-
1
-
-
0346491831
-
Justifying the Natural Law Theory of Constitutional Interpretation
-
Michael S. Moore, Justifying the Natural Law Theory of Constitutional Interpretation, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 2087 (2001).
-
(2001)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.69
, pp. 2087
-
-
Moore, M.S.1
-
2
-
-
0042926071
-
-
Moore is arguably the leading proponent of a moral realist or natural law theory of constitutional interpretation among law professors. Sotirios A. Barber is arguably the leading proponent of a theory similar to Moore's view among political science professors. See, e.g., Sotirios A. Barber, The Constitution of Judicial Power (1993); Sotirios A. Barber, On What the Constitution Means (1984). Robert P. George has developed a moral realist or natural law theory that is radically different from Moore's and Barber's views both in its content and in its implications for a theory of judicial review. See, e.g., Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review, 69 Fordham L. Rev. (forthcoming May 2001). In a forthcoming article, I criticize George's view. See James E. Fleming, Fidelity to Natural Law and Natural Rights in Constitutional Interpretation, 69 Fordham L. Rev. (May 2001). I should acknowledge and address an evident tension between my critique of Moore's view here and my critique of George's view there. Here, I criticize Moore for placing too much emphasis upon judicial enforcement of natural rights to the exclusion of protection of natural rights outside the courts by legislatures, executives, and citizens generally. There, I criticize George for rejecting judicial enforcement of natural rights and leaving the protection of natural rights to legislatures, executives, and citizens generally. I would reconcile my evidently conflicting positions in the two papers by claiming that we need protection of natural rights both in the courts (contra George) and outside the courts (contra Moore). Put another way, my view lies between those of Moore and George: we need more emphasis on protection of natural rights outside the courts than Moore countenances, and more emphasis on protection of natural rights by courts than George contemplates.
-
(1993)
The Constitution of Judicial Power
-
-
Barber, S.A.1
-
3
-
-
0011665728
-
-
Moore is arguably the leading proponent of a moral realist or natural law theory of constitutional interpretation among law professors. Sotirios A. Barber is arguably the leading proponent of a theory similar to Moore's view among political science professors. See, e.g., Sotirios A. Barber, The Constitution of Judicial Power (1993); Sotirios A. Barber, On What the Constitution Means (1984). Robert P. George has developed a moral realist or natural law theory that is radically different from Moore's and Barber's views both in its content and in its implications for a theory of judicial review. See, e.g., Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review, 69 Fordham L. Rev. (forthcoming May 2001). In a forthcoming article, I criticize George's view. See James E. Fleming, Fidelity to Natural Law and Natural Rights in Constitutional Interpretation, 69 Fordham L. Rev. (May 2001). I should acknowledge and address an evident tension between my critique of Moore's view here and my critique of George's view there. Here, I criticize Moore for placing too much emphasis upon judicial enforcement of natural rights to the exclusion of protection of natural rights outside the courts by legislatures, executives, and citizens generally. There, I criticize George for rejecting judicial enforcement of natural rights and leaving the protection of natural rights to legislatures, executives, and citizens generally. I would reconcile my evidently conflicting positions in the two papers by claiming that we need protection of natural rights both in the courts (contra George) and outside the courts (contra Moore). Put another way, my view lies between those of Moore and George: we need more emphasis on protection of natural rights outside the courts than Moore countenances, and more emphasis on protection of natural rights by courts than George contemplates.
-
(1984)
On What the Constitution Means
-
-
Barber, S.A.1
-
4
-
-
84937345096
-
Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review
-
forthcoming May
-
Moore is arguably the leading proponent of a moral realist or natural law theory of constitutional interpretation among law professors. Sotirios A. Barber is arguably the leading proponent of a theory similar to Moore's view among political science professors. See, e.g., Sotirios A. Barber, The Constitution of Judicial Power (1993); Sotirios A. Barber, On What the Constitution Means (1984). Robert P. George has developed a moral realist or natural law theory that is radically different from Moore's and Barber's views both in its content and in its implications for a theory of judicial review. See, e.g., Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review, 69 Fordham L. Rev. (forthcoming May 2001). In a forthcoming article, I criticize George's view. See James E. Fleming, Fidelity to Natural Law and Natural Rights in Constitutional Interpretation, 69 Fordham L. Rev. (May 2001). I should acknowledge and address an evident tension between my critique of Moore's view here and my critique of George's view there. Here, I criticize Moore for placing too much emphasis upon judicial enforcement of natural rights to the exclusion of protection of natural rights outside the courts by legislatures, executives, and citizens generally. There, I criticize George for rejecting judicial enforcement of natural rights and leaving the protection of natural rights to legislatures, executives, and citizens generally. I would reconcile my evidently conflicting positions in the two papers by claiming that we need protection of natural rights both in the courts (contra George) and outside the courts (contra Moore). Put another way, my view lies between those of Moore and George: we need more emphasis on protection of natural rights outside the courts than Moore countenances, and more emphasis on protection of natural rights by courts than George contemplates.
-
(2001)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.69
-
-
George, R.P.1
-
5
-
-
84937346114
-
Fidelity to Natural Law and Natural Rights in Constitutional Interpretation
-
May
-
Moore is arguably the leading proponent of a moral realist or natural law theory of constitutional interpretation among law professors. Sotirios A. Barber is arguably the leading proponent of a theory similar to Moore's view among political science professors. See, e.g., Sotirios A. Barber, The Constitution of Judicial Power (1993); Sotirios A. Barber, On What the Constitution Means (1984). Robert P. George has developed a moral realist or natural law theory that is radically different from Moore's and Barber's views both in its content and in its implications for a theory of judicial review. See, e.g., Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review, 69 Fordham L. Rev. (forthcoming May 2001). In a forthcoming article, I criticize George's view. See James E. Fleming, Fidelity to Natural Law and Natural Rights in Constitutional Interpretation, 69 Fordham L. Rev. (May 2001). I should acknowledge and address an evident tension between my critique of Moore's view here and my critique of George's view there. Here, I criticize Moore for placing too much emphasis upon judicial enforcement of natural rights to the exclusion of protection of natural rights outside the courts by legislatures, executives, and citizens generally. There, I criticize George for rejecting judicial enforcement of natural rights and leaving the protection of natural rights to legislatures, executives, and citizens generally. I would reconcile my evidently conflicting positions in the two papers by claiming that we need protection of natural rights both in the courts (contra George) and outside the courts (contra Moore). Put another way, my view lies between those of Moore and George: we need more emphasis on protection of natural rights outside the courts than Moore countenances, and more emphasis on protection of natural rights by courts than George contemplates.
-
(2001)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.69
-
-
Fleming, J.E.1
-
6
-
-
0347374601
-
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2089
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2089.
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
0347374597
-
-
(unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Princeton University) (on file with author) [hereinafter Fleming, Constitutional Constructivism]
-
In the 1980s, I wrote a Ph.D. doctoral dissertation developing a constitutional constructivism as a third way between legal positivist and natural law theories of constitutional interpretation. See James E. Fleming, Constitutional Constructivism (1988) (unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Princeton University) (on file with author) [hereinafter Fleming, Constitutional Constructivism].
-
(1988)
Constitutional Constructivism
-
-
Fleming, J.E.1
-
8
-
-
0039388859
-
The Independence of Moral Theory
-
Samuel Freeman ed.
-
John Rawls, The Independence of Moral Theory, in John Rawls: Collected Papers 286, 286-87 (Samuel Freeman ed., 1999).
-
(1999)
John Rawls: Collected Papers
, pp. 286
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
9
-
-
0003624191
-
-
hereinafter Rawls, Political Liberalism
-
See John Rawls, Political Liberalism 90-99 (1993) [hereinafter Rawls, Political Liberalism] (distinguishing his project of political constructivism from that of theories of moral realism or natural law); John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 263 (1971) (characterizing his theory as attempting to find an "Archimedean point" outside existing circumstances that does not "appeal to a priori or perfectionist principles").
-
(1993)
Political Liberalism
, pp. 90-99
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
10
-
-
0004048289
-
-
See John Rawls, Political Liberalism 90-99 (1993) [hereinafter Rawls, Political Liberalism] (distinguishing his project of political constructivism from that of theories of moral realism or natural law); John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 263 (1971) (characterizing his theory as attempting to find an "Archimedean point" outside existing circumstances that does not "appeal to a priori or perfectionist principles").
-
(1971)
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 263
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
11
-
-
85055294934
-
Constructing the Substantive Constitution
-
[hereinafter Fleming, Constructing the Substantive Constitution]
-
See James E. Fleming, Constructing the Substantive Constitution, 72 Tex. L. Rev. 211, 217 (1993) [hereinafter Fleming, Constructing the Substantive Constitution]; Fleming, Constitutional Constructivism, supra note 4.
-
(1993)
Tex. L. Rev.
, vol.72
, pp. 211
-
-
Fleming, J.E.1
-
12
-
-
0348004972
-
-
supra note 4
-
See James E. Fleming, Constructing the Substantive Constitution, 72 Tex. L. Rev. 211, 217 (1993) [hereinafter Fleming, Constructing the Substantive Constitution]; Fleming, Constitutional Constructivism, supra note 4.
-
Constitutional Constructivism
-
-
Fleming1
-
13
-
-
0347374600
-
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2099
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2099.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
0348004974
-
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
0348004976
-
-
Id. at 2102
-
Id. at 2102.
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
0347374598
-
-
Id. at 2100
-
Id. at 2100.
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
0346113646
-
-
Id. at 2100-01
-
Id. at 2100-01.
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
0348004977
-
-
Id. at 2101
-
Id. at 2101
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
0347374599
-
-
See id, at 129-53
-
See id, at 129-53.
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
0346113647
-
-
Id. at 165-72
-
Id. at 165-72.
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
23044521979
-
The Constitution Outside the Courts
-
[hereinafter Fleming The Constitution Outside the Courts] (reviewing Tushnet, supra note 14) (footnote omitted)
-
James E. Fleming, The Constitution Outside the Courts, 86 Cornell L. Rev. 215, 218 (2000) [hereinafter Fleming The Constitution Outside the Courts] (reviewing Tushnet, supra note 14) (footnote omitted).
-
(2000)
Cornell L. Rev.
, vol.86
, pp. 215
-
-
Fleming, J.E.1
-
23
-
-
77957180894
-
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2103
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2103 (referring to Jeremy Waldron, A Rights-Based Critique of Constitutional Rights, 13 Ox. J. Legal Stud. 18 (1993)) .
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
77957180894
-
A Rights-Based Critique of Constitutional Rights
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2103 (referring to Jeremy Waldron, A Rights-Based Critique of Constitutional Rights, 13 Ox. J. Legal Stud. 18 (1993)) .
-
(1993)
Ox. J. Legal Stud.
, vol.13
, pp. 18
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
26
-
-
0346744216
-
-
Id. at 2101
-
Id. at 2101.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
0348004965
-
-
Id. at 2102
-
Id. at 2102.
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
0346113611
-
-
Id. at 2103
-
Id. at 2103.
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
0347374596
-
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
0346744215
-
-
Id. at 2101
-
Id. at 2101.
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
0346744213
-
-
Id. at 2102
-
Id. at 2102.
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
0346744214
-
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
0347374571
-
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
0348004975
-
-
Id. at 2104
-
Id. at 2104.
-
-
-
-
35
-
-
0002231837
-
The Idea of Public Reason Revisited
-
supra note 5
-
See John Rawls, The Idea of Public Reason Revisited, in John Rawls: Collected Papers, supra note 5, at 573, 579-81; Rawls, Political Liberalism, supra note 6, at 4-5, 240, 299.
-
John Rawls: Collected Papers
, pp. 573
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
36
-
-
0003624191
-
-
supra note 6
-
See John Rawls, The Idea of Public Reason Revisited, in John Rawls: Collected Papers, supra note 5, at 573, 579-81; Rawls, Political Liberalism, supra note 6, at 4-5, 240, 299.
-
Political Liberalism
, pp. 4-5
-
-
Rawls1
-
37
-
-
37149031564
-
Law's Republic
-
See, e.g., Frank Michelman, Law's Republic, 97 Yale L.J. 1493 (1988).
-
(1988)
Yale L.J.
, vol.97
, pp. 1493
-
-
Michelman, F.1
-
40
-
-
0346744239
-
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2115-17
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2115-17.
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
0346744240
-
-
See, e.g., Sunstein, supra note 31, at 9-10
-
See, e.g., Sunstein, supra note 31, at 9-10; Lawrence G. Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms, 91 Harv. L. Rev. 1212 (1978) [hereinafter Sager, Fair Measure]; Lawrence G. Sager, Justice in Plain Clothes: Reflections on the Thinness of Constitutional Law, 88 Nw. U. L. Rev. 410 (1993) [hereinafter Sager, Thinness].
-
-
-
-
42
-
-
0039382284
-
Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms
-
hereinafter Sager, Fair Measure
-
See, e.g., Sunstein, supra note 31, at 9-10; Lawrence G. Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms, 91 Harv. L. Rev. 1212 (1978) [hereinafter Sager, Fair Measure]; Lawrence G. Sager, Justice in Plain Clothes: Reflections on the Thinness of Constitutional Law, 88 Nw. U. L. Rev. 410 (1993) [hereinafter Sager, Thinness].
-
(1978)
Harv. L. Rev.
, vol.91
, pp. 1212
-
-
Sager, L.G.1
-
43
-
-
77954331568
-
Justice in Plain Clothes: Reflections on the Thinness of Constitutional Law
-
hereinafter Sager, Thinness
-
See, e.g., Sunstein, supra note 31, at 9-10; Lawrence G. Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms, 91 Harv. L. Rev. 1212 (1978) [hereinafter Sager, Fair Measure]; Lawrence G. Sager, Justice in Plain Clothes: Reflections on the Thinness of Constitutional Law, 88 Nw. U. L. Rev. 410 (1993) [hereinafter Sager, Thinness].
-
(1993)
Nw. U. L. Rev.
, vol.88
, pp. 410
-
-
Sager, L.G.1
-
46
-
-
0348004973
-
-
See Tushnet, supra note 14, at 14-26, 57-65, 95-128
-
See Tushnet, supra note 14, at 14-26, 57-65, 95-128.
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
0040176202
-
The Conscientious Legislator's Guide to Constitutional Interpretation
-
Paul Brest, The Conscientious Legislator's Guide to Constitutional Interpretation, 27 Stan. L. Rev. 585, 585 (1975).
-
(1975)
Stan. L. Rev.
, vol.27
, pp. 585
-
-
Brest, P.1
-
50
-
-
0347752504
-
Thin Constitutions and the Good Society
-
Lawrence G. Sager, Thin Constitutions and the Good Society, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 1989 (2001); Sager, Fair Measure, supra note 34; Sager, Thinness, supra note 34.
-
(2001)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.69
, pp. 1989
-
-
Sager, L.G.1
-
51
-
-
0348004964
-
-
supra note 34
-
Lawrence G. Sager, Thin Constitutions and the Good Society, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 1989 (2001); Sager, Fair Measure, supra note 34; Sager, Thinness, supra note 34.
-
Fair Measure
-
-
Sager1
-
52
-
-
0348004969
-
-
supra note 34
-
Lawrence G. Sager, Thin Constitutions and the Good Society, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 1989 (2001); Sager, Fair Measure, supra note 34; Sager, Thinness, supra note 34.
-
Thinness
-
-
Sager1
-
53
-
-
0348005211
-
Conservative Free Speech and the Uneasy Case for Judicial Review
-
Mary Becker, Conservative Free Speech and the Uneasy Case for Judicial Review, 64 U. Colo. L. Rev. 975 (1993); Mary E. Becker, The Politics of Women's Wrongs and the Bill of "Rights": A Bicentennial Perspective, 59 U. Chi. L. Rev. 453 (1992); Mary Becker, Towards a Progressive Politics and a Progressive Constitution, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 2007 (2001).
-
(1993)
U. Colo. L. Rev.
, vol.64
, pp. 975
-
-
Becker, M.1
-
54
-
-
84933493444
-
The Politics of Women's Wrongs and the Bill of "Rights": A Bicentennial Perspective
-
Mary Becker, Conservative Free Speech and the Uneasy Case for Judicial Review, 64 U. Colo. L. Rev. 975 (1993); Mary E. Becker, The Politics of Women's Wrongs and the Bill of "Rights": A Bicentennial Perspective, 59 U. Chi. L. Rev. 453 (1992); Mary Becker, Towards a Progressive Politics and a Progressive Constitution, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 2007 (2001).
-
(1992)
U. Chi. L. Rev.
, vol.59
, pp. 453
-
-
Becker, M.E.1
-
55
-
-
0035625877
-
Towards a Progressive Politics and a Progressive Constitution
-
Mary Becker, Conservative Free Speech and the Uneasy Case for Judicial Review, 64 U. Colo. L. Rev. 975 (1993); Mary E. Becker, The Politics of Women's Wrongs and the Bill of "Rights": A Bicentennial Perspective, 59 U. Chi. L. Rev. 453 (1992); Mary Becker, Towards a Progressive Politics and a Progressive Constitution, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 2007 (2001).
-
(2001)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.69
, pp. 2007
-
-
Becker, M.1
-
56
-
-
0003964462
-
-
See, e.g., Louis Fisher, Constitutional Dialogues: Interpretation as Political Process (1988); Louis Fisher & Neal Devins, Political Dynamics of Constitutional Law (2d ed. 1996); Louis Fisher, Constitutional Interpretation by Members of Congress, 63 N.C. L. Rev. 707 (1985).
-
(1988)
Constitutional Dialogues: Interpretation as Political Process
-
-
Fisher, L.1
-
57
-
-
0346744212
-
-
See, e.g., Louis Fisher, Constitutional Dialogues: Interpretation as Political Process (1988); Louis Fisher & Neal Devins, Political Dynamics of Constitutional Law (2d ed. 1996); Louis Fisher, Constitutional Interpretation by Members of Congress, 63 N.C. L. Rev. 707 (1985).
-
(1996)
Political Dynamics of Constitutional Law 2d Ed.
-
-
Fisher, L.1
Devins, N.2
-
58
-
-
0039867249
-
Constitutional Interpretation by Members of Congress
-
See, e.g., Louis Fisher, Constitutional Dialogues: Interpretation as Political Process (1988); Louis Fisher & Neal Devins, Political Dynamics of Constitutional Law (2d ed. 1996); Louis Fisher, Constitutional Interpretation by Members of Congress, 63 N.C. L. Rev. 707 (1985).
-
(1985)
N.C. L. Rev.
, vol.63
, pp. 707
-
-
Fisher, L.1
-
62
-
-
84920564867
-
The Arduous Virtue of Fidelity: Originalism, Scalia, Tribe, and Nerve
-
Ronald Dworkin, The Arduous Virtue of Fidelity: Originalism, Scalia, Tribe, and Nerve, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1249, 1251-56 (1997); see also Ronald Dworkin, Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution (1996) [hereinafter Dworkin, Freedom's Law].
-
(1997)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.65
, pp. 1249
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
63
-
-
0003496214
-
-
hereinafter Dworkin, Freedom's Law
-
Ronald Dworkin, The Arduous Virtue of Fidelity: Originalism, Scalia, Tribe, and Nerve, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1249, 1251-56 (1997); see also Ronald Dworkin, Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution (1996) [hereinafter Dworkin, Freedom's Law].
-
(1996)
Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
64
-
-
0346113645
-
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2092
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2092. In his paper for the conference, Moore does not indicate whether he believes that aspects of moral reality in addition to natural rights (for example, aspirations to a good society besides natural rights) are incorporated in the Constitution and, if so, whether they are judicially enforceable.
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
0041580141
-
-
supra note 47
-
Dworkin, Freedom's Law, supra note 47, at 34-35.
-
Freedom's Law
, pp. 34-35
-
-
Dworkin1
-
66
-
-
0348004966
-
-
Id. at 10-12
-
Id. at 10-12.
-
-
-
-
67
-
-
0347374595
-
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2093-98
-
Moore, supra note 1, at 2093-98.
-
-
-
-
68
-
-
18444364995
-
Fidelity as Integrity
-
hereinafter Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity
-
See Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1357, 1357 (1997) [hereinafter Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity] (quoting Ronald Dworkin's reply to criticism that he was too "wedded to text," advanced by Robin West, Integrity and Universality: A Comment on Ronald Dworkin's Freedom's Law, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1313 (1997)).
-
(1997)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.65
, pp. 1357
-
-
Colloquy1
-
69
-
-
0031496216
-
Integrity and Universality: A Comment on Ronald Dworkin's Freedom's Law
-
See Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1357, 1357 (1997) [hereinafter Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity] (quoting Ronald Dworkin's reply to criticism that he was too "wedded to text," advanced by Robin West, Integrity and Universality: A Comment on Ronald Dworkin's Freedom's Law, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1313 (1997)).
-
(1997)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.65
, pp. 1313
-
-
West, R.1
-
70
-
-
0346744237
-
-
supra note 52
-
Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity, supra note 52, at 1360-63 (quoting Dworkin's reply to criticism that he was "not sufficiently wedded to text," put forward by Michael W. McConnell, The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review: A Comment on Ronald Dworkin's "Moral Reading" of the Constitution, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1269 (1997)).
-
Fidelity as Integrity
, pp. 1360-1363
-
-
Colloquy1
-
71
-
-
21744451134
-
The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review: A Comment on Ronald Dworkin's "Moral Reading" of the Constitution
-
Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity, supra note 52, at 1360-63 (quoting Dworkin's reply to criticism that he was "not sufficiently wedded to text," put forward by Michael W. McConnell, The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review: A Comment on Ronald Dworkin's "Moral Reading" of the Constitution, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1269 (1997)).
-
(1997)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.65
, pp. 1269
-
-
McConnell, M.W.1
-
72
-
-
0031520717
-
Fidelity to Our Imperfect Constitution
-
hereinafter Fleming, Imperfect Constitution
-
James E. Fleming, Fidelity to Our Imperfect Constitution, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1335, 1349 (1997) [hereinafter Fleming, Imperfect Constitution] (distinguishing between Dworkin's theory of fidelity as integrity with the moral reading (which in theory is sufficiently constrained by concern for fit with legal materials) and Dworkin's own application of it (for he fails satisfactorily to do the fit work that his own theory calls for), and urging "[d]o as Dworkin says, not as he does").
-
(1997)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.65
, pp. 1335
-
-
Fleming, J.E.1
-
73
-
-
0348004969
-
-
supra note 34
-
See Sager, Thinness, supra note 34, at 410, 414-19.
-
Thinness
, pp. 410
-
-
Sager1
-
74
-
-
0346744238
-
-
Id. at 433-35
-
Id. at 433-35; Sager, Fair Measure, supra note 34, at 1221, 1263-64.
-
-
-
-
75
-
-
0348004964
-
-
supra note 34
-
Id. at 433-35; Sager, Fair Measure, supra note 34, at 1221, 1263-64.
-
Fair Measure
, pp. 1221
-
-
Sager1
-
77
-
-
0348004967
-
The Essential Constitution
-
Spring (on file with author) [hereinafter Michelman, The Storrs Lectures]
-
Frank I. Michelman, The Essential Constitution, The Storrs Lectures at Yale Law School (Spring 2000) (on file with author) [hereinafter Michelman, The Storrs Lectures]; Frank I. Michelman, Populist Natural Law (Reflections on Tushnet's "Thin Constitution"), 34 U. Rich. L. Rev. 461, 462-64 (2000).
-
(2000)
The Storrs Lectures at Yale Law School
-
-
Michelman, F.I.1
-
78
-
-
0347374570
-
Populist Natural Law (Reflections on Tushnet's "Thin Constitution")
-
Frank I. Michelman, The Essential Constitution, The Storrs Lectures at Yale Law School (Spring 2000) (on file with author) [hereinafter Michelman, The Storrs Lectures]; Frank I. Michelman, Populist Natural Law (Reflections on Tushnet's "Thin Constitution"), 34 U. Rich. L. Rev. 461, 462-64 (2000).
-
(2000)
U. Rich. L. Rev.
, vol.34
, pp. 461
-
-
Michelman, F.I.1
-
80
-
-
0347374550
-
-
note
-
On this point, I have benefited from conversations with Frank Michelman and Larry Sager.
-
-
-
-
81
-
-
0346744237
-
-
supra note 52
-
I believe that the term "happy endings" comes from Sandy Levinson. See Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity, supra note 52, at 1358 (question from Professor Levinson). For application of the term, see Dworkin, Freedom's Law, supra note 47, at 38; James E. Fleming, Constitutional Tragedy in Dying: Or Whose Tragedy Is It, Anyway?, in Constitutional Stupidities, Constitutional Tragedies 162, 163, 166-67 (William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Sanford Levinson eds., 1998) [hereinafter Fleming, Constitutional Tragedy]. In this section, I draw upon my analysis in the work just cited.
-
Fidelity as Integrity
, pp. 1358
-
-
Colloquy1
-
82
-
-
0041580141
-
-
supra note 47
-
I believe that the term "happy endings" comes from Sandy Levinson. See Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity, supra note 52, at 1358 (question from Professor Levinson). For application of the term, see Dworkin, Freedom's Law, supra note 47, at 38; James E. Fleming, Constitutional Tragedy in Dying: Or Whose Tragedy Is It, Anyway?, in Constitutional Stupidities, Constitutional Tragedies 162, 163, 166-67 (William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Sanford Levinson eds., 1998) [hereinafter Fleming, Constitutional Tragedy]. In this section, I draw upon my analysis in the work just cited.
-
Freedom's Law
, pp. 38
-
-
Dworkin1
-
83
-
-
0346744193
-
Constitutional Tragedy in Dying: Or Whose Tragedy Is It, Anyway?
-
William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Sanford Levinson eds., [hereinafter Fleming, Constitutional Tragedy]
-
I believe that the term "happy endings" comes from Sandy Levinson. See Colloquy, Fidelity as Integrity, supra note 52, at 1358 (question from Professor Levinson). For application of the term, see Dworkin, Freedom's Law, supra note 47, at 38; James E. Fleming, Constitutional Tragedy in Dying: Or Whose Tragedy Is It, Anyway?, in Constitutional Stupidities, Constitutional Tragedies 162, 163, 166-67 (William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Sanford Levinson eds., 1998) [hereinafter Fleming, Constitutional Tragedy]. In this section, I draw upon my analysis in the work just cited.
-
(1998)
Constitutional Stupidities, Constitutional Tragedies
, pp. 162
-
-
Fleming, J.E.1
-
84
-
-
0346591546
-
Our Perfect Constitution
-
See Henry P. Monaghan, Our Perfect Constitution, 56 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 353, 353-60 (1981).
-
(1981)
N.Y.U. L. Rev.
, vol.56
, pp. 353
-
-
Monaghan, H.P.1
-
86
-
-
21344498369
-
Justice and the Text: Rethinking the Constitutional Relation between Principle and Prudence
-
See Christopher L. Eisgruber, Justice and the Text: Rethinking the Constitutional Relation Between Principle and Prudence, 43 Duke L.J. 1, 7 (1993).
-
(1993)
Duke L.J.
, vol.43
, pp. 1
-
-
Eisgruber, C.L.1
-
88
-
-
84936068266
-
-
See Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire 365-68 (1986); Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle 146-66 (1985).
-
(1986)
Law's Empire
, pp. 365-368
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
89
-
-
0003981612
-
-
See Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire 365-68 (1986); Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle 146-66 (1985).
-
(1985)
A Matter of Principle
, pp. 146-166
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
90
-
-
0348004970
-
-
supra note 7
-
For the idea of a "Constitution-perfecting" theory, as distinguished from a "process-perfecting" theory, see Fleming, Constructing the Substantive Constitution, supra note 7, at 214-15. I mean "perfecting" in the sense of interpreting the Constitution with integrity so as to render it a coherent whole, not in Monaghan's caricatured sense of "Our Perfect Constitution" as creating a perfect liberal utopia or an "ideal object" of political morality. See Monaghan, supra note 62, at 354-60.
-
Constructing the Substantive Constitution
, pp. 214-215
-
-
Fleming1
-
91
-
-
0347374572
-
-
See Monaghan, supra note 62, at 354-60
-
For the idea of a "Constitution-perfecting" theory, as distinguished from a "process-perfecting" theory, see Fleming, Constructing the Substantive Constitution, supra note 7, at 214-15. I mean "perfecting" in the sense of interpreting the Constitution with integrity so as to render it a coherent whole, not in Monaghan's caricatured sense of "Our Perfect Constitution" as creating a perfect liberal utopia or an "ideal object" of political morality. See Monaghan, supra note 62, at 354-60.
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
0346744211
-
-
See Eisgruber, supra note 64, at 13
-
See Eisgruber, supra note 64, at 13.
-
-
-
|