumpeter, The History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), p. 21; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 11, 12; Schumpeter, 'The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and Economics," in Clemence, ed. Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 282-95, at pp. 287, 289; Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology', in Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 267-81, at pp. 269-71; Schumpeter, 'Review: The Road to Serfdom', Journal of Political Economy, 54 (1946), 269-70, at p. 270.
    • Essays of J. A. Schumpeter , pp. 267-281
    • Schumpeter1
  • 71
    • 0000262568 scopus 로고
    • Review: The road to serfdom
    • Schumpeter, The History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), p. 21; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 11, 12; Schumpeter, 'The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and Economics," in Clemence, ed. Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 282-95, at pp. 287, 289; Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology', in Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 267-81, at pp. 269-71; Schumpeter, 'Review: The Road to Serfdom', Journal of Political Economy, 54 (1946), 269-70, at p. 270.
    • (1946) Journal of Political Economy , vol.54 , pp. 269-270
    • Schumpeter1
  • 73
    • 0002112928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 11, 121; Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology', pp. 269-70; Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis, p. 33.
    • Science and Ideology , pp. 269-270
    • Schumpeter1
  • 74
    • 0004203360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 11, 121; Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology', pp. 269-70; Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis, p. 33.
    • History of Economic Analysis , pp. 33
    • Schumpeter1
  • 75
    • 0040800345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, 'Review: The Road to Serfdom', p. 270; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 10-12; Schumpeter, 'The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and Economics', pp. 287-9.
    • Review: The Road to Serfdom , pp. 270
    • Schumpeter1
  • 76
    • 0004295760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, 'Review: The Road to Serfdom', p. 270; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 10-12; Schumpeter, 'The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and Economics', pp. 287-9.
    • Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy , pp. 10-12
    • Schumpeter1
  • 78
    • 0002112928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology'; Schumpeter, 'The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and Economics', p. 286, n. 8; Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis, pp. 33-47.
    • Science and Ideology
    • Schumpeter1
  • 80
    • 0004203360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology'; Schumpeter, 'The Communist Manifesto in Sociology and Economics', p. 286, n. 8; Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis, pp. 33-47.
    • History of Economic Analysis , pp. 33-47
    • Schumpeter1
  • 81
    • 0002112928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology'; Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis, pp. 33-47; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 264-8.
    • Science and Ideology
    • Schumpeter1
  • 82
    • 0004203360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology'; Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis, pp. 33-47; Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, pp. 264-8.
    • History of Economic Analysis , pp. 33-47
    • Schumpeter1
  • 84
    • 0002861165 scopus 로고
    • Ideology as a cultural system
    • New York: Basic Books
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1973) The Interpretation of Cultures
    • Geertz, C.1
  • 85
    • 0003419716 scopus 로고
    • San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936]
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1985) Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge
    • Mannheim, K.1
  • 86
    • 0002342717 scopus 로고
    • New York: International Publishers
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1960) The German Ideology, Parts I & Iii
    • Marx, K.1    Engels, F.2
  • 87
    • 0003586486 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1962) How to Do Things with Words
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 88
    • 84904519672 scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1983) Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis
    • Bernstein, R.1
  • 89
    • 0003463975 scopus 로고
    • Leeds: Leeds Books
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1975) A Realist Theory of Science
    • Bhaskar, R.1
  • 90
    • 0004222329 scopus 로고
    • New York: Mentor Books, [1949]
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1920) Reconstruction in Philosophy
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 91
    • 1642593208 scopus 로고
    • London: Verso
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1988) Against Method, Rev'd Edn
    • Feyerabend, P.1
  • 92
    • 0003769690 scopus 로고
    • Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem
    • (1975) Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry
    • Gunnell, J.1
  • 93
    • 0002644749 scopus 로고
    • Logic of discovery or psychology of research?
    • Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge , pp. 1-23
    • Kuhn, T.1
  • 94
    • 0002479337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes
    • Lakatos and Musgrave, eds
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge , pp. 91-189
    • Lakatos, I.1
  • 95
    • 0040511745 scopus 로고
    • Two dogmas of empiricism
    • A. P. Martinich, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The conception presented here draws on Schumpeter's work cited above and several other sources; Clifford Geertz, 'Ideology as a Cultural System', The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973); Karl Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, [1936] 1985); and Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Parts I & III (New York: International Publishers, 1960). Scholarly discussions of these sources, especially of Marx and Mannheim, all too often focuses on whether any precinct of thought can be saved from the 'ideological' label, and on the problem of whether a particular conception of ideology commits one to a self-undermining admission that even one's own perspective is ideological. Generally speaking, like Schumpeter, I am convinced that the problems of uncertainty, perspective, and the social conditioning of thought - usually associated with the term 'ideology' - are endemic to all forms of knowledge and investigation, including those we deem (more or less justifiably) scientific. With this in mind, my conception of ideology also draws on a number of sources that would normally be considered as contributions not to the theory of ideology, but to epistemology, the theory of language, and the philosophy of science. These sources include: J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962); Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983); Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science (Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975); John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York: Mentor Books, [1949] 1920); Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev'd edn (London: Verso, 1988); John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975); Thomas Kuhn, 'Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?' in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 1-23; Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Lakatos and Musgrave, eds, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91-189; W. V. Quine, 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', in A. P. Martinich, ed., The Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 26-39.
    • (1990) The Philosophy of Language, 2nd Edn , pp. 26-39
    • Quine, W.V.1
  • 96
    • 0039614312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For those who wish to pursue the point, my argument here is directly analogous to Quine's portrayal of knowledge, in 'Two Dogmas', at p. 37, as a 'man-made fabric' or a 'field' so 'underdetermined' by experience 'that there is much latitude of choice as to what statement to reevaluate in the light of any single contrary experience'.
    • Two Dogmas , pp. 37
  • 99
    • 0039614313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and ideology
    • Clemence, ed.
    • Schumpeter, 'Science and Ideology', in Clemence, ed., Essays of J. A. Schumpeter, pp. 267-81, at p. 272.
    • Essays of J. A. Schumpeter , pp. 267-281
    • Schumpeter1
  • 101
    • 0039614311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Galileo, for example, did not merely refute Aristotelian astronomical ideas with facts; he did so with telescopic observations, which in turn rested on a theory of optics (Lakatos, 'Falsification', p. 98).
    • Falsification , pp. 98
    • Lakatos1
  • 104
    • 0002041171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction: Opportunities, mobilizing structures, and framing processes - Toward a synthetic, comparative perspective on social movements
    • D. McAdam, J. D. McCarthy and M. N. Zald, eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Doug McAdam, John D. McCarthy and Mayer N. Zald, 'Introduction: Opportunities, Mobilizing Structures, and Framing Processes - Toward a Synthetic, Comparative Perspective on Social Movements', in D. McAdam, J. D. McCarthy and M. N. Zald, eds, Comparative Perspectives on Social Movements: Political Opportunities, Mobilizing Structures, and Cultural Framings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 1-20, at p. 2.
    • (1996) Comparative Perspectives on Social Movements: Political Opportunities, Mobilizing Structures, and Cultural Framings , pp. 1-20
    • McAdam, D.1    McCarthy, J.D.2    Zald, M.N.3
  • 106
    • 0010126587 scopus 로고
    • Many democracies: On Tocqueville and Jacksonian America
    • A. S. Eisenstadt, ed., New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press
    • Sean Wilentz, 'Many Democracies: On Tocqueville and Jacksonian America', in A. S. Eisenstadt, ed., Reconsidering Tocqueville's Democracy in America (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1988), pp. 207-28.
    • (1988) Reconsidering Tocqueville's Democracy in America , pp. 207-228
    • Wilentz, S.1
  • 108
    • 0002678579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy's third wave
    • L. Diamond and M. F. Plattner, eds, Baltimore, Md: Johns Hopkins University Press
    • Samuel P. Huntington, 'Democracy's Third Wave', in L. Diamond and M. F. Plattner, eds, The Global Resurgence of Democracy, 2nd edn (Baltimore, Md: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1996), pp. 3-25, at p. 21.
    • (1996) The Global Resurgence of Democracy, 2nd Edn , pp. 3-25
    • Huntington, S.P.1
  • 110
    • 0009347062 scopus 로고
    • On the social contract
    • Indianapolis: Hackett
    • See, e.g., Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 'On the Social Contract', The Basic Political Writings (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987); John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1991); G. D. H. Cole, Guild Socialism: A Plan for Economic Democracy (New York: Frederick A. Stokes, 1920); John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1935); Carole Pateman, Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
    • (1987) The Basic Political Writings
    • Rousseau, J.-J.1
  • 111
    • 0003433597 scopus 로고
    • Buffalo: Prometheus Books
    • See, e.g., Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 'On the Social Contract', The Basic Political Writings (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987); John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1991); G. D. H. Cole, Guild Socialism: A Plan for Economic Democracy (New York: Frederick A. Stokes, 1920); John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1935); Carole Pateman, Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
    • (1991) Considerations on Representative Government
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 112
    • 0039614349 scopus 로고
    • New York: Frederick A. Stokes
    • See, e.g., Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 'On the Social Contract', The Basic Political Writings (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987); John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1991); G. D. H. Cole, Guild Socialism: A Plan for Economic Democracy (New York: Frederick A. Stokes, 1920); John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1935); Carole Pateman, Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
    • (1920) Guild Socialism: A Plan for Economic Democracy
    • Cole, G.D.H.1
  • 113
    • 0004269427 scopus 로고
    • New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons
    • See, e.g., Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 'On the Social Contract', The Basic Political Writings (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987); John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1991); G. D. H. Cole, Guild Socialism: A Plan for Economic Democracy (New York: Frederick A. Stokes, 1920); John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1935); Carole Pateman, Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
    • (1935) Liberalism and Social Action
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 114
    • 84952647825 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See, e.g., Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 'On the Social Contract', The Basic Political Writings (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987); John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1991); G. D. H. Cole, Guild Socialism: A Plan for Economic Democracy (New York: Frederick A. Stokes, 1920); John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1935); Carole Pateman, Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
    • (1970) Participation and Democratic Theory
    • Pateman, C.1
  • 121
    • 0004295760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, p. 271. This, of course, invites criticisms that Schumpeter's elite conception of democracy is not very democratic. But that is not my point here.
    • Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy , pp. 271
    • Schumpeter1
  • 128
    • 0039021999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 11
    • Downs, Economic Theory, pp. 28, 29, note 11, p. 284. In fact, Downs twice quotes Schumpeter's summary argument from Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, p. 282, quoted above.
    • Economic Theory , pp. 28
    • Downs1
  • 129
    • 84972938272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Downs, Economic Theory, pp. 28, 29, note 11, p. 284. In fact, Downs twice quotes Schumpeter's summary argument from Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, p. 282, quoted above.
    • Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy , pp. 282
  • 136
    • 77949803173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Economic Theory, at pp. 79 and 83, Downs clearly equates information with data or facts.
    • Economic Theory , pp. 79
  • 149
    • 0039021999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Downs, Economic Theory, p. 23, n. 5. Standing on purely terminological grounds, one might acquit Downs of the charge of contradiction by pointing out that 'universal suffrage' and 'manhood' suffrage have often been used synonymously. But the overall point would be the same. Downs's failure to recognize the real, practical and principled contradiction between universal suffrage and the exclusion of women and 'resident aliens' from voting was emblematic of his larger failure to make the establishment of democracy and battles about the meaning of democracy part of his supposedly comprehensive theory of democracy.
    • Economic Theory , pp. 23
    • Downs1
  • 152
    • 0003417695 scopus 로고
    • London: Collier-Macmillan
    • Brian Barry noted this problem almost thirty years ago in Sociologists, Economists and Democracy (London: Collier-Macmillan, 1970), pp. 13-23. More recently, Green and Shapiro have traced the broader rational choice literature deriving from Downs's prediction of 'rational abstention' (Pathologies of Rational Choice, pp. 47-71). Both Barry and Green and Shapiro argue that since Downs postulated voting as a collective action problem, his conjecture that some voters may feel very committed to the continuance of democratic practices could no more account for their voting than could self-interested calculation (Barry, Sociologists, Economists and Democracy, p. 20; Green and Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice, pp. 50-1), but this is beyond the scope of my interests here.
    • (1970) Sociologists, Economists and Democracy , pp. 13-23
    • Barry, B.1
  • 153
    • 0003436920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brian Barry noted this problem almost thirty years ago in Sociologists, Economists and Democracy (London: Collier-Macmillan, 1970), pp. 13-23. More recently, Green and Shapiro have traced the broader rational choice literature deriving from Downs's prediction of 'rational abstention' (Pathologies of Rational Choice, pp. 47-71). Both Barry and Green and Shapiro argue that since Downs postulated voting as a collective action problem, his conjecture that some voters may feel very committed to the continuance of democratic practices could no more account for their voting than could self-interested calculation (Barry, Sociologists, Economists and Democracy, p. 20; Green and Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice, pp. 50-1), but this is beyond the scope of my interests here.
    • Pathologies of Rational Choice , pp. 47-71
    • Green1    Shapiro2
  • 154
    • 84959617517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brian Barry noted this problem almost thirty years ago in Sociologists, Economists and Democracy (London: Collier-Macmillan, 1970), pp. 13-23. More recently, Green and Shapiro have traced the broader rational choice literature deriving from Downs's prediction of 'rational abstention' (Pathologies of Rational Choice, pp. 47-71). Both Barry and Green and Shapiro argue that since Downs postulated voting as a collective action problem, his conjecture that some voters may feel very committed to the continuance of democratic practices could no more account for their voting than could self-interested calculation (Barry, Sociologists, Economists and Democracy, p. 20; Green and Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice, pp. 50-1), but this is beyond the scope of my interests here.
    • Sociologists, Economists and Democracy , pp. 20
  • 155
    • 0003436920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brian Barry noted this problem almost thirty years ago in Sociologists, Economists and Democracy (London: Collier-Macmillan, 1970), pp. 13-23. More recently, Green and Shapiro have traced the broader rational choice literature deriving from Downs's prediction of 'rational abstention' (Pathologies of Rational Choice, pp. 47-71). Both Barry and Green and Shapiro argue that since Downs postulated voting as a collective action problem, his conjecture that some voters may feel very committed to the continuance of democratic practices could no more account for their voting than could self-interested calculation (Barry, Sociologists, Economists and Democracy, p. 20; Green and Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice, pp. 50-1), but this is beyond the scope of my interests here.
    • Pathologies of Rational Choice , pp. 50-51
    • Green1    Shapiro2
  • 156
    • 0040206084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ordeshook, 'Constitutional Stability'; Przeworski, Democracy and the Market; Weingast, 'Economic Role of Political Institutions'; Weingast, 'Political Foundations of Democracy'.
    • Constitutional Stability
    • Ordeshook1
  • 157
    • 0004274890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ordeshook, 'Constitutional Stability'; Przeworski, Democracy and the Market; Weingast, 'Economic Role of Political Institutions'; Weingast, 'Political Foundations of Democracy'.
    • Democracy and the Market
    • Przeworski1
  • 158
  • 159
    • 0040800351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ordeshook, 'Constitutional Stability'; Przeworski, Democracy and the Market; Weingast, 'Economic Role of Political Institutions'; Weingast, 'Political Foundations of Democracy'.
    • Political Foundations of Democracy
    • Weingast1
  • 160
    • 84972780484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Przeworski, Democracy, p. 15. He poses the problem similarly in 'Minimalist Conception of Democracy', at pp. 46 and 49, as part of a broader argument in favour of what he terms, at p. 23, a 'Schumpeterian conception of democracy'.
    • Democracy , pp. 15
    • Przeworski1
  • 161
    • 0039022051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Przeworski, Democracy, p. 15. He poses the problem similarly in 'Minimalist Conception of Democracy', at pp. 46 and 49, as part of a broader argument in favour of what he terms, at p. 23, a 'Schumpeterian conception of democracy'.
    • Minimalist Conception of Democracy , pp. 46
  • 162
    • 0040800350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Przeworski, Democracy, p. 15. He poses the problem similarly in 'Minimalist Conception of Democracy', at pp. 46 and 49, as part of a broader argument in favour of what he terms, at p. 23, a 'Schumpeterian conception of democracy'.
    • Schumpeterian Conception of Democracy , pp. 23
  • 168
    • 0003424516 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • It was only after decades of Jim Crow oppression that many Americans recognized even the most blatant transgressions of African Americans' democratic rights. See, e.g., Doug McAdam, Political Process and the Development of Black Insurgency, 1930-1970 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), p. 109. There were at least two intertwined aspects to the ideological shift brought about by African-American insurgency. McAdam refers to one of these as 'cognitive liberation', the process by which some African Americans themselves came to recognize what Weingast would call 'transgressions' as problems they could challenge by collective action. As McAdam points out, in Political Process, at p. 35, 'structural inequities may be constant, but the collective perception of the legitimacy and mutability of those conditions is likely to vary a great deal over time'. The other aspect is the shift in the ideological response of 'other groups to blacks', which McAdam largely attributes to a sense of legitimacy won by the Civil Rights movement through the tactic for forcing the federal government to intervene on its behalf (Political Process, pp. 108, 163-6, 169-72).
    • (1982) Political Process and the Development of Black Insurgency, 1930-1970 , pp. 109
    • McAdam, D.1
  • 169
    • 0004331245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It was only after decades of Jim Crow oppression that many Americans recognized even the most blatant transgressions of African Americans' democratic rights. See, e.g., Doug McAdam, Political Process and the Development of Black Insurgency, 1930-1970 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), p. 109. There were at least two intertwined aspects to the ideological shift brought about by African-American insurgency. McAdam refers to one of these as 'cognitive liberation', the process by which some African Americans themselves came to recognize what Weingast would call 'transgressions' as problems they could challenge by collective action. As McAdam points out, in Political Process, at p. 35, 'structural inequities may be constant, but the collective perception of the legitimacy and mutability of those conditions is likely to vary a great deal over time'. The other aspect is the shift in the ideological response of 'other groups to blacks', which McAdam largely attributes to a sense of legitimacy won by the Civil Rights movement through the tactic for forcing the federal government to intervene on its behalf (Political Process, pp. 108, 163-6, 169-72).
    • Political Process , pp. 35
    • McAdam1
  • 170
    • 0004331245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It was only after decades of Jim Crow oppression that many Americans recognized even the most blatant transgressions of African Americans' democratic rights. See, e.g., Doug McAdam, Political Process and the Development of Black Insurgency, 1930-1970 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), p. 109. There were at least two intertwined aspects to the ideological shift brought about by African-American insurgency. McAdam refers to one of these as 'cognitive liberation', the process by which some African Americans themselves came to recognize what Weingast would call 'transgressions' as problems they could challenge by collective action. As McAdam points out, in Political Process, at p. 35, 'structural inequities may be constant, but the collective perception of the legitimacy and mutability of those conditions is likely to vary a great deal over time'. The other aspect is the shift in the ideological response of 'other groups to blacks', which McAdam largely attributes to a sense of legitimacy won by the Civil Rights movement through the tactic for forcing the federal government to intervene on its behalf (Political Process, pp. 108, 163-6, 169-72).
    • Political Process , pp. 108
    • McAdam1
  • 173
    • 84972780484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Przeworski, Democracy, p. 19. On pp. 29-31, he also offers a formal elaboration of this argument.
    • Democracy , pp. 19
    • Przeworski1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.