메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 2, 2000, Pages 233-251

The liberal-communitarian debate in contemporary political philosophy and its significance for international relations

(1)  Morrice, David a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0034400429     PISSN: 02602105     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0260210500002333     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (29)

References (85)
  • 1
    • 0004335493 scopus 로고
    • Hemel Hempstead
    • Chris Brown, International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches (Hemel Hempstead, 1992), p. 8. For further consideration of the links between political theory and international relations theory see E. B. F. Midgley, The Natural Law Tradition and the Theory of International Relations (London, 1975); Michael Donelan, 'The Political Theorists and International Theory', m M. Donelan (ed.), The Reason of States (London, 1978), pp. 75-91; Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, 1979); Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations (London, 1982); and Mervyn Frost, Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations (Cambridge, 1986).
    • (1992) International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches , pp. 8
    • Brown, C.1
  • 2
    • 0040352830 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Chris Brown, International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches (Hemel Hempstead, 1992), p. 8. For further consideration of the links between political theory and international relations theory see E. B. F. Midgley, The Natural Law Tradition and the Theory of International Relations (London, 1975); Michael Donelan, 'The Political Theorists and International Theory', m M. Donelan (ed.), The Reason of States (London, 1978), pp. 75-91; Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, 1979); Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations (London, 1982); and Mervyn Frost, Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations (Cambridge, 1986).
    • (1975) The Natural Law Tradition and the Theory of International Relations
    • Midgley, E.B.F.1
  • 3
    • 0039948683 scopus 로고
    • The political theorists and international theory
    • m M. Donelan (ed.), London
    • Chris Brown, International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches (Hemel Hempstead, 1992), p. 8. For further consideration of the links between political theory and international relations theory see E. B. F. Midgley, The Natural Law Tradition and the Theory of International Relations (London, 1975); Michael Donelan, 'The Political Theorists and International Theory', m M. Donelan (ed.), The Reason of States (London, 1978), pp. 75-91; Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, 1979); Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations (London, 1982); and Mervyn Frost, Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations (Cambridge, 1986).
    • (1978) The Reason of States , pp. 75-91
    • Donelan, M.1
  • 4
    • 0003556319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • Chris Brown, International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches (Hemel Hempstead, 1992), p. 8. For further consideration of the links between political theory and international relations theory see E. B. F. Midgley, The Natural Law Tradition and the Theory of International Relations (London, 1975); Michael Donelan, 'The Political Theorists and International Theory', m M. Donelan (ed.), The Reason of States (London, 1978), pp. 75-91; Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, 1979); Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations (London, 1982); and Mervyn Frost, Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations (Cambridge, 1986).
    • (1979) Political Theory and International Relations
    • Beitz, C.1
  • 5
    • 0003579953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London
    • Chris Brown, International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches (Hemel Hempstead, 1992), p. 8. For further consideration of the links between political theory and international relations theory see E. B. F. Midgley, The Natural Law Tradition and the Theory of International Relations (London, 1975); Michael Donelan, 'The Political Theorists and International Theory', m M. Donelan (ed.), The Reason of States (London, 1978), pp. 75-91; Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, 1979); Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations (London, 1982); and Mervyn Frost, Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations (Cambridge, 1986).
    • (1982) Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations
    • Linklater, A.1
  • 6
    • 80052355997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Chris Brown, International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches (Hemel Hempstead, 1992), p. 8. For further consideration of the links between political theory and international relations theory see E. B. F. Midgley, The Natural Law Tradition and the Theory of International Relations (London, 1975); Michael Donelan, 'The Political Theorists and International Theory', m M. Donelan (ed.), The Reason of States (London, 1978), pp. 75-91; Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, 1979); Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations (London, 1982); and Mervyn Frost, Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations (Cambridge, 1986).
    • (1986) Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations
    • Frost, M.1
  • 10
    • 0004253960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • See Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge, 1982); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (Oxford, 1983); Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (London, 1981); Charles Taylor, Hegel and Modern Society (Cambridge, 1979); Taylor, 'Atomism', in Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (Cambridge, 1985).
    • (1982) Liberalism and the Limits of Justice
    • Sandel, M.1
  • 11
    • 0004238625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • See Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge, 1982); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (Oxford, 1983); Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (London, 1981); Charles Taylor, Hegel and Modern Society (Cambridge, 1979); Taylor, 'Atomism', in Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (Cambridge, 1985).
    • (1983) Spheres of Justice
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 12
    • 0004123406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London
    • See Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge, 1982); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (Oxford, 1983); Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (London, 1981); Charles Taylor, Hegel and Modern Society (Cambridge, 1979); Taylor, 'Atomism', in Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (Cambridge, 1985).
    • (1981) After Virtue
    • Macintyre, A.1
  • 13
    • 0004184760 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • See Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge, 1982); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (Oxford, 1983); Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (London, 1981); Charles Taylor, Hegel and Modern Society (Cambridge, 1979); Taylor, 'Atomism', in Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (Cambridge, 1985).
    • (1979) Hegel and Modern Society
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 14
    • 0001753541 scopus 로고
    • Atomism
    • Cambridge
    • See Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge, 1982); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (Oxford, 1983); Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (London, 1981); Charles Taylor, Hegel and Modern Society (Cambridge, 1979); Taylor, 'Atomism', in Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (Cambridge, 1985).
    • (1985) Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Philosophical Papers , vol.2
    • Taylor1
  • 15
    • 84972425553 scopus 로고
    • The communitarian critique of liberalism
    • Contemporary communitarians recognise this point, of course. Michael Walzer acknowledges that the 'writings of the young Marx represent one of the early appearances of communitarian criticism', and argues that the communitarian critique of liberalism is like a fashion: 'transient but certain to return'. Walzer, 'The Communitarian Critique of Liberalism', Political Theory, 18 (1990), pp. 6-23, at p. 8 and p. 6.
    • (1990) Political Theory , vol.18 , pp. 6-23
    • Walzer1
  • 16
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York, 1993). Amongst other things, Rawls now argues that his theory of justice is political and not metaphysical. That is, the theory of justice cannot depend on a comprehensive religious, philosophical or moral doctrine accepted by all citizens, but on an overlapping consensus of competing doctrines in the political domain of society. The theory of justice is applicable not universally but only in regimes with a certain sort of political culture, that is, constitutional democracies.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 17
    • 84981683828 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and communitarianism: A misconceived debate
    • This point is well made by Simon Caney, 'Liberalism and Communitarianism: a Misconceived Debate', Political Studies, 40 (1992), pp. 273-89. However, see the rejoinder by Stephen Mulhall and Adam Swift, 'Liberalisms and Communitarianisms: whose Misconception?', Political Studies, 41 (1993), pp. 650-56. Charles Taylor identifies 'a lot of cross-purposes, and just plain confusion' in the liberal-communitarian debate. Charles Taylor, 'Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate', in Nancy Rosenblum (ed.), Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge, MA., 1989), p.159.
    • (1992) Political Studies , vol.40 , pp. 273-289
    • Caney, S.1
  • 18
    • 84981656873 scopus 로고
    • Liberalisms and communitarianisms: Whose misconception?
    • This point is well made by Simon Caney, 'Liberalism and Communitarianism: a Misconceived Debate', Political Studies, 40 (1992), pp. 273-89. However, see the rejoinder by Stephen Mulhall and Adam Swift, 'Liberalisms and Communitarianisms: whose Misconception?', Political Studies, 41 (1993), pp. 650-56. Charles Taylor identifies 'a lot of cross-purposes, and just plain confusion' in the liberal-communitarian debate. Charles Taylor, 'Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate', in Nancy Rosenblum (ed.), Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge, MA., 1989), p.159.
    • (1993) Political Studies , vol.41 , pp. 650-656
    • Mulhall, S.1    Swift, A.2
  • 19
    • 84981683828 scopus 로고
    • Cross-purposes: The liberal-communitarian debate
    • Nancy Rosenblum (ed.), Cambridge, MA.
    • This point is well made by Simon Caney, 'Liberalism and Communitarianism: a Misconceived Debate', Political Studies, 40 (1992), pp. 273-89. However, see the rejoinder by Stephen Mulhall and Adam Swift, 'Liberalisms and Communitarianisms: whose Misconception?', Political Studies, 41 (1993), pp. 650-56. Charles Taylor identifies 'a lot of cross-purposes, and just plain confusion' in the liberal-communitarian debate. Charles Taylor, 'Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate', in Nancy Rosenblum (ed.), Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge, MA., 1989), p.159.
    • (1989) Liberalism and the Moral Life , pp. 159
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 20
    • 0004135332 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • See Caney, 'Liberalism and Communitarianism', whose formulation I follow here; Daniel Bell, Communitarianism and its Critics (Oxford, 1993), pp. 4-8; and Patrick Neal and David Paris, 'Liberalism and the Communitarian Critique: A Guide for the Perplexed', Canadian Journal of Political Science, XXIII (1990), pp. 418-19.
    • (1993) Communitarianism and its Critics , pp. 4-8
    • Bell, D.1
  • 21
    • 84974269864 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and the communitarian critique: A guide for the perplexed
    • See Caney, 'Liberalism and Communitarianism', whose formulation I follow here; Daniel Bell, Communitarianism and its Critics (Oxford, 1993), pp. 4-8; and Patrick Neal and David Paris, 'Liberalism and the Communitarian Critique: A Guide for the Perplexed', Canadian Journal of Political Science, XXIII (1990), pp. 418-19.
    • (1990) Canadian Journal of Political Science , vol.23 , pp. 418-419
    • Neal, P.1    Paris, D.2
  • 25
  • 26
    • 0039356232 scopus 로고
    • Commentary: The value of community
    • Sean Sayers says: 'Whether the policies of the Thatcher and Reagan years brought any overall economic benefits is doubtful: that they have had high social costs is now quite evident. The unfettered pursuit of self-interest has weakened social bonds and led to social decay and disintegration on a scale which is causing alarm right across the political spectrum'. Sean Sayers, 'Commentary: The Value of Community', Radical Philosophy, 69 (1995), p. 2.
    • (1995) Radical Philosophy , vol.69 , pp. 2
    • Sayers, S.1
  • 32
    • 0004426479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 110. Onora O'Neill also notes the similarities between liberalism and cosmopolitanism and the opposition of both to communitarianism. Onora O'Neill, Transnational Justice', in David Held (ed.), Political Theory Today (Cambridge, 1991), pp. 279-82.
    • International Relations Theory , pp. 110
  • 33
    • 0002366171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Transnational justice
    • David Held (ed.), Cambridge
    • Ibid., p. 110. Onora O'Neill also notes the similarities between liberalism and cosmopolitanism and the opposition of both to communitarianism. Onora O'Neill, Transnational Justice', in David Held (ed.), Political Theory Today (Cambridge, 1991), pp. 279-82.
    • (1991) Political Theory Today , pp. 279-282
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 34
    • 84891284710 scopus 로고
    • De potestate civili
    • A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds.), Cambridge
    • See Francisco de Vitoria, De Potestate Civili, in A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds.), Francisco de Vitoria: Political Writings (Cambridge, 1991); and Francisco Suarez, Tractatus de Legibus ac Deo Legislature, in J. B. Scott (ed.), Selections from Three Works (Oxford, 1944).
    • (1991) Francisco de Vitoria: Political Writings
    • De Vitoria, F.1
  • 35
    • 0346313103 scopus 로고
    • Tractatus de Legibus ac Deo Legislature
    • J. B. Scott (ed.), Oxford
    • See Francisco de Vitoria, De Potestate Civili, in A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds.), Francisco de Vitoria: Political Writings (Cambridge, 1991); and Francisco Suarez, Tractatus de Legibus ac Deo Legislature, in J. B. Scott (ed.), Selections from Three Works (Oxford, 1944).
    • (1944) Selections from Three Works
    • Suarez, F.1
  • 36
    • 0003556319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations; Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations; and Onora O'Neill, Faces of Hunger (London, 1986), Constructions of Reason (Cambridge, 1989), and 'Transnational Justice'.
    • Political Theory and International Relations
    • Beitz, C.1
  • 38
    • 0006946337 scopus 로고
    • London
    • See Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations; Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations; and Onora O'Neill, Faces of Hunger (London, 1986), Constructions of Reason (Cambridge, 1989), and 'Transnational Justice'.
    • (1986) Faces of Hunger
  • 39
    • 0004231396 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, and 'Transnational Justice'
    • See Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations; Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations; and Onora O'Neill, Faces of Hunger (London, 1986), Constructions of Reason (Cambridge, 1989), and 'Transnational Justice'.
    • (1989) Constructions of Reason
  • 41
    • 0004002174 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • Frost, Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations; David Miller, On Nationality (Oxford, 1995); and Walzer, Spheres of Justice (especially ch. 2), and Just and Unjust Wars (Harmondsworth , 1980).
    • (1995) On Nationality
    • Miller, D.1
  • 42
    • 84960234430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (especially ch. 2)
    • Frost, Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations; David Miller, On Nationality (Oxford, 1995); and Walzer, Spheres of Justice (especially ch. 2), and Just and Unjust Wars (Harmondsworth , 1980).
    • Spheres of Justice
  • 43
    • 0004083066 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth
    • Frost, Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations; David Miller, On Nationality (Oxford, 1995); and Walzer, Spheres of Justice (especially ch. 2), and Just and Unjust Wars (Harmondsworth , 1980).
    • (1980) Just and Unjust Wars
  • 45
    • 0004099967 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Important texts of modern realism include E. H. Carr, The Twenty Years' Crisis, 1919-1939: An Introduction to the Study of International Relations, 2nd edn. (London, 1946); and Hans Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 2nd edn. (New York, 1954). The classic texts of realism are usually said to include Niccolo Machiavelli, The Prince, Q. Skinner (ed.) (Cambridge, 1988) ,
    • (1954) Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 2nd Edn.
    • Morgenthau, H.1
  • 46
    • 0002368205 scopus 로고
    • Q. Skinner (ed.) Cambridge
    • Important texts of modern realism include E. H. Carr, The Twenty Years' Crisis, 1919-1939: An Introduction to the Study of International Relations, 2nd edn. (London, 1946); and Hans Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 2nd edn. (New York, 1954). The classic texts of realism are usually said to include Niccolo Machiavelli, The Prince, Q. Skinner (ed.) (Cambridge, 1988) ,
    • (1988) The Prince
    • Machiavelli, N.1
  • 47
    • 0004287799 scopus 로고
    • R. Tuck (ed.) Cambridge
    • and Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, R. Tuck (ed.) (Cambridge, 1991).
    • (1991) Leviathan
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 48
    • 84970721377 scopus 로고
    • A city which sustains all things? Communitarianism and international society
    • N. J. Rengger, 'A City Which Sustains All Things? Communitarianism and International Society', Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 21 (1992), pp. 362 and 353.
    • (1992) Millennium: Journal of International Studies , vol.21 , pp. 362
    • Rengger, N.J.1
  • 49
    • 0041135450 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • See Hugo Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pacis (Oxford, 1925); and Samuel Pufendorf, On the Duty of Man and Citizen According to Natural Law (Cambridge, 1991).
    • (1925) De Jure Belli Ac Pacis
    • Grotius, H.1
  • 51
    • 85037783489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Book 1, ch. 2, in R. McKeon (ed.)
    • Aristotle, Politics, Book 1, ch. 2, in R. McKeon (ed.), The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York, 1941), p. 1129.
    • Politics
    • Aristotle1
  • 52
    • 0004241322 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Aristotle, Politics, Book 1, ch. 2, in R. McKeon (ed.), The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York, 1941), p. 1129.
    • (1941) The Basic Works of Aristotle , pp. 1129
  • 55
    • 21144481115 scopus 로고
    • Nation and community in the international order
    • Anthony Black, 'Nation and Community in the International Order', Review of International Studies, 19 (1993), p. 88.
    • (1993) Review of International Studies , vol.19 , pp. 88
    • Black, A.1
  • 58
    • 79960371621 scopus 로고
    • The ethical significance of nationality
    • David Miller, 'The Ethical Significance of Nationality', Ethics, 98 (1988), p. 647. John O'Neill challenges the commonly accepted association of communitarianism and nationalism. He argues: 'Ties to nation do not represent the continuation of ties to community in a society in which such ties are being otherwise undermined - they rather signify the absence of such ties. The nation is one of the main vehicles for the construction of the unencumbered self and the disappearance of ties of community'. John O'Neill, 'Should Communitarians be Nationalists?', Journal of Applied Philosophy, 11 (1994), p. 136.
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.98 , pp. 647
    • Miller, D.1
  • 59
    • 84968798996 scopus 로고
    • Should communitarians be nationalists?
    • David Miller, 'The Ethical Significance of Nationality', Ethics, 98 (1988), p. 647. John O'Neill challenges the commonly accepted association of communitarianism and nationalism. He argues: 'Ties to nation do not represent the continuation of ties to community in a society in which such ties are being otherwise undermined - they rather signify the absence of such ties. The nation is one of the main vehicles for the construction of the unencumbered self and the disappearance of ties of community'. John O'Neill, 'Should Communitarians be Nationalists?', Journal of Applied Philosophy, 11 (1994), p. 136.
    • (1994) Journal of Applied Philosophy , vol.11 , pp. 136
    • O'Neill, J.1
  • 60
    • 0003919553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism and Truth, p. 29. Rorty does seek to offer some support for his privileging of liberalism. Although all human communities remain ethnocentric and limited by the bounds of their culture, it is the merit of 'the liberal culture of recent times' that it 'has found a strategy for avoiding the disadvantage of ethnocentrism'. It is in the nature of liberal culture 'to be open to encounters with other actual and possible culture'. The liberal culture makes 'openness central to its self-image' and 'prides itself on its suspicion of ethnocentrism' (p. 2). One problem with this argument is that the openness which is the supposed merit of the liberal culture is a value embedded in, and peculiar to, this culture.
    • Objectivity, Relativism and Truth , pp. 29
    • Rorty1
  • 65
    • 0003981612 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Oxford, 1985), pp. 217, 219-20. Walzer, in common with most relativists, seeks to deny his relativism. In a number of publications following Spheres of Justice, including Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, MA, 1987), The Company of Critics (London, 1989), and Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (Notre Dame, IN, 1994), Walzer has attempted to argue that social criticism is possible in the absence of universal, objective principles. Walzer's attempt is bound to fail because his communitarianism cannot allow any critic an objective position outside of any community, or sufficient critical distance from any community, from which to formulate any objective evaluation.
    • (1985) A Matter of Principle , pp. 217
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 66
    • 0041135446 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA
    • Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Oxford, 1985), pp. 217, 219-20. Walzer, in common with most relativists, seeks to deny his relativism. In a number of publications following Spheres of Justice, including Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, MA, 1987), The Company of Critics (London, 1989), and Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (Notre Dame, IN, 1994), Walzer has attempted to argue that social criticism is possible in the absence of universal, objective principles. Walzer's attempt is bound to fail because his communitarianism cannot allow any critic an objective position outside of any community, or sufficient critical distance from any community, from which to formulate any objective evaluation.
    • (1987) Spheres of Justice, Including Interpretation and Social Criticism
  • 67
    • 0038991968 scopus 로고
    • London
    • Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Oxford, 1985), pp. 217, 219-20. Walzer, in common with most relativists, seeks to deny his relativism. In a number of publications following Spheres of Justice, including Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, MA, 1987), The Company of Critics (London, 1989), and Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (Notre Dame, IN, 1994), Walzer has attempted to argue that social criticism is possible in the absence of universal, objective principles. Walzer's attempt is bound to fail because his communitarianism cannot allow any critic an objective position outside of any community, or sufficient critical distance from any community, from which to formulate any objective evaluation.
    • (1989) The Company of Critics
  • 68
    • 0003685593 scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame, IN
    • Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Oxford, 1985), pp. 217, 219-20. Walzer, in common with most relativists, seeks to deny his relativism. In a number of publications following Spheres of Justice, including Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, MA, 1987), The Company of Critics (London, 1989), and Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (Notre Dame, IN, 1994), Walzer has attempted to argue that social criticism is possible in the absence of universal, objective principles. Walzer's attempt is bound to fail because his communitarianism cannot allow any critic an objective position outside of any community, or sufficient critical distance from any community, from which to formulate any objective evaluation.
    • (1994) Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad
  • 70
    • 84935566128 scopus 로고
    • Communitarian critics of liberalism
    • Amy Gutmann, 'Communitarian Critics of Liberalism', Philosophy And Public Affairs, 14 (1985), pp. 308-22.
    • (1985) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.14 , pp. 308-322
    • Gutmann, A.1
  • 72
    • 0041135442 scopus 로고
    • Not my department? Normative theory and international relations
    • Chris Brown, 'Not My Department? Normative Theory and International Relations', Paradigms, 2 (1987), pp. 107, 109 and 110. Another modern account of the morality of states position is set out in R. J. Vincent, Nonintervention and International Order (Princeton, 1974), ch. 9.
    • (1987) Paradigms , vol.2 , pp. 107
    • Brown, C.1
  • 73
    • 85002919477 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, ch. 9
    • Chris Brown, 'Not My Department? Normative Theory and International Relations', Paradigms, 2 (1987), pp. 107, 109 and 110. Another modern account of the morality of states position is set out in R. J. Vincent, Nonintervention and International Order (Princeton, 1974), ch. 9.
    • (1974) Nonintervention and International Order
    • Vincent, R.J.1
  • 74
    • 0013424644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chris Brown assumes that the 'morality of states' is the normative aspect of the idea of 'international society': Brown, International Relations Theory, p. 123.
    • International Relations Theory , pp. 123
    • Brown1
  • 76
    • 0003556319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 181. In his construction of a theory of international distributive justice, Beitz makes much use of the work of John Rawls. Given that Rawls has revised his original theory of justice in the light of communitarian criticism, it would be interesting to know how, if at all, Beitz might wish to revise his work. (This article was completed before the publication of the revised edition of Beitz's Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, 1999), which contains a new afterword.)
    • Political Theory and International Relations , pp. 181
    • Beitz1
  • 77
    • 0003556319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, which contains a new afterword
    • Ibid., p. 181. In his construction of a theory of international distributive justice, Beitz makes much use of the work of John Rawls. Given that Rawls has revised his original theory of justice in the light of communitarian criticism, it would be interesting to know how, if at all, Beitz might wish to revise his work. (This article was completed before the publication of the revised edition of Beitz's Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, 1999), which contains a new afterword.)
    • (1999) Beitz's Political Theory and International Relations
  • 79
    • 70350119864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De potestate civili
    • question 3, article 4, in A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds.)
    • Francisco de Vitoria, De Potestate Civili, question 3, article 4, in A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds.), Francisco de Vitoria: Political Writings , p. 40.
    • Francisco de Vitoria: Political Writings , pp. 40
    • De Vitoria, F.1
  • 80
    • 85037754289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De indis
    • question 3, article 1, A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds.)
    • Francisco de Vitoria, De Indis, question 3, article 1, in A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds.), Francisco de Vitoria: Political Writings, p. 281.
    • Francisco de Vitoria: Political Writings , pp. 281
    • De Vitoria, F.1
  • 81
    • 0004308743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • translated by John Fitzgerald Notre Dame, IN
    • Jacques Maritain, The Person and the Common Good, translated by John Fitzgerald (Notre Dame, IN, 1966), pp. 101, 50 and 51 (Maritain's emphasis). For a relevant discussion of Maritain see Michelle Watkins and Ralph McInerny, 'Jacques Maritain and the Rapprochment of Liberalism and Communitarianism', in K. Grasso, G. Bradley and R. Hunt (eds.), Catholicism, Liberalism and Communitarianism (Lanham, MD, 1995), pp. 151-72.
    • (1966) The Person and the Common Good , pp. 101
    • Maritain, J.1
  • 82
    • 0141991421 scopus 로고
    • Lanham, MD
    • Jacques Maritain, The Person and the Common Good, translated by John Fitzgerald (Notre Dame, IN, 1966), pp. 101, 50 and 51 (Maritain's emphasis). For a relevant discussion of Maritain see Michelle Watkins and Ralph McInerny, 'Jacques Maritain and the Rapprochment of Liberalism and Communitarianism', in K. Grasso, G. Bradley and R. Hunt (eds.), Catholicism, Liberalism and Communitarianism (Lanham, MD, 1995), pp. 151-72.
    • (1995) Catholicism, Liberalism and Communitarianism , pp. 151-172
    • Grasso, K.1    Bradley, G.2    Hunt, R.3
  • 83
    • 84917241137 scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitan confusions: A reply to Hoffman
    • Chris Brown, 'Cosmopolitan Confusions: A Reply to Hoffman', Paradigms, 2 (1988), p. 107.
    • (1988) Paradigms , vol.2 , pp. 107
    • Brown, C.1
  • 84
    • 85037753500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Pope John XXIII, Encyclical Letter, Pacem in Terris (London, 1965), paras. 140 and 141. The 'principle of subsidiary function' is outlined by Pope Pius XI in his 1931 Encyclical Letter, Quadragesimo Anno (London, 1960), in which he comments on the 1891 Encyclical Letter of Pope Leo XIII, Rerum Novarum, and seeks to establish the correct role of government in social and economic affairs. Pius XI says: 'just as it is wrong to withdraw from the individual and commit to a group what private enterprise and industry can accomplish, so too it is an injustice, a grave evil and a disturbance of right order, for a larger and higher association to arrogate to itself functions which can be performed efficiently by smaller and lower societies'. He continues: 'Let those in power, therefore, be convinced that the more faithfully this principle of subsidiary function be followed, and a graded hierarchical order exist between various associations, the greater will be both social authority and social efficiency, and the happier and more prosperous the condition of the commonwealth' (paragraphs 79 and 80).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.