메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 29, Issue 6, 2001, Pages 806-832

Oakeshott's Hobbes and the fear of political rationalism

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0035540181     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591701029006005     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (7)

References (120)
  • 3
    • 0003555163 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press
    • See, for example, Barry's defense of impartiality in Brian Barry, Justice As Impartiality (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1995).
    • (1995) Justice as Impartiality
    • Barry, B.1
  • 4
    • 0003687286 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • William Connolly, The Terms of Political Discourse, 2d ed. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1983); Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
    • (1983) The Terms of Political Discourse, 2d Ed.
    • Connolly, W.1
  • 5
    • 0003967815 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • William Connolly, The Terms of Political Discourse, 2d ed. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1983); Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
    • (1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 6
    • 0004076633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Viertel Boston: Beacon
    • Jürgen Habermas, Theory and Practice, trans. John Viertel (Boston: Beacon, 1971).
    • (1971) Theory and Practice
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 7
    • 0003210325 scopus 로고
    • Political theory as a vocation
    • ed. Martin Fleisher New York: Atheneum
    • Sheldon Wolin, "Political Theory As a Vocation," Machiavelli and the Nature of Political Thought, ed. Martin Fleisher (New York: Atheneum, 1972).
    • (1972) Machiavelli and the Nature of Political Thought
    • Wolin, S.1
  • 8
    • 0007312667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • December
    • Most recently, the controversy started with the "Mr. Perestroika" e-mail. See PS: Political Science & Politics 4 (December 2000): 735-41.
    • (2000) PS: Political Science & Politics , vol.4 , pp. 735-741
  • 9
    • 0004163409 scopus 로고
    • Boston: Beacon
    • See, for example, Marcuse's observations on the status of philosophy and social science in Herbert Marcuse, One Dimensional Man (Boston: Beacon, 1964).
    • (1964) One Dimensional Man
    • Marcuse, H.1
  • 10
    • 0003877679 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Hubert Dreyfus is a key proponent of this reading of Heidegger and of those Heideggerian-influenced thinkers such as Foucault. See Hubert Dreyfus, Michel Foucault, beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983). Jacques Derrida's work, particularly the earlier works and his own critique of Foucault, are illustrative of the efforts to resist lapses into metaphysics. See, notably, Jacques Derrida, "Cogito and the History of Madness" in Jacques Derrida, Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978).
    • (1983) Michel Foucault, Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2d Ed.
    • Dreyfus, H.1
  • 11
    • 0002647840 scopus 로고
    • Cogito and the history of madness
    • Jacques Derrida, Alan Bass Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Hubert Dreyfus is a key proponent of this reading of Heidegger and of those Heideggerian-influenced thinkers such as Foucault. See Hubert Dreyfus, Michel Foucault, beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983). Jacques Derrida's work, particularly the earlier works and his own critique of Foucault, are illustrative of the efforts to resist lapses into metaphysics. See, notably, Jacques Derrida, "Cogito and the History of Madness" in Jacques Derrida, Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978).
    • (1978) Writing and Difference
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 13
    • 85037400914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction to Leviathan
    • hereafter, "Introduction" reprinted in Oakeshott
    • Michael Oakeshott, "Introduction to Leviathan," [hereafter, "Introduction"] reprinted in Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, 240. Oakeshott here quotes J. S. Mill's Autobiography, but more proximal sources for this claim included Ferdinand Tönnies, Thomas Hobbes: Leben und Lehre (Stuttgart, Germany: Friedrich Frommanns Verlag, E. Hauff, 1896);
    • Rationalism in Politics , pp. 240
    • Oakeshott, M.1
  • 14
    • 0007253690 scopus 로고
    • J. S. Mill's autobiography
    • Ferdinand Tönnies, Stuttgart, Germany: Friedrich Frommanns Verlag, E. Hauff
    • Michael Oakeshott, "Introduction to Leviathan," [hereafter, "Introduction"] reprinted in Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, 240. Oakeshott here quotes J. S. Mill's Autobiography, but more proximal sources for this claim included Ferdinand Tönnies, Thomas Hobbes: Leben und Lehre (Stuttgart, Germany: Friedrich Frommanns Verlag, E. Hauff, 1896);
    • (1896) Thomas Hobbes: Leben und Lehre
    • Oakeshott1
  • 16
    • 0007312765 scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hobbes
    • see Michael Oakeshott, "Thomas Hobbes," Scrutiny, 4 (1935-36): 263-77. Leo Strauss also wishes to distance Hobbes the moral philosopher from Hobbes the social scientist, but he allows for greater affinities between Hobbes and social scientific techniques.
    • (1935) Scrutiny , vol.4 , pp. 263-277
    • Oakeshott, M.1
  • 18
    • 84873576001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rationalism in politics
    • Michael Oakeshott
    • Michael Oakeshott, "Rationalism in Politics" in Michael Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, esp. 31; Michael Oakeshott, "Political Education," in ibid., 54.
    • Rationalism in Politics , pp. 31
    • Oakeshott, M.1
  • 19
    • 0010948125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political education
    • Michael Oakeshott, "Rationalism in Politics" in Michael Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, esp. 31; Michael Oakeshott, "Political Education," in ibid., 54.
    • Rationalism in Politics , pp. 54
    • Oakeshott, M.1
  • 20
    • 85037388538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "Introduction," 235-39. Thus, Hobbes's enthusiasm for Kepler, Galileo, and Harvey should not outweigh his antipathy toward the Royal Society. When we see "what Hobbes was about" we realize that this confusion, this "internal tension" in his thought arose from an attempted but imperfectly achieved distinction between science and philosophy. The distinction, well known to us now, is that between knowledge of things as they appear and enquiry into the fact of their appearing, between a knowledge (with all the necessary assumptions) of the phenomenal world and a theory of knowledge itself . . . his concern as a philosopher was with the second and not the first. (Ibid., 239)
  • 21
    • 85037387167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 236
    • Ibid., 236.
  • 22
    • 85037397290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 236-37
    • Ibid., 236-37.
  • 23
    • 85037380749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 236
    • Ibid., 236.
  • 24
    • 84953649781 scopus 로고
    • Philip P. Wiener Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Pierre Duhem, The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, trans. Philip P. Wiener (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1954).
    • (1954) The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory
    • Duhem, P.1
  • 25
    • 85037391767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "Introduction," 227-28, 233, 276-78, 280. The important distinction for Oakeshott is that Hobbes is a part of - indeed the fruition of - a break from an earlier tradition of "Reason and Nature," which rooted obedience in natural law, and natural law in the obligatory force of reason's dictates.
  • 26
    • 85037394832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 236
    • Ibid., 236.
  • 27
    • 85037401160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 246-47
    • Ibid., 246-47.
  • 28
    • 85037383433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 244
    • Ibid., 244.
  • 29
    • 85037391903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 244-45
    • Ibid., 244-45.
  • 30
    • 85037380574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is also, notably, a part of an argument that stresses a picture of the individual that stresses willfulness over reason, but I will not be addressing this part of Oakeshott's interpretation here. See, for example, ibid., 280.
  • 31
    • 85037391294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 242
    • Ibid., 242.
  • 32
    • 85037395052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 243
    • Ibid., 243.
  • 33
    • 84973223855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. I, chap. 3, sections 1-2
    • Thomas Hobbes, De Corpore, bk. I, chap. 3, sections 1-2, 7, Opera Philosophica (vol. 2), ed. Sir William Molesworth (London: John Bohn, 1839) [hereafter, De Corpore, book, chapter, section]. See also Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, chap. 4, sections 11-12, ed. Edwin Curley (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1994) [hereafter, Leviathan, chapter, section]; Thomas Hobbes, Elements of Law, bk. I, chap. 5, section 10, ed. Ferdinand Tönnies (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1889).
    • De Corpore , pp. 7
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 34
    • 0007177632 scopus 로고
    • London: John Bohn, hereafter, De Corpore, book, chapter, section
    • Thomas Hobbes, De Corpore, bk. I, chap. 3, sections 1-2, 7, Opera Philosophica (vol. 2), ed. Sir William Molesworth (London: John Bohn, 1839) [hereafter, De Corpore, book, chapter, section]. See also Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, chap. 4, sections 11-12, ed. Edwin Curley (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1994) [hereafter, Leviathan, chapter, section]; Thomas Hobbes, Elements of Law, bk. I, chap. 5, section 10, ed. Ferdinand Tönnies (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1889).
    • (1839) Opera Philosophica , vol.2
    • Molesworth, S.W.1
  • 35
    • 85037385963 scopus 로고
    • chap. 4, sections 11-12, ed. Edwin Curley Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, hereafter, Leviathan, chapter, section
    • Thomas Hobbes, De Corpore, bk. I, chap. 3, sections 1-2, 7, Opera Philosophica (vol. 2), ed. Sir William Molesworth (London: John Bohn, 1839) [hereafter, De Corpore, book, chapter, section]. See also Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, chap. 4, sections 11-12, ed. Edwin Curley (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1994) [hereafter, Leviathan, chapter, section]; Thomas Hobbes, Elements of Law, bk. I, chap. 5, section 10, ed. Ferdinand Tönnies (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1889).
    • (1994) Leviathan
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 36
    • 85037392056 scopus 로고
    • bk. I, chap. 5, section 10, ed. Ferdinand Tönnies Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • Thomas Hobbes, De Corpore, bk. I, chap. 3, sections 1-2, 7, Opera Philosophica (vol. 2), ed. Sir William Molesworth (London: John Bohn, 1839) [hereafter, De Corpore, book, chapter, section]. See also Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, chap. 4, sections 11-12, ed. Edwin Curley (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1994) [hereafter, Leviathan, chapter, section]; Thomas Hobbes, Elements of Law, bk. I, chap. 5, section 10, ed. Ferdinand Tönnies (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1889).
    • (1889) Elements of Law
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 37
    • 85037395904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In De Corpore, I, 3, 10, he writes, "truth adheres not to things, but to speech only, for some truths are eternal; for it will be eternally true, if man, then living creature; but that any man, or living creature, should exist eternally, is not necessary." This assertion is explained by the fact that Hobbes defines "living creature" as one of the accidents that are necessary to "man"; in his terminology, a cause of man. Thus, it is true that "man" entails the notion of "living creature," but it could be that men, and all living creatures, will one day be gone. Nonetheless, the formal truth that "man" is a "living creature" will nonetheless remain true. In Leviathan, 4, 11, Hobbes writes, "For True and False are attributes of Speech, not of Things. And where Speech is not, there is neither Truth nor Falsehood."
  • 38
    • 85037400758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reprinted in Oakeshott, Rationalism and Politics
    • Reprinted in Oakeshott, Rationalism and Politics.
  • 43
    • 0010925754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rational conduct
    • reprinted in Oakeshott
    • Michael Oakeshott, "Rational Conduct," reprinted in Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, esp. 102-15.
    • Rationalism in Politics , pp. 102-115
    • Oakeshott, M.1
  • 45
    • 85037395844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., 27. Oakeshott makes this point in the context of a more specific critique of "the politics of the book." Here, one imagines that he is not merely speaking of political rationalism generally but the political rationalist ideologies that generated books. None too specific, Oakeshott may be thinking of manuals such as Mao's little red book. In any case, this argument is an extension of his more general point about the inherent inadequacies of technique in the realm of politics.
  • 46
    • 85037382023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Gerencer, The Skeptic's Oakeshott. Other instances of "strong readings" - and perhaps it is no accident that strong readings are often Hobbes interpretations - include Wolin's "epic theorist" interpretation of Hobbes, at once an explanation for strong reading and a strong reading in itself. Sheldon Wolin, Hobbes and the Epic Tradition of Political Theory, (Los Angeles: Clark Memorial Library, 1970). See also Richard Flathman's account of his purposes in Thomas Hobbes: Skepticism, Individuality and Chastened Politics (Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1993), xxi.
  • 48
    • 79957107478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 276 ff
    • See the preceding discussion. See also "Introduction" 232-33, 237, 276 ff.
    • Introduction , pp. 232-233
  • 49
    • 85037393512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De Corpore, I, 1, 6.
    • De Corpore , vol.1 , Issue.1 , pp. 6
  • 50
    • 0004076633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Habermas, Theory and Practice; Benjamin Barber, Strong Democracy, Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984); Stephan Salkever, "'Lopp'd and Bound': How Liberal Theory Obscures the Goods of Liberal Practices," Liberalism and the Good, ed. R. Bruce Douglas, Gerald Mara, and Henry Richardson (New York: Routledge, 1990), 167-202.
    • Theory and Practice
    • Habermas1
  • 51
    • 84936526619 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • For example, Habermas, Theory and Practice; Benjamin Barber, Strong Democracy, Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984); Stephan Salkever, "'Lopp'd and Bound': How Liberal Theory Obscures the Goods of Liberal Practices," Liberalism and the Good, ed. R. Bruce Douglas, Gerald Mara, and Henry Richardson (New York: Routledge, 1990), 167-202.
    • (1984) Strong Democracy, Participatory Politics for a New Age
    • Barber, B.1
  • 52
    • 0002143877 scopus 로고
    • 'Lopp'd and bound': How liberal theory obscures the goods of liberal practices
    • ed. R. Bruce Douglas, Gerald Mara, and Henry Richardson New York: Routledge
    • For example, Habermas, Theory and Practice; Benjamin Barber, Strong Democracy, Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984); Stephan Salkever, "'Lopp'd and Bound': How Liberal Theory Obscures the Goods of Liberal Practices," Liberalism and the Good, ed. R. Bruce Douglas, Gerald Mara, and Henry Richardson (New York: Routledge, 1990), 167-202.
    • (1990) Liberalism and the Good , pp. 167-202
    • Salkever, S.1
  • 53
    • 85037398260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These boasts are made in De Corpore, Epistle Dedicatory; see also the Dedicatory and the Preface to Readers of De Cive, Opera Philosophica
    • These boasts are made in De Corpore, Epistle Dedicatory; see also the Dedicatory and the Preface to Readers of De Cive, Opera Philosophica.
  • 56
    • 85037380523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 5, 5.
    • Leviathan , vol.5 , pp. 5
  • 57
    • 85037396417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Hobbes's illustration of the difference between prudence and science in terms of the distinction between the merely prudent fencer and the scientific fencer (Leviathan, 5, 21) reinforces this point. He is not merely concerned with the knowledge of the scientific fencer but with the fact that he is "infallible" in his capacity as a fencer.
  • 58
    • 85037393777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 13, 9.
    • Leviathan , vol.13 , pp. 9
  • 59
  • 60
    • 84968742586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De Corpore, I, 1, 7. See also De Cive, Dedicatory.
    • De Corpore , vol.1 , Issue.1 , pp. 7
  • 61
    • 85037397634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dedicatory
    • De Corpore, I, 1, 7. See also De Cive, Dedicatory.
    • De Cive
  • 63
    • 0007250823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • Two contributors to the recent Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. Tom Sorell (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996) confront this question (and also answer no). See Alan Ryan, "Hobbes's Political Philosophy," in ibid., 208-45, esp. 212-14, for the analogy between Hobbes's science and normative aspects of modern economics. See also Douglas Jesseph, "Hobbes and the Method of Natural Science" in ibid., 86-107, esp. 100-101, where it is claimed that Hobbes had a commitment to "uncover the mechanical causes of natural phenomena"; this commitment is said to mitigate the force of his claims concerning the restriction of philosophic truths to true propositions (and therewith a conventionalist theory of natural science). These very recent interpreters are hardly alone. Even among earlier interpreters, who have been mindful of the distinction between Hobbes's work and contemporary social scientific enterprises, there is recognition that his science is concerned with describing the world. See, for example, David Johnston, The Rhetoric of Leviathan (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 22-24, 52-54; J.W.N. Watkins, Hobbes's System of Ideas (London: Hutchinson, 1965) esp. 8-11, 47-81, 121-25.
    • (1996) Cambridge Companion to Hobbes
    • Sorell, T.1
  • 64
    • 0038223981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbes's political philosophy
    • Two contributors to the recent Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. Tom Sorell (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996) confront this question (and also answer no). See Alan Ryan, "Hobbes's Political Philosophy," in ibid., 208-45, esp. 212-14, for the analogy between Hobbes's science and normative aspects of modern economics. See also Douglas Jesseph, "Hobbes and the Method of Natural Science" in ibid., 86-107, esp. 100-101, where it is claimed that Hobbes had a commitment to "uncover the mechanical causes of natural phenomena"; this commitment is said to mitigate the force of his claims concerning the restriction of philosophic truths to true propositions (and therewith a conventionalist theory of natural science). These very recent interpreters are hardly alone. Even among earlier interpreters, who have been mindful of the distinction between Hobbes's work and contemporary social scientific enterprises, there is recognition that his science is concerned with describing the world. See, for example, David Johnston, The Rhetoric of Leviathan (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 22-24, 52-54; J.W.N. Watkins, Hobbes's System of Ideas (London: Hutchinson, 1965) esp. 8-11, 47-81, 121-25.
    • Cambridge Companion to Hobbes , pp. 208-245
    • Ryan, A.1
  • 65
    • 0007155298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbes and the method of natural science
    • Two contributors to the recent Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. Tom Sorell (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996) confront this question (and also answer no). See Alan Ryan, "Hobbes's Political Philosophy," in ibid., 208-45, esp. 212-14, for the analogy between Hobbes's science and normative aspects of modern economics. See also Douglas Jesseph, "Hobbes and the Method of Natural Science" in ibid., 86-107, esp. 100-101, where it is claimed that Hobbes had a commitment to "uncover the mechanical causes of natural phenomena"; this commitment is said to mitigate the force of his claims concerning the restriction of philosophic truths to true propositions (and therewith a conventionalist theory of natural science). These very recent interpreters are hardly alone. Even among earlier interpreters, who have been mindful of the distinction between Hobbes's work and contemporary social scientific enterprises, there is recognition that his science is concerned with describing the world. See, for example, David Johnston, The Rhetoric of Leviathan (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 22-24, 52-54; J.W.N. Watkins, Hobbes's System of Ideas (London: Hutchinson, 1965) esp. 8-11, 47-81, 121-25.
    • Cambridge Companion to Hobbes , pp. 86-107
    • Jesseph, D.1
  • 66
    • 0003736186 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Two contributors to the recent Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. Tom Sorell (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996) confront this question (and also answer no). See Alan Ryan, "Hobbes's Political Philosophy," in ibid., 208-45, esp. 212-14, for the analogy between Hobbes's science and normative aspects of modern economics. See also Douglas Jesseph, "Hobbes and the Method of Natural Science" in ibid., 86-107, esp. 100-101, where it is claimed that Hobbes had a commitment to "uncover the mechanical causes of natural phenomena"; this commitment is said to mitigate the force of his claims concerning the restriction of philosophic truths to true propositions (and therewith a conventionalist theory of natural science). These very recent interpreters are hardly alone. Even among earlier interpreters, who have been mindful of the distinction between Hobbes's work and contemporary social scientific enterprises, there is recognition that his science is concerned with describing the world. See, for example, David Johnston, The Rhetoric of Leviathan (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 22-24, 52-54; J.W.N. Watkins, Hobbes's System of Ideas (London: Hutchinson, 1965) esp. 8-11, 47-81, 121-25.
    • (1986) The Rhetoric of Leviathan , pp. 22-24
    • Johnston, D.1
  • 67
    • 0004216228 scopus 로고
    • London: Hutchinson
    • Two contributors to the recent Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. Tom Sorell (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996) confront this question (and also answer no). See Alan Ryan, "Hobbes's Political Philosophy," in ibid., 208-45, esp. 212-14, for the analogy between Hobbes's science and normative aspects of modern economics. See also Douglas Jesseph, "Hobbes and the Method of Natural Science" in ibid., 86-107, esp. 100-101, where it is claimed that Hobbes had a commitment to "uncover the mechanical causes of natural phenomena"; this commitment is said to mitigate the force of his claims concerning the restriction of philosophic truths to true propositions (and therewith a conventionalist theory of natural science). These very recent interpreters are hardly alone. Even among earlier interpreters, who have been mindful of the distinction between Hobbes's work and contemporary social scientific enterprises, there is recognition that his science is concerned with describing the world. See, for example, David Johnston, The Rhetoric of Leviathan (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 22-24, 52-54; J.W.N. Watkins, Hobbes's System of Ideas (London: Hutchinson, 1965) esp. 8-11, 47-81, 121-25.
    • (1965) Hobbes's System of Ideas , pp. 8-11
    • Watkins, J.W.N.1
  • 68
    • 0007256275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hobbes and the constraints that enable the imitation of God
    • Ted H. Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints That Enable the Imitation of God," Inquiry 42 (1999): 149-76.
    • (1999) Inquiry , vol.42 , pp. 149-176
    • Miller, T.H.1
  • 69
    • 0007255440 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes: The problem of interpretation
    • ed. Maurice Cranston and Richard Peters Garden City, NY: Anchor
    • For an Oakeshott-inspired classification and evaluation of the secondary literature (written in the early 1970s) that affirms this division and critique of Hobbes interpretation, see W. H. Greenleaf, "Hobbes: The Problem of Interpretation," Hobbes and Rousseau, ed. Maurice Cranston and Richard Peters (Garden City, NY: Anchor, 1972).
    • (1972) Hobbes and Rousseau
    • Greenleaf, W.H.1
  • 70
    • 0004065718 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • I discuss this at length in Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints." Some of the most sustained claims along these lines occur in De Cive, Dedicatory and Preface to the Readers. Some of the more important works on mathematics pertinent to Hobbes's own include Peter Dear, Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995); Peter Dear, Mersenne and the Learning of the Schools (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Paolo Mancosu, "Aristotelian Logic and Euclidean Mathematics: Seventeenth-Century Developments of the Quaestio de certitudine mathematicarum," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 23 (1992): 241-65 (Mancosu briefly discusses Hobbes's conflict with John Wallis); Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); Nicolas Jardine, The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler's 'A Defence of Tycho against Ursus' with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Robert Westman, "The Astronomer's Role in the Sixteenth Century: A Preliminary Study," History of Science 18 (1980): 105-47; A. C. Crombie, "Mathematics and Platonism in the Sixteenth-Century Italian Universities and in Jesuit Educational Policy," Prismata, Naturwissenschaftgeschichtliche Studien, ed. Y. Maeyama and W. G. Slatzer (Wiesbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1977), 63-94.
    • (1995) Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution
    • Dear, P.1
  • 71
    • 0007255441 scopus 로고
    • I discuss this at length in Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints." Some of the most sustained claims along these lines occur in De Cive, Dedicatory and Preface to the Readers. Some of the more important works on mathematics pertinent to Hobbes's own include Peter Dear, Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995); Peter Dear, Mersenne and the Learning of the Schools (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Paolo Mancosu, "Aristotelian Logic and Euclidean Mathematics: Seventeenth-Century Developments of the Quaestio de certitudine mathematicarum," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 23 (1992): 241-65 (Mancosu briefly discusses Hobbes's conflict with John Wallis); Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); Nicolas Jardine, The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler's 'A Defence of Tycho against Ursus' with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Robert Westman, "The Astronomer's Role in the Sixteenth Century: A Preliminary Study," History of Science 18 (1980): 105-47; A. C. Crombie, "Mathematics and Platonism in the Sixteenth-Century Italian Universities and in Jesuit Educational Policy," Prismata, Naturwissenschaftgeschichtliche Studien, ed. Y. Maeyama and W. G. Slatzer (Wiesbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1977), 63-94.
    • (1988) Mersenne and the Learning of the Schools Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • Peter Dear1
  • 72
    • 38249011862 scopus 로고
    • Aristotelian logic and Euclidean mathematics: Seventeenth-century developments of the quaestio de certitudine mathematicarum
    • I discuss this at length in Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints." Some of the most sustained claims along these lines occur in De Cive, Dedicatory and Preface to the Readers. Some of the more important works on mathematics pertinent to Hobbes's own include Peter Dear, Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995); Peter Dear, Mersenne and the Learning of the Schools (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Paolo Mancosu, "Aristotelian Logic and Euclidean Mathematics: Seventeenth-Century Developments of the Quaestio de certitudine mathematicarum," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 23 (1992): 241-65 (Mancosu briefly discusses Hobbes's conflict with John Wallis); Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); Nicolas Jardine, The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler's 'A Defence of Tycho against Ursus' with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Robert Westman, "The Astronomer's Role in the Sixteenth Century: A Preliminary Study," History of Science 18 (1980): 105-47; A. C. Crombie, "Mathematics and Platonism in the Sixteenth-Century Italian Universities and in Jesuit Educational Policy," Prismata, Naturwissenschaftgeschichtliche Studien, ed. Y. Maeyama and W. G. Slatzer (Wiesbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1977), 63-94.
    • (1992) Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , vol.23 , pp. 241-265
    • Mancosu, P.1
  • 73
    • 80054250776 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • I discuss this at length in Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints." Some of the most sustained claims along these lines occur in De Cive, Dedicatory and Preface to the Readers. Some of the more important works on mathematics pertinent to Hobbes's own include Peter Dear, Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995); Peter Dear, Mersenne and the Learning of the Schools (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Paolo Mancosu, "Aristotelian Logic and Euclidean Mathematics: Seventeenth-Century Developments of the Quaestio de certitudine mathematicarum," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 23 (1992): 241-65 (Mancosu briefly discusses Hobbes's conflict with John Wallis); Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); Nicolas Jardine, The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler's 'A Defence of Tycho against Ursus' with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Robert Westman, "The Astronomer's Role in the Sixteenth Century: A Preliminary Study," History of Science 18 (1980): 105-47; A. C. Crombie, "Mathematics and Platonism in the Sixteenth-Century Italian Universities and in Jesuit Educational Policy," Prismata, Naturwissenschaftgeschichtliche Studien, ed. Y. Maeyama and W. G. Slatzer (Wiesbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1977), 63-94.
    • (1985) Leviathan and the Air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life
    • Shapin, S.1    Schaffer, S.2
  • 74
    • 0003822922 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • I discuss this at length in Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints." Some of the most sustained claims along these lines occur in De Cive, Dedicatory and Preface to the Readers. Some of the more important works on mathematics pertinent to Hobbes's own include Peter Dear, Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995); Peter Dear, Mersenne and the Learning of the Schools (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Paolo Mancosu, "Aristotelian Logic and Euclidean Mathematics: Seventeenth-Century Developments of the Quaestio de certitudine mathematicarum," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 23 (1992): 241-65 (Mancosu briefly discusses Hobbes's conflict with John Wallis); Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); Nicolas Jardine, The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler's 'A Defence of Tycho against Ursus' with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Robert Westman, "The Astronomer's Role in the Sixteenth Century: A Preliminary Study," History of Science 18 (1980): 105-47; A. C. Crombie, "Mathematics and Platonism in the Sixteenth-Century Italian Universities and in Jesuit Educational Policy," Prismata, Naturwissenschaftgeschichtliche Studien, ed. Y. Maeyama and W. G. Slatzer (Wiesbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1977), 63-94.
    • (1984) The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler's 'A Defence of Tycho Against Ursus' with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance
    • Jardine, N.1
  • 75
    • 84965861917 scopus 로고
    • The astronomer's role in the sixteenth century: A preliminary study
    • I discuss this at length in Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints." Some of the most sustained claims along these lines occur in De Cive, Dedicatory and Preface to the Readers. Some of the more important works on mathematics pertinent to Hobbes's own include Peter Dear, Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995); Peter Dear, Mersenne and the Learning of the Schools (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Paolo Mancosu, "Aristotelian Logic and Euclidean Mathematics: Seventeenth-Century Developments of the Quaestio de certitudine mathematicarum," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 23 (1992): 241-65 (Mancosu briefly discusses Hobbes's conflict with John Wallis); Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); Nicolas Jardine, The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler's 'A Defence of Tycho against Ursus' with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Robert Westman, "The Astronomer's Role in the Sixteenth Century: A Preliminary Study," History of Science 18 (1980): 105-47; A. C. Crombie, "Mathematics and Platonism in the Sixteenth-Century Italian Universities and in Jesuit Educational Policy," Prismata, Naturwissenschaftgeschichtliche Studien, ed. Y. Maeyama and W. G. Slatzer (Wiesbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1977), 63-94.
    • (1980) History of Science , vol.18 , pp. 105-147
    • Westman, R.1
  • 76
    • 0007303904 scopus 로고
    • Mathematics and platonism in the sixteenth-century Italian universities and in Jesuit educational policy
    • ed. Y. Maeyama and W. G. Slatzer Wiesbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag
    • I discuss this at length in Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints." Some of the most sustained claims along these lines occur in De Cive, Dedicatory and Preface to the Readers. Some of the more important works on mathematics pertinent to Hobbes's own include Peter Dear, Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995); Peter Dear, Mersenne and the Learning of the Schools (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Paolo Mancosu, "Aristotelian Logic and Euclidean Mathematics: Seventeenth-Century Developments of the Quaestio de certitudine mathematicarum," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 23 (1992): 241-65 (Mancosu briefly discusses Hobbes's conflict with John Wallis); Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); Nicolas Jardine, The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler's 'A Defence of Tycho against Ursus' with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Robert Westman, "The Astronomer's Role in the Sixteenth Century: A Preliminary Study," History of Science 18 (1980): 105-47; A. C. Crombie, "Mathematics and Platonism in the Sixteenth-Century Italian Universities and in Jesuit Educational Policy," Prismata, Naturwissenschaftgeschichtliche Studien, ed. Y. Maeyama and W. G. Slatzer (Wiesbaden, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1977), 63-94.
    • (1977) Prismata, Naturwissenschaftgeschichtliche Studien , pp. 63-94
    • Crombie, A.C.1
  • 77
    • 85037389712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I discuss this conflict in Making Certain: Thomas Hobbes and the Fashioning of States, Citizens, and Mathematicians (book manuscript in preparation). See also Douglas Jesseph, Squaring the Circle: The War between Hobbes and Wallis (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999). Hobbes's mathematical works include Six Lessons to the Professors of Mathematiques (1656); ΣTIΓMAI or MARKES of the Absurd Geometry, Rural Language, Scottish-Politics, and Barbarism of John Wallis (1657); Examinatio et Emedation Mathematicae Hodiernae (1660); Principia et Problemata Aliquot Geometrarum (1666); Lux Mathematica (1672). All are reprinted in the English Works (11 vols.), ed. Sir William Molesworth (London: John Bohn, 1839-45) or in Opera Latino (5 vols.), ed. Sir William Molesworth (1839-45).
  • 78
    • 85037389757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 1, 5; 4, 4; 5, 5-16; 8, 27; 12, 31, throughout; De Corpore I, 5, 1-9.
    • Leviathan , vol.1 , pp. 5
  • 79
    • 85037395406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 1, 5; 4, 4; 5, 5-16; 8, 27; 12, 31, throughout; De Corpore I, 5, 1-9.
    • Leviathan , vol.4 , pp. 4
  • 80
    • 85037396018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 1, 5; 4, 4; 5, 5-16; 8, 27; 12, 31, throughout; De Corpore I, 5, 1-9.
    • Leviathan , vol.5 , pp. 5-16
  • 81
    • 85037382364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 1, 5; 4, 4; 5, 5-16; 8, 27; 12, 31, throughout; De Corpore I, 5, 1-9.
    • Leviathan , vol.8 , pp. 27
  • 82
    • 85037379653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 1, 5; 4, 4; 5, 5-16; 8, 27; 12, 31, throughout; De Corpore I, 5, 1-9.
    • , vol.12 , pp. 31
  • 83
    • 85037388406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 1, 5; 4, 4; 5, 5-16; 8, 27; 12, 31, throughout; De Corpore I, 5, 1-9.
    • De Corpore , vol.1 , Issue.5 , pp. 1-9
  • 84
    • 85037400323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 4, 12.
    • Leviathan , vol.4 , pp. 12
  • 85
    • 84904142049 scopus 로고
    • Francis Bacon and man's two-faced kingdom
    • ed. G.H.R. Parkinson London: Routledge
    • See discussion of "maker's knowledge" in Antonio Pérez-Ramos, "Francis Bacon and Man's Two-Faced Kingdom," Renaissance and Seventeenth-Century Rationalism, ed. G.H.R. Parkinson (London: Routledge, 1993); Antonio Pérez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's Idea of Science and the Maker's Knowledge Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon, 1989); Arthur Child, "Making and Knowing in Hobbes, Vico, and Dewey," University of California Publications in Philosophy 16 (1953): 271-310. Child, however, shies away from more interesting conclusions concerning Hobbes's civil science.
    • (1993) Renaissance and Seventeenth-century Rationalism
    • Pérez-Ramos, A.1
  • 86
    • 0003849390 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon
    • See discussion of "maker's knowledge" in Antonio Pérez-Ramos, "Francis Bacon and Man's Two-Faced Kingdom," Renaissance and Seventeenth-Century Rationalism, ed. G.H.R. Parkinson (London: Routledge, 1993); Antonio Pérez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's Idea of Science and the Maker's Knowledge Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon, 1989); Arthur Child, "Making and Knowing in Hobbes, Vico, and Dewey," University of California Publications in Philosophy 16 (1953): 271-310. Child, however, shies away from more interesting conclusions concerning Hobbes's civil science.
    • (1989) Francis Bacon's Idea of Science and the Maker's Knowledge Tradition
    • Pérez-Ramos, A.1
  • 87
    • 0007186693 scopus 로고
    • Making and knowing in Hobbes, Vico, and Dewey
    • See discussion of "maker's knowledge" in Antonio Pérez-Ramos, "Francis Bacon and Man's Two-Faced Kingdom," Renaissance and Seventeenth-Century Rationalism, ed. G.H.R. Parkinson (London: Routledge, 1993); Antonio Pérez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's Idea of Science and the Maker's Knowledge Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon, 1989); Arthur Child, "Making and Knowing in Hobbes, Vico, and Dewey," University of California Publications in Philosophy 16 (1953): 271-310. Child, however, shies away from more interesting conclusions concerning Hobbes's civil science.
    • (1953) University of California Publications in Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 271-310
    • Child, A.1
  • 88
    • 0007312669 scopus 로고
    • London: Methuen
    • Norman Jacobson's reading of Hobbes in Norman Jacobson, Pride and Solace (London: Methuen, 1978) makes light of the God-like claims that Hobbes makes for his philosophy. I find that Jacobson's assertions are in many respects similar to my own conclusions, although the two studies have different purposes.
    • (1978) Pride and Solace
    • Jacobson, N.1
  • 89
    • 85037396959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De Corpore, I, 1, 5.
    • De Corpore , vol.1 , Issue.1 , pp. 5
  • 90
    • 85037396959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
    • De Corpore , vol.1 , Issue.1 , pp. 5
  • 91
    • 85037396959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
    • De Corpore , vol.1 , Issue.1 , pp. 5
  • 92
    • 85037396765 scopus 로고
    • De homine
    • chap. 10, section 5, Charles Wood, T.S.K. Scott-Craig, and Bernard Gert, New York: Anchor
    • De Homine, chap. 10, section 5, trans. Charles Wood, T.S.K. Scott-Craig, and Bernard Gert, in Man and Citizen (New York: Anchor, 1972). See also Hobbes's concluding remarks in De Corpore, IV, 30, 15.
    • (1972) Man and Citizen
  • 93
    • 85037397885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De Homine, chap. 10, section 5, trans. Charles Wood, T.S.K. Scott-Craig, and Bernard Gert, in Man and Citizen (New York: Anchor, 1972). See also Hobbes's concluding remarks in De Corpore, IV, 30, 15.
    • De Corpore , vol.4 , Issue.30 , pp. 15
  • 94
    • 85037396908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The doctrine of natural causes hath not infallible and evident principles. For there is no effect which the power of God cannot produce by many several ways. But seeing all effects are produced by motion, he that supposing someone or more motions, can derive from them the necessity of that effect whose cause is required, has done all that is to be expected from natural reason. And though he prove not that the thing was thus produced, yet he proves that thus it may be produced when the materials and the power of moving are in our hands: which is as useful as if the causes themselves were known. (Thomas Hobbes, Seven Philosophical Problems, Dedicatory, in English Works [vol. 7])
  • 95
    • 85037398815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I discuss this distinction at length in Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints."
  • 96
    • 85037398846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De Homine, 10, 5. In the Latin, Hobbes writes of these things, "ipsi fecimus" (i.e., from "facere," to make), Opera Latino (vol. 1 ), 94.
    • De Homine , vol.10 , pp. 5
  • 97
    • 85037384411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De Homine, 10, 5. In the Latin, Hobbes writes of these things, "ipsi fecimus" (i.e., from "facere," to make), Opera Latino (vol. 1 ), 94.
    • Opera Latino , vol.1 , pp. 94
  • 98
    • 85037388810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leviathan, 17, 2.
    • Leviathan , vol.17 , pp. 2
  • 99
    • 85037394621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Oakeshott in fact argued this characteristic of Hobbes's laws of nature. See "Introduction," 256-57. He only does so, however, after having neutralized the practical implications of this reading - noting that in civil philosophy, "the generation [of effects] is rational and not physical" (ibid., 248).
  • 100
    • 84908911724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The masses in representative democracy
    • reprinted in Oakeshott
    • This assertion may seem to cut against Oakeshott's professed liberalism. Oakeshott was in fact a liberal. He was particularly concerned with protecting the individual and with cultivating circumstances that allowed the virtues of individuality to flourish. See, for example, Michael Oakeshott, "The Masses in Representative Democracy," reprinted in Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, and Michael Oakeshott, On Human Conduct (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1991). See also Flathman, Skepticism, Individuality and Chastened Politics. One need not deny his liberalism to acknowledge that this liberalism, and his other stands, were defended with the tools of a rather aristocratic habit of mind. In fact, it is the preference for trading in critiques that emphasize habits of mind, of character revealed through practice (habitus), that make Oakeshott's intellectual tools so aristocratic in nature.
    • Rationalism in Politics
    • Oakeshott, M.1
  • 101
    • 0004027182 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press
    • This assertion may seem to cut against Oakeshott's professed liberalism. Oakeshott was in fact a liberal. He was particularly concerned with protecting the individual and with cultivating circumstances that allowed the virtues of individuality to flourish. See, for example, Michael Oakeshott, "The Masses in Representative Democracy," reprinted in Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, and Michael Oakeshott, On Human Conduct (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1991). See also Flathman, Skepticism, Individuality and Chastened Politics. One need not deny his liberalism to acknowledge that this liberalism, and his other stands, were defended with the tools of a rather aristocratic habit of mind. In fact, it is the preference for trading in critiques that emphasize habits of mind, of character revealed through practice (habitus), that make Oakeshott's intellectual tools so aristocratic in nature.
    • (1991) On Human Conduct
    • Oakeshott, M.1
  • 102
    • 79957794009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This assertion may seem to cut against Oakeshott's professed liberalism. Oakeshott was in fact a liberal. He was particularly concerned with protecting the individual and with cultivating circumstances that allowed the virtues of individuality to flourish. See, for example, Michael Oakeshott, "The Masses in Representative Democracy," reprinted in Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics, and Michael Oakeshott, On Human Conduct (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1991). See also Flathman, Skepticism, Individuality and Chastened Politics. One need not deny his liberalism to acknowledge that this liberalism, and his other stands, were defended with the tools of a rather aristocratic habit of mind. In fact, it is the preference for trading in critiques that emphasize habits of mind, of character revealed through practice (habitus), that make Oakeshott's intellectual tools so aristocratic in nature.
    • Skepticism, Individuality and Chastened Politics
    • Flathman1
  • 103
    • 0003583974 scopus 로고
    • Richard Nice Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Cf. Pierre Bourdieu, Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste, trans. Richard Nice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984), a more distanced, scientific study of habitus in the pursuit of a fundamentally different political goal.
    • (1984) Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste
    • Bourdieu, P.1
  • 104
    • 0003876640 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin
    • A good example is Richard Peters, Hobbes (Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin, 1956).
    • (1956) Hobbes
    • Peters, R.1
  • 105
    • 0004076633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two good examples of such critiques are Habermas, "Theory and Practice"; Jürgen Habermas, "Technology and Science As Ideology," in Jürgen Habermas, Toward a Rational Society; Student Protest, Science, and Politics, trans. Jeremy Shapiro (Boston: Beacon, 1970), 81-122; and Hans Georg-Gadamer, Reason in the Age of Science, trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981).
    • Theory and Practice
    • Habermas1
  • 106
    • 0007343196 scopus 로고
    • Technology and science as ideology
    • Jürgen Habermas, Jeremy Shapiro Boston: Beacon
    • Two good examples of such critiques are Habermas, "Theory and Practice"; Jürgen Habermas, "Technology and Science As Ideology," in Jürgen Habermas, Toward a Rational Society; Student Protest, Science, and Politics, trans. Jeremy Shapiro (Boston: Beacon, 1970), 81-122; and Hans Georg-Gadamer, Reason in the Age of Science, trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981).
    • (1970) Toward a Rational Society; Student Protest, Science, and Politics , pp. 81-122
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 107
    • 0004171421 scopus 로고
    • Frederick Lawrence Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • Two good examples of such critiques are Habermas, "Theory and Practice"; Jürgen Habermas, "Technology and Science As Ideology," in Jürgen Habermas, Toward a Rational Society; Student Protest, Science, and Politics, trans. Jeremy Shapiro (Boston: Beacon, 1970), 81-122; and Hans Georg-Gadamer, Reason in the Age of Science, trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981).
    • (1981) Reason in the Age of Science
    • Georg-Gadamer, H.1
  • 108
    • 0004000174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • One finds, for example, citations to Oakeshott's arguments in the recent work of James Scott, Seeing Like a State (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998); Chantal Mouffe, The Return of the Political (London: Verso, 1993); Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989); Ronald Beiner, Political Judgment (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983).
    • (1998) Seeing Like a State
    • Scott, J.1
  • 109
    • 0004099909 scopus 로고
    • London: Verso
    • One finds, for example, citations to Oakeshott's arguments in the recent work of James Scott, Seeing Like a State (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998); Chantal Mouffe, The Return of the Political (London: Verso, 1993); Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989); Ronald Beiner, Political Judgment (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983).
    • (1993) The Return of the Political
    • Mouffe, C.1
  • 110
    • 0003967815 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • One finds, for example, citations to Oakeshott's arguments in the recent work of James Scott, Seeing Like a State (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998); Chantal Mouffe, The Return of the Political (London: Verso, 1993); Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989); Ronald Beiner, Political Judgment (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983).
    • (1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 111
    • 0003979560 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • One finds, for example, citations to Oakeshott's arguments in the recent work of James Scott, Seeing Like a State (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998); Chantal Mouffe, The Return of the Political (London: Verso, 1993); Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989); Ronald Beiner, Political Judgment (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983).
    • (1983) Political Judgment
    • Beiner, R.1
  • 113
    • 85037392343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 28, 32-33. The reference to old parchment is Alexander Hamilton's, here cited by Oakeshott.
    • Rationalism in Politics , vol.28 , pp. 32-33
  • 114
    • 0003897575 scopus 로고
    • Anne M. Cohler, Basia C. Miller, and Harold Stone Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, trans. Anne M. Cohler, Basia C. Miller, and Harold Stone (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 6; Rousseau, Discourse on the Origins of Inequality, trans. Donald Cress, The Basic Political Writings (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1987), 53.
    • (1989) The Spirit of the Laws , vol.6
    • Montesquieu1
  • 115
    • 0007253697 scopus 로고
    • Discourse on the origins of inequality
    • Donald Cress, Indianapolis, IN: Hackett
    • Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, trans. Anne M. Cohler, Basia C. Miller, and Harold Stone (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 6; Rousseau, Discourse on the Origins of Inequality, trans. Donald Cress, The Basic Political Writings (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1987), 53.
    • (1987) The Basic Political Writings , pp. 53
    • Rousseau1
  • 116
    • 85037380760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I discuss this in Making Certain: Thomas Hobbes and the Fashioning of States, Citizens, and Mathematicians (book manuscript in preparation), particularly the common feelings of political disillusionment and stoicism among the British political elite in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries.
  • 117
    • 85037390505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To suggest that it is nothing but misery and fear that animates the politics of an artificer, however, is too one-sided. Hobbes also wrote to tempt and/or appease those likely to become sovereign over the order that he would found. He did so by appealing to their desire for glory. It was not the glory of scientific discovery, but a glory that would allow them to see themselves as imitators of God. See Ted H. Miller, "Thomas Hobbes and the Constraints." Hobbes promises to make those who follow his philosophical advice concerning the a priori sciences imitators of God as a creator. Hobbes's creators do not create out of nothing, but, still like the divine, they create order where there was once none.
  • 118
    • 85037387114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Carl Schmitt's temporary, but influential, admiration for Hobbes also bespeaks his credentials as a theorist familiar with 'the political'. A discussion of Schmitt, however, is outside the scope of this essay.
  • 119
    • 84998186801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking the state: Perspectives on the legibility and reproduction of political societies
    • James Scott, cited in Shannon Stimpson, "Rethinking the State: Perspectives on the Legibility and Reproduction of Political Societies," Political Theory, 28 (2000): 822-34.
    • (2000) Political Theory , vol.28 , pp. 822-834
    • Scott, J.1    Stimpson, S.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.