메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 29, Issue 1, 2001, Pages 4-29

Hobbes, romance, and the contract of mimesis

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0035579256     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591701029001002     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (20)

References (65)
  • 1
    • 85037283551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Mates means overpowers; preoccupateth means anticipates, as in the case of suicide. In the following pages, I cite Leviathan from the edition by Richard Tuck (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991); chapter is indicated first, followed by page number.
  • 2
    • 0039074455 scopus 로고
    • Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, chap. 3
    • This is, of course, a simplification of an enormously complicated series of political negotiations. The annulment was desired not only by Frances but also by her powerful relatives, the Earl of Northampton and the Earl of Suffolk. See Vernon F. Snow, Essex the Rebel (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1970), chap. 3. Snow tells us that Essex owned a copy of "Amadis de Gaul, the bible of chivalry-conscious knights and nobles" (187).
    • (1970) Essex the Rebel
    • Snow, V.F.1
  • 3
    • 85037259322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I owe this information to Sears McGee of the University of California, Santa Barbara. Snow discusses the royalist lampooning of Essex (343) but does not mention this incident.
  • 4
    • 79958560266 scopus 로고
    • ed. Stephen Holmes Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Thomas Hobbes, Behemoth, ed. Stephen Holmes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 112.
    • (1990) Behemoth , pp. 112
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 5
    • 85037274404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As Hobbes remarked in Leviathan, glory "maketh men invade ... for trifles, as a word, a smile, a different opinion, and any other signe of undervalue, either direct in their Persons, or by reflexion in their Kindred, their Friends, their Nation, their Profession, or their Name" (13.88). Although the word Hobbes uses here is glory, the examples he gives suggest that it is identical with vainglory or self-love.
  • 7
    • 0005599614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, chap. 3
    • In addition to Lois Potter, Secret Rites and Secret Writing: Royalist Literature 1641-1660 (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989), chap. 3, see Ananbel Patterson, Censorship and Interpretation (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1984), chap. 4, and Kevin Sharpe, Criticism and Compliment: The Politics of Literature in the England of Charles I (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 95-96. For examples of the republican use of romance, see Nigel Smith, Literature and Revolution in England, 1640-1660 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1994), 246-49. Here seventeenth-century writers would have been influenced by the many reprintings of Sidney's Arcadia, which not only provided contemporaries with a gripping narrative of chivalric adventures but also kept the figure of Sidney, the exemplary Protestant poet and military hero, foremost in their minds.
    • (1989) Secret Rites and Secret Writing: Royalist Literature 1641-1660
    • Potter, L.1
  • 8
    • 0039074453 scopus 로고
    • Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, chap. 4
    • In addition to Lois Potter, Secret Rites and Secret Writing: Royalist Literature 1641-1660 (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989), chap. 3, see Ananbel Patterson, Censorship and Interpretation (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1984), chap. 4, and Kevin Sharpe, Criticism and Compliment: The Politics of Literature in the England of Charles I (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 95-96. For examples of the republican use of romance, see Nigel Smith, Literature and Revolution in England, 1640-1660 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1994), 246-49. Here seventeenth-century writers would have been influenced by the many reprintings of Sidney's Arcadia, which not only provided contemporaries with a gripping narrative of chivalric adventures but also kept the figure of Sidney, the exemplary Protestant poet and military hero, foremost in their minds.
    • (1984) Censorship and Interpretation
    • Patterson, A.1
  • 9
    • 0039823693 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • In addition to Lois Potter, Secret Rites and Secret Writing: Royalist Literature 1641-1660 (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989), chap. 3, see Ananbel Patterson, Censorship and Interpretation (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1984), chap. 4, and Kevin Sharpe, Criticism and Compliment: The Politics of Literature in the England of Charles I (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 95-96. For examples of the republican use of romance, see Nigel Smith, Literature and Revolution in England, 1640-1660 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1994), 246-49. Here seventeenth-century writers would have been influenced by the many reprintings of Sidney's Arcadia, which not only provided contemporaries with a gripping narrative of chivalric adventures but also kept the figure of Sidney, the exemplary Protestant poet and military hero, foremost in their minds.
    • (1987) Criticism and Compliment: The Politics of Literature in the England of Charles I , pp. 95-96
    • Sharpe, K.1
  • 10
    • 0005614858 scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • In addition to Lois Potter, Secret Rites and Secret Writing: Royalist Literature 1641-1660 (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989), chap. 3, see Ananbel Patterson, Censorship and Interpretation (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1984), chap. 4, and Kevin Sharpe, Criticism and Compliment: The Politics of Literature in the England of Charles I (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 95-96. For examples of the republican use of romance, see Nigel Smith, Literature and Revolution in England, 1640-1660 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1994), 246-49. Here seventeenth-century writers would have been influenced by the many reprintings of Sidney's Arcadia, which not only provided contemporaries with a gripping narrative of chivalric adventures but also kept the figure of Sidney, the exemplary Protestant poet and military hero, foremost in their minds.
    • (1994) Literature and Revolution in England, 1640-1660 , pp. 246-249
    • Smith, N.1
  • 11
    • 85037261668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Imitation is a complex term in this period. It serves as a translation of both Platonic and Aristotelian mimesis, but it also refers in the rhetorical tradition to an author's imitation of prior texts and the imitative response on the part of the readers.
  • 12
    • 0003575534 scopus 로고
    • Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, [1966]
    • See René Girard, Deceit, Desire, and the Novel (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, [1966] 1981) and Girard, Violence and the Sacred, trans. Patrick Gregory (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977), 143-68.
    • (1981) Deceit, Desire, and the Novel
    • Girard, R.1
  • 13
    • 0004272335 scopus 로고
    • trans. Patrick Gregory Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press
    • See René Girard, Deceit, Desire, and the Novel (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, [1966] 1981) and Girard, Violence and the Sacred, trans. Patrick Gregory (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977), 143-68.
    • (1977) Violence and the Sacred , pp. 143-168
    • Girard1
  • 15
    • 0007187488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: Chicago University Press, [1936]
    • This is one common reading of individuals such as Essex, whose behavior is not governed by the fear of violent death. On the centrality of the problem of vainglory in Hobbes's work, see, among others, Leo Strauss, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes (Chicago: Chicago University Press, [1936] 1963) and Keith Thomas, "The Social Origins of Hobbes's Political Thought," in Hobbes Studies, ed. K. C. Brown (Oxford, UK: Blackwell, 1965), 185-236.
    • (1963) The Political Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 16
    • 0007107951 scopus 로고
    • The social origins of Hobbes's political thought
    • ed. K. C. Brown Oxford, UK: Blackwell
    • This is one common reading of individuals such as Essex, whose behavior is not governed by the fear of violent death. On the centrality of the problem of vainglory in Hobbes's work, see, among others, Leo Strauss, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes (Chicago: Chicago University Press, [1936] 1963) and Keith Thomas, "The Social Origins of Hobbes's Political Thought," in Hobbes Studies, ed. K. C. Brown (Oxford, UK: Blackwell, 1965), 185-236.
    • (1965) Hobbes Studies , pp. 185-236
    • Thomas, K.1
  • 17
    • 0007187488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 18 and passim
    • See Strauss, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, 18 and passim. In The Passions and the Interests (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1977), Albert O. Hirschman elaborated Strauss's observations into a full-fledged account of the passions and interests in early modern political theory.
    • The Political Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Strauss1
  • 18
    • 0004127377 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • See Strauss, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, 18 and passim. In The Passions and the Interests (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1977), Albert O. Hirschman elaborated Strauss's observations into a full-fledged account of the passions and interests in early modern political theory.
    • (1977) The Passions and the Interests
  • 19
    • 0039547362 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press
    • David P. Gauthier, The Logic of Leviathan (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1969); Jean Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1986).
    • (1969) The Logic of Leviathan
    • Gauthier, D.P.1
  • 20
    • 0003649180 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • David P. Gauthier, The Logic of Leviathan (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1969); Jean Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1986).
    • (1986) Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 21
    • 0007250823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, my emphasis
    • The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 169, my emphasis. In the same volume, Richard Tuck cautions us that passion for Hobbes "is in part a matter of cognition: it involves beliefs about what sort of power we possess and what we can do with it" (184). Yet, because all men understand the claim of self-defense, "self-preservation was ... an extremely plausible candidate for a universal principle" (188), a plausible starting point for deducing the laws of nature. In short, men do not always fear violent death, they do not always act in rational accordance with the right of self-preservation, and they do not agree at any moment on what constitutes a threat of violent death - but they can recognize the value of acting as though they did. That is, although men are not always motivated by fear of violent death, they should be. For similar reasoning, see the essay in this volume by Alan Ryan (213, 225).
    • (1996) The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes , pp. 169
  • 22
    • 85037264244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or, in the case of Tuck, for the rational transcendence of skepticism (Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, 192-93).
    • Cambridge Companion to Hobbes , pp. 192-193
  • 26
    • 84930893533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 9
    • See The Elements of Law, chap. 9, for Hobbes's analysis of how love, "the great theme of poets," is often an expression of the desire to master others (56). In his Brief View and Survey of ... Leviathan (London, 1676), Clarendon criticized Hobbes for neglecting the importance of affection in generating political allegiance. Unlike Hobbes, kings have learned "that there is a great difference between the subjection that love and discretion paies, and that which results only from fear and force" (70).
    • The Elements of Law
  • 27
    • 0039086680 scopus 로고
    • London
    • See The Elements of Law, chap. 9, for Hobbes's analysis of how love, "the great theme of poets," is often an expression of the desire to master others (56). In his Brief View and Survey of ... Leviathan (London, 1676), Clarendon criticized Hobbes for neglecting the importance of affection in generating political allegiance. Unlike Hobbes, kings have learned "that there is a great difference between the subjection that love and discretion paies, and that which results only from fear and force" (70).
    • (1676) Brief View and Survey of ... Leviathan
  • 29
    • 0039873299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge Kegan Paul, 1096
    • On Hobbes's account of relation of thought to language, see Tom Sorell, Hobbes (London: Routledge Kegan Paul, 1096), 37-41 and chap. 4 on Hobbes's conventionalist account of knowledge and the nonconventionalist dimension of Hobbes's thought. See also George MacDonald Ross, "Hobbes's Two Theories of Meaning," in The Figural and the Literal, ed. Andrew E. Benjamin, Geoffrey N. Cantor, and John R. R. Christie (Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press, 1987), 31-57. Ross argues that in Leviathan, Hobbes presents a positivistic account of language according to which names arbitrarily designate mental images, as well as an "ordinary language theory" according to which meaning is established by common usage.
    • Hobbes , pp. 37-41
    • Sorell, T.1
  • 30
    • 0039074443 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes's two theories of meaning
    • ed. Andrew E. Benjamin, Geoffrey N. Cantor, and John R. R. Christie Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press
    • On Hobbes's account of relation of thought to language, see Tom Sorell, Hobbes (London: Routledge Kegan Paul, 1096), 37-41 and chap. 4 on Hobbes's conventionalist account of knowledge and the nonconventionalist dimension of Hobbes's thought. See also George MacDonald Ross, "Hobbes's Two Theories of Meaning," in The Figural and the Literal, ed. Andrew E. Benjamin, Geoffrey N. Cantor, and John R. R. Christie (Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press, 1987), 31-57. Ross argues that in Leviathan, Hobbes presents a positivistic account of language according to which names arbitrarily designate mental images, as well as an "ordinary language theory" according to which meaning is established by common usage.
    • (1987) The Figural and the Literal , pp. 31-57
    • MacDonald Ross, G.1
  • 31
    • 84855571894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See The Elements, 61, where Hobbes defines "the excellency of FANCY" as "finding unexpected similitudes in things," "from [whence] proceed those grateful similes, metaphors, and other tropes." By metaphorical thinking, I mean this reasoning by analogy or similitude.
    • The Elements , pp. 61
  • 32
    • 85037290634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thus, in the final chapter of Leviathan, Hobbes compares the papacy to "the Kingdome of Fayries": "The Faeries in what Nation soever they converse, have but one Universall King, which some Poets of ours call King Oberon; but the Scripture calls Beelzebub, Prince of Daemons. The Ecclesiastiques likewise, in whose dominion soever they be found, acknowledge but one Universall King, the Pope" (47.481).
  • 33
    • 85037273702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In chapter 13, Hobbes describes the state of nature as "this Inference, made from the passions" (89).
  • 34
    • 85037264495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Men believe themselves equally endowed "in the faculties of body, and mind," and "from this equality of ability, ariseth equality of hope in the attaining of our Ends. And therefore if any two men desire the same thing, which nevertheless they cannot both enjoy, they become enemies" (13.87). In a classic illustration of mediated desire, desiring the same object is not a simple function of scarcity but of the opinion of equality, and it is precisely this perception of one's likeness to another (this perception of shared desire) that gives rise to enmity. On the role of opinion in the state of nature, see Tuck, Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, 184-85, and David Johnston, The Rhetoric of Leviathan (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 77-78.
    • Cambridge Companion to Hobbes , pp. 184-185
    • Tuck1
  • 35
    • 0003736186 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Men believe themselves equally endowed "in the faculties of body, and mind," and "from this equality of ability, ariseth equality of hope in the attaining of our Ends. And therefore if any two men desire the same thing, which nevertheless they cannot both enjoy, they become enemies" (13.87). In a classic illustration of mediated desire, desiring the same object is not a simple function of scarcity but of the opinion of equality, and it is precisely this perception of one's likeness to another (this perception of shared desire) that gives rise to enmity. On the role of opinion in the state of nature, see Tuck, Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, 184-85, and David Johnston, The Rhetoric of Leviathan (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 77-78.
    • (1986) The Rhetoric of Leviathan , pp. 77-78
    • Johnston, D.1
  • 36
    • 85037262912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • On Hobbes's use of the term diffidence, Gert observes (without commenting on the implications of this observation for Hobbes's argument), "It may simply be that it is because Hobbes wanted to use the passion of fear as one of the 'passions that incline men to peace' (Lev. ch. 13, EW III, 116) that he decided to use a different word when he wanted a passion that led to war" (161).
  • 37
    • 85037264244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Strauss on Hobbes's belief that reason is impotent, whence the necessity of focusing on the motivating power of fear, but also on Hobbes' redefinition of fear itself as rational. See also Gert, Cambridge Companion to Hobbes: "All of the premises about human nature, which Hobbes claims are true of all persons and which he uses in arguing for the necessity of an unlimited sovereign, are in fact statements about the rationally required desires, and not, as most commentators have taken them, statements about the passions" (164). As I have been arguing, they are both - which is why Hobbes can use fear to get us out of the state of nature and also why this solution is vexed.
    • Cambridge Companion to Hobbes
    • Gert1
  • 38
    • 0003650067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • In Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996), Skinner argues that paradiastole is one of the central problems Hobbes wishes to address in his political philosophy but is not Hobbes's solution. Rather, rhetoric in Leviathan has the function of supplementing Hobbes's rational arguments and of ridiculing Hobbes's opponents. Yet an earlier version of his argument is much closer to the point I am making here. See "Thomas Hobbes: Rhetoric and the Construction of Morality," Proceedings of the British Academy 76 (1990): 1-61. After arguing that Hobbes thought it was impossible to gain general agreement about correct evaluative descriptions, whence the necessity of an absolute sovereign, Skinner comments, "The very core of [Hobbes's] argument, both in De Cive and in Leviathan, takes the form of an appeal to authority. Although Hobbes undoubtedly provides a solution to the problem of paradiastole, he appears to do so only at the expense of sacrificing his own scientific ideal" (56).
    • (1996) Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes
  • 39
    • 0039678846 scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hobbes: Rhetoric and the construction of morality
    • In Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996), Skinner argues that paradiastole is one of the central problems Hobbes wishes to address in his political philosophy but is not Hobbes's solution. Rather, rhetoric in Leviathan has the function of supplementing Hobbes's rational arguments and of ridiculing Hobbes's opponents. Yet an earlier version of his argument is much closer to the point I am making here. See "Thomas Hobbes: Rhetoric and the Construction of Morality," Proceedings of the British Academy 76 (1990): 1-61. After arguing that Hobbes thought it was impossible to gain general agreement about correct evaluative descriptions, whence the necessity of an absolute sovereign, Skinner comments, "The very core of [Hobbes's] argument, both in De Cive and in Leviathan, takes the form of an appeal to authority. Although Hobbes undoubtedly provides a solution to the problem of paradiastole, he appears to do so only at the expense of sacrificing his own scientific ideal" (56).
    • (1990) Proceedings of the British Academy , vol.76 , pp. 1-61
  • 40
    • 0004013746 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • Once we see Hobbes's argument about fear of violent death as part and parcel of an argument about romance and the imagination, books 3 and 4 of Leviathan appear as the logical extension of Hobbes's analysis in books 1 and 2. For the Church is, as we have seen, one of the chief promulgators of romance fictions. Because the goal of Leviathan is to set up a political authority about which one can say, "upon earth there is not his like" (Job 41:33, the epigraph to the frontispiece of Leviathan, emphasis added) - an authority that escapes the contagion of the imagination and of imitation - it becomes necessary to dismantle the temporal/spiritual distinction of powers that "makes men see double and mistake their lawful sovereign"; cited by S. A. Lloyd, Ideals as Interests in Hobbes's "Leviathan" (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 226.
    • (1992) Ideals as Interests in Hobbes's "Leviathan" , pp. 226
    • Lloyd, S.A.1
  • 41
    • 85037286654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Richard Tuck and Michael Silverthorne Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, chap. 17, section 28
    • Hobbes, On the Citizen, ed. Richard Tuck and Michael Silverthorne (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998), chap. 17, section 28, p. 232.
    • (1998) On the Citizen , pp. 232
    • Hobbes1
  • 42
    • 85037276099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See also the chart of the several kinds of knowledge in chapter 9 of Leviathan, where Hobbes derives "the Science of JUST and UNJUST" from "Contracting," which is in turn one of the "Consequences of Speech" (61).
  • 43
    • 85037276028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See also Leviathan: "But the most noble and profitable invention of all other, was that of SPEECH, consisting of Names or Appellations, and their Connexion ... without which, there had been amongst men, neither Common-wealth, nor Society, nor Contract, nor Peace" (4.23). See also Sorell, 39, on fixed similitudes in Hobbes.
  • 44
    • 0040941265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The locus classicus in the Renaissance is Pico's Oration on the Dignity of Man. See also Sidney's Defence of Poesy, in which the poet is described as a "maker." In his treatise On the Sublime, Longinus quotes God's creative "fiat" as an example of sublime discourse. Note also how Hobbes's comparison of the establishment of the commonwealth to the divine "fiat" complicates his argument about contract, for God is not a party to a contract when he creates the world; he is instead an absolute sovereign. This may be an example (and there are others, as many critics have noted) of the way in which something such as sovereign power - including the sovereign power to define and constrain our interpretation of our passions - is a precondition of the contract of government that is itself a precondition of sovereign power.
    • Oration on the Dignity of Man
    • Pico1
  • 45
    • 0039074452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The locus classicus in the Renaissance is Pico's Oration on the Dignity of Man. See also Sidney's Defence of Poesy, in which the poet is described as a "maker." In his treatise On the Sublime, Longinus quotes God's creative "fiat" as an example of sublime discourse. Note also how Hobbes's comparison of the establishment of the commonwealth to the divine "fiat" complicates his argument about contract, for God is not a party to a contract when he creates the world; he is instead an absolute sovereign. This may be an example (and there are others, as many critics have noted) of the way in which something such as sovereign power - including the sovereign power to define and constrain our interpretation of our passions - is a precondition of the contract of government that is itself a precondition of sovereign power.
    • Defence of Poesy
    • Sidney1
  • 46
    • 0039296908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The locus classicus in the Renaissance is Pico's Oration on the Dignity of Man. See also Sidney's Defence of Poesy, in which the poet is described as a "maker." In his treatise On the Sublime, Longinus quotes God's creative "fiat" as an example of sublime discourse. Note also how Hobbes's comparison of the establishment of the commonwealth to the divine "fiat" complicates his argument about contract, for God is not a party to a contract when he creates the world; he is instead an absolute sovereign. This may be an example (and there are others, as many critics have noted) of the way in which something such as sovereign power - including the sovereign power to define and constrain our interpretation of our passions - is a precondition of the contract of government that is itself a precondition of sovereign power.
    • On the Sublime
  • 47
    • 0040258228 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • See Leviathan: "The light of humane minds is Perspicuous Words, but by exact definitions first snuffed, and purged from ambiguity; Reason is the pace; Encrease of Science, the way; and the Benefit of man-kind, the end. And on the contrary, Metaphors, and senslesse and ambiguous words, are like ignes fatui; and reasoning upon them, is wandering amongst innumerable absurdities; and their end, contention, and sedition, or contempt" (5.36). As we saw in Hobbes's discussion of compound imagination, in the Renaissance, metaphor was frequently conceived of as a deviation or wandering from the literal sense and thus an example in the realm of figuration of the kind of wandering or error Renaissance commentators regularly associated with the genre of romance. On romance error, see Patricia Parker, Inescapable Romance (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); on the romance plot of metaphor, see Parker, "The Metaphorical Plot," in Literary Fat Ladies (New York: Routledge Kegan Paul, 1987), and Terence Cave, Recognitions: A Study in Poetics (Oxford, UK: Clarendon, 1988). Cave does not limit his study of the plot of metaphor to romance, although the Odyssey and later romances figure prominently in his discussion.
    • (1979) Inescapable Romance
    • Parker, P.1
  • 48
    • 0039074449 scopus 로고
    • The metaphorical plot
    • New York: Routledge Kegan Paul
    • See Leviathan: "The light of humane minds is Perspicuous Words, but by exact definitions first snuffed, and purged from ambiguity; Reason is the pace; Encrease of Science, the way; and the Benefit of man-kind, the end. And on the contrary, Metaphors, and senslesse and ambiguous words, are like ignes fatui; and reasoning upon them, is wandering amongst innumerable absurdities; and their end, contention, and sedition, or contempt" (5.36). As we saw in Hobbes's discussion of compound imagination, in the Renaissance, metaphor was frequently conceived of as a deviation or wandering from the literal sense and thus an example in the realm of figuration of the kind of wandering or error Renaissance commentators regularly associated with the genre of romance. On romance error, see Patricia Parker, Inescapable Romance (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); on the romance plot of metaphor, see Parker, "The Metaphorical Plot," in Literary Fat Ladies (New York: Routledge Kegan Paul, 1987), and Terence Cave, Recognitions: A Study in Poetics (Oxford, UK: Clarendon, 1988). Cave does not limit his study of the plot of metaphor to romance, although the Odyssey and later romances figure prominently in his discussion.
    • (1987) Literary Fat Ladies
    • Parker1
  • 49
    • 0038634832 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Clarendon
    • See Leviathan: "The light of humane minds is Perspicuous Words, but by exact definitions first snuffed, and purged from ambiguity; Reason is the pace; Encrease of Science, the way; and the Benefit of man-kind, the end. And on the contrary, Metaphors, and senslesse and ambiguous words, are like ignes fatui; and reasoning upon them, is wandering amongst innumerable absurdities; and their end, contention, and sedition, or contempt" (5.36). As we saw in Hobbes's discussion of compound imagination, in the Renaissance, metaphor was frequently conceived of as a deviation or wandering from the literal sense and thus an example in the realm of figuration of the kind of wandering or error Renaissance commentators regularly associated with the genre of romance. On romance error, see Patricia Parker, Inescapable Romance (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); on the romance plot of metaphor, see Parker, "The Metaphorical Plot," in Literary Fat Ladies (New York: Routledge Kegan Paul, 1987), and Terence Cave, Recognitions: A Study in Poetics (Oxford, UK: Clarendon, 1988). Cave does not limit his study of the plot of metaphor to romance, although the Odyssey and later romances figure prominently in his discussion.
    • (1988) Recognitions: A Study in Poetics
    • Cave, T.1
  • 50
    • 0004252914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toronto: University of Toronto Press
    • See Paul Ricoeur, The Rule of Metaphor (Toronto: University of Toronto Press), 198, citing Aristotle's Poetics 1410b, 1459a: "The same operation that lets us 'see the similar' also 'conveys learning and knowledge through the medium of the genus.' ... But if it is true that one learns what one does not yet know, then to make the similar visible is to produce the genus within the differences, and not elevated beyond differences, in the transcendence of the concept." See also the discussion of Ricoeur and Aristotle on the productive power of metaphor in Joel Altman, "'Preposterous Conclusions': Eros, Enargeia, and the Composition of Othello," Representations 18 (1987): 137.
    • The Rule of Metaphor , pp. 198
    • Ricoeur, P.1
  • 51
    • 0039074438 scopus 로고
    • 'Preposterous conclusions': Eros, enargeia, and the composition of Othello
    • See Paul Ricoeur, The Rule of Metaphor (Toronto: University of Toronto Press), 198, citing Aristotle's Poetics 1410b, 1459a: "The same operation that lets us 'see the similar' also 'conveys learning and knowledge through the medium of the genus.' ... But if it is true that one learns what one does not yet know, then to make the similar visible is to produce the genus within the differences, and not elevated beyond differences, in the transcendence of the concept." See also the discussion of Ricoeur and Aristotle on the productive power of metaphor in Joel Altman, "'Preposterous Conclusions': Eros, Enargeia, and the Composition of Othello," Representations 18 (1987): 137.
    • (1987) Representations , vol.18 , pp. 137
    • Altman, J.1
  • 53
    • 0346586428 scopus 로고
    • Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • This argument could even be made on the level of syntax. In his introduction to The Rhetorics of Thomas Hobbes and Bernard Lamy (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986), John T. Harwood suggests that Hobbes's use of parataxis and asyndeton - for example, "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short" - creates the impression of a dangerous, contingent world on the level of sentence - a syntactical state of nature (28). Hobbes thus replicates on the level of syntax the paratactic plot structure of much prose romance.
    • (1986) The Rhetorics of Thomas Hobbes and Bernard Lamy
  • 54
    • 0039666470 scopus 로고
    • ed. R. J. Schoek Ontario: Dent
    • There were precedents for this greater emphasis on contingency and political machinations in popular prose romances of the late sixteenth and earlier seventeenth centuries. In sixteenth-century England, Italian romance in particular symbolized the potentially dangerous connection between romance and artful deception and between the imitation of the passions and rhetorical technique, which was negatively associated with the pursuit of self-interest. This self-interest could take an erotic or political form or sometimes both. Hence the Elizabethan scholar Roger Ascham's warning against "bawdie books ... translated out of the Italian tongue." Ascham implied that the reading of romances gives rise to faithlessness in love, and he went on to observe that the rhetorical manipulation of the passions "in Circes court" is closely linked to the pursuit of self-interest and faction at the royal court. Romance, Ascham suggests, does not simply represent the old world of aristocratic relations but the new world of the Italianate rhetorician: the arriviste, the pretender, the seducer, and the fraud. See Ascham, The Scholemaster, ed. R. J. Schoek (Ontario: Dent, 1966), 67, 72. In The Political Unconscious (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1981), Fredric Jameson described romance as a kind of magical narrative, one that involves a simplified, polarized world of good and evil. For Jameson, Nietzsche is the philosopher who helps us see that this ethical opposition is itself ideologically motivated, a romantic veiling of more fundamental relationships of power. And tragedy for Jameson is the genre that troubles or exceeds the romance habit of moral dichotomizing, the genre that "rebuke[s] the ideological core of the romance paradigm" (115-16). In contrast to Jameson, prose romance of the late sixteenth and seventeenth centuries often performs its own Nietzschean critique of ethical values, which is one of the reasons Ascham associated Italian prose romance with Machiavellian conniving (see The Scholemaster). Hobbes's own derivation of ethics from interests in chapter 9 of Leviathan conforms to this impulse. See the chart on p. 149 in which "Ethiques" is derived from "the passions of Men."
    • (1966) The Scholemaster , pp. 67
    • Ascham1
  • 55
    • 0004241282 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • There were precedents for this greater emphasis on contingency and political machinations in popular prose romances of the late sixteenth and earlier seventeenth centuries. In sixteenth-century England, Italian romance in particular symbolized the potentially dangerous connection between romance and artful deception and between the imitation of the passions and rhetorical technique, which was negatively associated with the pursuit of self-interest. This self-interest could take an erotic or political form or sometimes both. Hence the Elizabethan scholar Roger Ascham's warning against "bawdie books ... translated out of the Italian tongue." Ascham implied that the reading of romances gives rise to faithlessness in love, and he went on to observe that the rhetorical manipulation of the passions "in Circes court" is closely linked to the pursuit of self-interest and faction at the royal court. Romance, Ascham suggests, does not simply represent the old world of aristocratic relations but the new world of the Italianate rhetorician: the arriviste, the pretender, the seducer, and the fraud. See Ascham, The Scholemaster, ed. R. J. Schoek (Ontario: Dent, 1966), 67, 72. In The Political Unconscious (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1981), Fredric Jameson described romance as a kind of magical narrative, one that involves a simplified, polarized world of good and evil. For Jameson, Nietzsche is the philosopher who helps us see that this ethical opposition is itself ideologically motivated, a romantic veiling of more fundamental relationships of power. And tragedy for Jameson is the genre that troubles or exceeds the romance habit of moral dichotomizing, the genre that "rebuke[s] the ideological core of the romance paradigm" (115-16). In contrast to Jameson, prose romance of the late sixteenth and seventeenth centuries often performs its own Nietzschean critique of ethical values, which is one of the reasons Ascham associated Italian prose romance with Machiavellian conniving (see The Scholemaster). Hobbes's own derivation of ethics from interests in chapter 9 of Leviathan conforms to this impulse. See the chart on p. 149 in which "Ethiques" is derived from "the passions of Men."
    • (1981) The Political Unconscious
  • 56
    • 60949156210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There were precedents for this greater emphasis on contingency and political machinations in popular prose romances of the late sixteenth and earlier seventeenth centuries. In sixteenth-century England, Italian romance in particular symbolized the potentially dangerous connection between romance and artful deception and between the imitation of the passions and rhetorical technique, which was negatively associated with the pursuit of self-interest. This self-interest could take an erotic or political form or sometimes both. Hence the Elizabethan scholar Roger Ascham's warning against "bawdie books ... translated out of the Italian tongue." Ascham implied that the reading of romances gives rise to faithlessness in love, and he went on to observe that the rhetorical manipulation of the passions "in Circes court" is closely linked to the pursuit of self-interest and faction at the royal court. Romance, Ascham suggests, does not simply represent the old world of aristocratic relations but the new world of the Italianate rhetorician: the arriviste, the pretender, the seducer, and the fraud. See Ascham, The Scholemaster, ed. R. J. Schoek (Ontario: Dent, 1966), 67, 72. In The Political Unconscious (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1981), Fredric Jameson described romance as a kind of magical narrative, one that involves a simplified, polarized world of good and evil. For Jameson, Nietzsche is the philosopher who helps us see that this ethical opposition is itself ideologically motivated, a romantic veiling of more fundamental relationships of power. And tragedy for Jameson is the genre that troubles or exceeds the romance habit of moral dichotomizing, the genre that "rebuke[s] the ideological core of the romance paradigm" (115-16). In contrast to Jameson, prose romance of the late sixteenth and seventeenth centuries often performs its own Nietzschean critique of ethical values, which is one of the reasons Ascham associated Italian prose romance with Machiavellian conniving (see The Scholemaster). Hobbes's own derivation of ethics from interests in chapter 9 of Leviathan conforms to this impulse. See the chart on p. 149 in which "Ethiques" is derived from "the passions of Men."
    • The Scholemaster
  • 57
    • 84922892169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbes himself seems at times to have felt that Leviathan was a philosophical fantasy or fiction. At the end of book 2 of Leviathan, he wrote that he was "at the point of believing this my labour, as uselesse, as the Common-wealth of Plato; for he also is of opinion that it is impossible for the disorders of State, and change of Governments by Civill Warre, ever to be taken away, till Soveraigns be Philosophers" (31.254). And Filmer seconded this view in a sarcastic vein when, in The Anarchy of a Limited or Mixed Monarchy, he criticized Hobbes's "platonic monarchy": "The book hath so much of fancy that it is a better piece of poetry than policy"; Robert Filmer, Patriarcha and Other Writings, ed. Johann Sommerville (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
    • The Anarchy of a Limited or Mixed Monarchy
  • 58
    • 0040852654 scopus 로고
    • ed. Johann Sommerville Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • Hobbes himself seems at times to have felt that Leviathan was a philosophical fantasy or fiction. At the end of book 2 of Leviathan, he wrote that he was "at the point of believing this my labour, as uselesse, as the Common-wealth of Plato; for he also is of opinion that it is impossible for the disorders of State, and change of Governments by Civill Warre, ever to be taken away, till Soveraigns be Philosophers" (31.254). And Filmer seconded this view in a sarcastic vein when, in The Anarchy of a Limited or Mixed Monarchy, he criticized Hobbes's "platonic monarchy": "The book hath so much of fancy that it is a better piece of poetry than policy"; Robert Filmer, Patriarcha and Other Writings, ed. Johann Sommerville (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
    • (1991) Patriarcha and Other Writings
    • Filmer, R.1
  • 59
    • 84855571894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Terence Cave has argued in his study, Recognitions, the recognition (in romance, in particular) often turns on what Aristotle in the Rhetoric called inartistic signs, on paralogism or faulty inference. It is striking in this context that Hobbes explicitly conceives of his "know thyself as a remedy for faulty inference. In The Elements, he writes: "Now, if we consider the power of those deceptions of sense ... and also how inconstantly names have been settled, and how subject they are to equivocation, and how diversified by passion ... I may in a manner conclude, [that] nosce te ipsum [is] a precept worthy the reputation it hath gotten" (39).
    • The Elements
  • 60
    • 84855571894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It may be for that reason that in The Elements, Hobbes echoes the contemporary language of marriage contracts. He insists that when political right is transferred, it must be not only de futuro but also de praesenti (83). De praesenti vows referred to marriage vows that were binding in the present; de futuro vows were vows of betrothal, binding the couple to marry at some future time. See Henry Swinburne, A Treatise of Spousals (London, 1686). On the gender dimension of Hobbes's argument, see also Strauss, Political Philosophy of Hobbes, and Stephen Holmes, Passions and Constraint (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995). Strauss argues that Hobbes, like Plato, criticizes traditional equations of manliness with military valor. Holmes mentions Hobbes's appreciation of the Church's "unmanning" of subjects by inculcating Christian meekness (96). On the effeminacy of the Hobbesian subject, see also Harvey C. Mansfield, "Virilité et libéralisme," Archives de philosophie du droit 41 (1997): 25-42. On the female fear for one's reputation (for chastity), see the example of the Greek maidens discussed above in section III.
    • The Elements
  • 61
    • 0040258222 scopus 로고
    • London
    • It may be for that reason that in The Elements, Hobbes echoes the contemporary language of marriage contracts. He insists that when political right is transferred, it must be not only de futuro but also de praesenti (83). De praesenti vows referred to marriage vows that were binding in the present; de futuro vows were vows of betrothal, binding the couple to marry at some future time. See Henry Swinburne, A Treatise of Spousals (London, 1686). On the gender dimension of Hobbes's argument, see also Strauss, Political Philosophy of Hobbes, and Stephen Holmes, Passions and Constraint (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995). Strauss argues that Hobbes, like Plato, criticizes traditional equations of manliness with military valor. Holmes mentions Hobbes's appreciation of the Church's "unmanning" of subjects by inculcating Christian meekness (96). On the effeminacy of the Hobbesian subject, see also Harvey C. Mansfield, "Virilité et libéralisme," Archives de philosophie du droit 41 (1997): 25-42. On the female fear for one's reputation (for chastity), see the example of the Greek maidens discussed above in section III.
    • (1686) A Treatise of Spousals
    • Swinburne, H.1
  • 62
    • 0007187488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It may be for that reason that in The Elements, Hobbes echoes the contemporary language of marriage contracts. He insists that when political right is transferred, it must be not only de futuro but also de praesenti (83). De praesenti vows referred to marriage vows that were binding in the present; de futuro vows were vows of betrothal, binding the couple to marry at some future time. See Henry Swinburne, A Treatise of Spousals (London, 1686). On the gender dimension of Hobbes's argument, see also Strauss, Political Philosophy of Hobbes, and Stephen Holmes, Passions and Constraint (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995). Strauss argues that Hobbes, like Plato, criticizes traditional equations of manliness with military valor. Holmes mentions Hobbes's appreciation of the Church's "unmanning" of subjects by inculcating Christian meekness (96). On the effeminacy of the Hobbesian subject, see also Harvey C. Mansfield, "Virilité et libéralisme," Archives de philosophie du droit 41 (1997): 25-42. On the female fear for one's reputation (for chastity), see the example of the Greek maidens discussed above in section III.
    • Political Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Strauss1
  • 63
    • 0004308019 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • It may be for that reason that in The Elements, Hobbes echoes the contemporary language of marriage contracts. He insists that when political right is transferred, it must be not only de futuro but also de praesenti (83). De praesenti vows referred to marriage vows that were binding in the present; de futuro vows were vows of betrothal, binding the couple to marry at some future time. See Henry Swinburne, A Treatise of Spousals (London, 1686). On the gender dimension of Hobbes's argument, see also Strauss, Political Philosophy of Hobbes, and Stephen Holmes, Passions and Constraint (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995). Strauss argues that Hobbes, like Plato, criticizes traditional equations of manliness with military valor. Holmes mentions Hobbes's appreciation of the Church's "unmanning" of subjects by inculcating Christian meekness (96). On the effeminacy of the Hobbesian subject, see also Harvey C. Mansfield, "Virilité et libéralisme," Archives de philosophie du droit 41 (1997): 25-42. On the female fear for one's reputation (for chastity), see the example of the Greek maidens discussed above in section III.
    • (1995) Passions and Constraint
    • Holmes, S.1
  • 64
    • 0040258216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virilité et libéralisme
    • It may be for that reason that in The Elements, Hobbes echoes the contemporary language of marriage contracts. He insists that when political right is transferred, it must be not only de futuro but also de praesenti (83). De praesenti vows referred to marriage vows that were binding in the present; de futuro vows were vows of betrothal, binding the couple to marry at some future time. See Henry Swinburne, A Treatise of Spousals (London, 1686). On the gender dimension of Hobbes's argument, see also Strauss, Political Philosophy of Hobbes, and Stephen Holmes, Passions and Constraint (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995). Strauss argues that Hobbes, like Plato, criticizes traditional equations of manliness with military valor. Holmes mentions Hobbes's appreciation of the Church's "unmanning" of subjects by inculcating Christian meekness (96). On the effeminacy of the Hobbesian subject, see also Harvey C. Mansfield, "Virilité et libéralisme," Archives de philosophie du droit 41 (1997): 25-42. On the female fear for one's reputation (for chastity), see the example of the Greek maidens discussed above in section III.
    • (1997) Archives de Philosophie du Droit , vol.41 , pp. 25-42
    • Mansfield, H.C.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.