메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 4, 2000, Pages 480-508

Five myths about pragmatism, or, against a second pragmatic acquiescence

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0034347434     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591700028004003     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (19)

References (109)
  • 1
    • 0002092540 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism (1907)
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • William James, Pragmatism (1907), in Pragmatism and the Meaning of Truth (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), 95.
    • (1978) Pragmatism and the Meaning of Truth , pp. 95
    • James, W.1
  • 2
    • 84936526619 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • These positions are most closely associated with Benjamin Barber and Richard Rorty, respectively. See, for example, Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), and Rorty, Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).
    • (1984) Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age
    • Barber1
  • 3
    • 0003900058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • These positions are most closely associated with Benjamin Barber and Richard Rorty, respectively. See, for example, Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), and Rorty, Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).
    • (1998) Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century America
    • Rorty1
  • 4
    • 0002820563 scopus 로고
    • Two dogmas of empiricism
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • W.V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism, "in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), 20-46. The essay first appeared in Philosophical Review in 1951. Two recent critiques of the notion of a "rediscovered" pragmatic tradition are found in Richard J. Bernstein, "The Resurgence of Pragmatism, "Social Research 59 (1992): 813-40, and Richard A. Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" Southern California Law Review 63 (1990): 1653-70.
    • (1953) From a Logical Point of View , pp. 20-46
    • Quine, W.V.O.1
  • 5
    • 53249114013 scopus 로고
    • W.V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism, "in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), 20-46. The essay first appeared in Philosophical Review in 1951. Two recent critiques of the notion of a "rediscovered" pragmatic tradition are found in Richard J. Bernstein, "The Resurgence of Pragmatism, "Social Research 59 (1992): 813-40, and Richard A. Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" Southern California Law Review 63 (1990): 1653-70.
    • (1951) Philosophical Review
  • 6
    • 77957568691 scopus 로고
    • The resurgence of pragmatism
    • W.V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism, "in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), 20-46. The essay first appeared in Philosophical Review in 1951. Two recent critiques of the notion of a "rediscovered" pragmatic tradition are found in Richard J. Bernstein, "The Resurgence of Pragmatism, "Social Research 59 (1992): 813-40, and Richard A. Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" Southern California Law Review 63 (1990): 1653-70.
    • (1992) Social Research , vol.59 , pp. 813-840
    • Bernstein, R.J.1
  • 7
    • 0002271337 scopus 로고
    • What has pragmatism to offer law?
    • W.V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism, "in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), 20-46. The essay first appeared in Philosophical Review in 1951. Two recent critiques of the notion of a "rediscovered" pragmatic tradition are found in Richard J. Bernstein, "The Resurgence of Pragmatism, "Social Research 59 (1992): 813-40, and Richard A. Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" Southern California Law Review 63 (1990): 1653-70.
    • (1990) Southern California Law Review , vol.63 , pp. 1653-1670
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 9
    • 84923478336 scopus 로고
    • "The pragmatic acquiescence" (1927)
    • Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • Dewey's reply to Mumford is found in "The Pragmatic Acquiescence" (1927), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1981-91), 3:145-51. Sidney Hook reports that Dewey vowed "never [to] forgive" Bertrand Russell for his role in propagating a similar view; a rare lapse, as Hook saw it, from his "genuine, constant and sustained, even … somewhat oppressive" goodness. Sidney Hook, "Some Memories of John Dewey, "in Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 106-7, 108. For his part, Russell professed "regret and surprise" at Dewey's hostile reaction, going on to say, "I am accustomed to having my opinions explained… as due to my connection with the British aristocracy, and I am quite willing to suppose that my views, like other men's, are influenced by social environment." A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1945), 827.
    • (1981) John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953 , vol.3 , pp. 145-151
    • Boydston, J.A.1
  • 10
    • 0002269805 scopus 로고
    • Some memories of John Dewey
    • New York: Basic Books
    • Dewey's reply to Mumford is found in "The Pragmatic Acquiescence" (1927), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1981-91), 3:145-51. Sidney Hook reports that Dewey vowed "never [to] forgive" Bertrand Russell for his role in propagating a similar view; a rare lapse, as Hook saw it, from his "genuine, constant and sustained, even … somewhat oppressive" goodness. Sidney Hook, "Some Memories of John Dewey, "in Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 106-7, 108. For his part, Russell professed "regret and surprise" at Dewey's hostile reaction, going on to say, "I am accustomed to having my opinions explained… as due to my connection with the British aristocracy, and I am quite willing to suppose that my views, like other men's, are influenced by social environment." A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1945), 827.
    • (1974) Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life , pp. 106-107
    • Hook, S.1
  • 11
    • 0004077535 scopus 로고
    • New York: Simon & Schuster
    • Dewey's reply to Mumford is found in "The Pragmatic Acquiescence" (1927), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1981-91), 3:145-51. Sidney Hook reports that Dewey vowed "never [to] forgive" Bertrand Russell for his role in propagating a similar view; a rare lapse, as Hook saw it, from his "genuine, constant and sustained, even … somewhat oppressive" goodness. Sidney Hook, "Some Memories of John Dewey, "in Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 106-7, 108. For his part, Russell professed "regret and surprise" at Dewey's hostile reaction, going on to say, "I am accustomed to having my opinions explained… as due to my connection with the British aristocracy, and I am quite willing to suppose that my views, like other men's, are influenced by social environment." A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1945), 827.
    • (1945) A History of Western Philosophy , pp. 827
  • 12
    • 0003546431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Knopf, chap. 14
    • Two notable examples of this line of argument are found in Richard Hofstadter, Anti-Intellectualism in American Life (New York: Knopf, 1962), chap. 14, and Christopher Lasch, The New Radicalism in America, 1889-1963: The Intellectual as a Social Type (New York: Knopf, 1965), chap. 5. On Dewey's opposition to the war, see Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), chap. 14.
    • (1962) Anti-Intellectualism in American Life
    • Hofstadter, R.1
  • 13
    • 0003857880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Knopf, chap. 5
    • Two notable examples of this line of argument are found in Richard Hofstadter, Anti-Intellectualism in American Life (New York: Knopf, 1962), chap. 14, and Christopher Lasch, The New Radicalism in America, 1889-1963: The Intellectual as a Social Type (New York: Knopf, 1965), chap. 5. On Dewey's opposition to the war, see Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), chap. 14.
    • (1965) The New Radicalism in America, 1889-1963: The Intellectual As a Social Type
    • Lasch, C.1
  • 14
    • 0004067080 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, chap. 14
    • Two notable examples of this line of argument are found in Richard Hofstadter, Anti-Intellectualism in American Life (New York: Knopf, 1962), chap. 14, and Christopher Lasch, The New Radicalism in America, 1889-1963: The Intellectual as a Social Type (New York: Knopf, 1965), chap. 5. On Dewey's opposition to the war, see Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), chap. 14.
    • (1991) John Dewey and American Democracy
    • Westbrook, R.B.1
  • 16
    • 0002350569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Idealizations, foundations, and social practices
    • ed. Seyla Benhabib Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Richard Rorty, "Idealizations, Foundations, and Social Practices, "in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 334.
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political , pp. 334
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 17
    • 84972770679 scopus 로고
    • One step forward, two steps back: Richard Rorty on liberal democracy and philosophy
    • quoted at 541
    • See, for example, Richard J. Bernstein, "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back: Richard Rorty on Liberal Democracy and Philosophy, "Political Theory 15 (1987): quoted at 541.
    • (1987) Political Theory , vol.15
    • Bernstein, R.J.1
  • 18
    • 85199533319 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • See, for example, Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981); Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy; Cornel West, The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989).
    • (1979) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 19
    • 0004235120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • See, for example, Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981); Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy; Cornel West, The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989).
    • (1981) Reason, Truth, and History
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 20
    • 84989359024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981); Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy; Cornel West, The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989).
    • John Dewey and American Democracy
    • Westbrook1
  • 21
    • 0003968693 scopus 로고
    • Madison: University of Wisconsin Press
    • See, for example, Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981); Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy; Cornel West, The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989).
    • (1989) The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism
    • West, C.1
  • 22
    • 84878140284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The quoted phrase is the subtitle of James's Pragmatism.
    • Pragmatism
    • James1
  • 23
    • 84929225642 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatic inquiry and social conflict: A critical reconstruction of dewey's model of democracy
    • Marion Smiley has argued, by contrast, that "political processes, and not scientific inquiry per se, enable Dewey to generate evaluative criteria out of social conflict." "Pragmatic Inquiry and Social Conflict: A Critical Reconstruction of Dewey's Model of Democracy, "Praxis International 9 (1990): 373.
    • (1990) Praxis International , vol.9 , pp. 373
    • Smiley, M.1
  • 24
    • 85164861867 scopus 로고
    • Los Angeles: University of California Press, chaps. 7-9
    • See, for example, Ian Shapiro, Political Criticism (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1990), chaps. 7-9.
    • (1990) Political Criticism
    • Shapiro, I.1
  • 25
    • 0001260436 scopus 로고
    • The priority of democracy to philosophy
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Richard Rorty, "The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy, "in Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 175-96.
    • (1991) Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers , vol.1 , pp. 175-196
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 26
    • 0002378879 scopus 로고
    • Dewey's naturalistic metaphysics
    • ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp and Lewis Edwin Hahn La Salle, IL: Open Court, James does not entirely escape censure; "too spontaneous and rare a person to be a good mirror of any general movement, "he is said to be "more representative of America in the past than in the future." (p. 247)
    • George Santayana, "Dewey's Naturalistic Metaphysics, "in The Philosophy of John Dewey, ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp and Lewis Edwin Hahn (La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1939), 247-48. James does not entirely escape censure; "too spontaneous and rare a person to be a good mirror of any general movement, "he is said to be "more representative of America in the past than in the future." (p. 247).
    • (1939) The Philosophy of John Dewey , pp. 247-248
    • Santayana, G.1
  • 27
    • 0038756039 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism
    • London: George Allen & Unwin
    • Bertrand Russell, "Pragmatism, "in Philosophical Essays (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1910), 110.
    • (1910) Philosophical Essays , pp. 110
    • Russell, B.1
  • 30
    • 0347845950 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism, relativism, and irrationalism
    • Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • Rorty, "Pragmatism, Relativism, and Irrationalism, "in Consequences of Pragmatism: Essays, 1972-1980 (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), 166.
    • (1982) Consequences of Pragmatism: Essays, 1972-1980 , pp. 166
    • Rorty1
  • 31
    • 0039356491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solidarity or objectivity?
    • Rorty, "Solidarity or Objectivity?" Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, 25; "Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism, "ibid., 198-99.
    • Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth , pp. 25
    • Rorty1
  • 32
    • 0002203899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Postmodernist bourgeois liberalism
    • Rorty, "Solidarity or Objectivity?" Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, 25; "Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism, "ibid., 198-99.
    • Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth , pp. 198-199
  • 33
    • 0040931347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction: Pragmatism and philosophy
    • Rorty, "Introduction: Pragmatism and Philosophy, "Consequences of Pragmatism, xxx.
    • Consequences of Pragmatism , pp. xxx
    • Rorty1
  • 34
    • 4243218248 scopus 로고
    • "The fixation of belief" (1877) and "How to make our ideas clear" (1878)
    • ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • This model is laid out by Peirce in what are now considered to be the founding papers of the pragmatic movement: "The Fixation of Belief" (1877) and "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (1878), in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1932-35), 5:223-71.
    • (1932) Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce , vol.5 , pp. 223-271
  • 35
    • 84923520631 scopus 로고
    • "Pragmatic america" (1922)
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, "Pragmatic America" (1922), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1976-83), 13:307.
    • (1976) John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924 , vol.13 , pp. 307
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 36
    • 0003386206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peirce makes a similarly unfavorable comparison between the "scientific" viewpoint and that of traditional philosophy in "The Fixation of Belief."
    • See especially Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920), Middle Works, 12:77-201. Peirce makes a similarly unfavorable comparison between the "scientific" viewpoint and that of traditional philosophy in "The Fixation of Belief."
    • Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920), Middle Works , vol.12 , pp. 77-201
    • Dewey1
  • 37
    • 85013283936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is not to deny that, as an empirical matter, the range of solutions considered will be limited to those with which we have some familiarity, but merely to point out that pragmatism does not require that we give greater normative weight to traditional approaches.
  • 40
    • 0003857880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lasch, New Radicalism in America, 14. Lasch offers a more balanced assessment of Dewey and pragmatism in The True and Only Heaven: Progress and Its Critics (New York: Norton, 1991), esp. chaps. 7-8.
    • New Radicalism in America , pp. 14
    • Lasch1
  • 41
    • 84936824205 scopus 로고
    • New York: Norton, esp. chaps. 7-8
    • Lasch, New Radicalism in America, 14. Lasch offers a more balanced assessment of Dewey and pragmatism in The True and Only Heaven: Progress and Its Critics (New York: Norton, 1991), esp. chaps. 7-8.
    • (1991) The True and Only Heaven: Progress and Its Critics
  • 42
    • 0004162070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Richard A. Posner, The Problems of Jurisprudence (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990); Rorty, "Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism, "202.
    • (1990) The Problems of Jurisprudence
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 43
    • 0002378883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richard A. Posner, The Problems of Jurisprudence (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990); Rorty, "Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism, "202.
    • Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism , pp. 202
    • Rorty1
  • 45
    • 0000695174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thugs and theorists: A reply to bernstein
    • Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists: A Reply to Bernstein, "Political Theory 15 (1987): 573.
    • (1987) Political Theory , vol.15 , pp. 573
    • Rorty1
  • 46
    • 0003214062 scopus 로고
    • Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'pragmatic acquiescence, '
    • ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes New York: Oxford University Press, n. 4
    • Robert Westbrook often fails to grasp this distinction, leading him, for example, to find Mumford's criticism of James "less misleading than his criticism of Dewey; insofar as the issue is 'acquiescence' to industrial capitalism, James was a mugwump, Dewey a radical." But Mumford does not discuss James's political views (or, for that matter, Dewey's) at all; he cites rather his "lack of comprehensive ideas" and his "cultural adolescence." Compare Westbrook, "Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'Pragmatic Acquiescence, '" in Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual, ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 420, n. 4, and Mumford, Golden Day, 93, 95. Rorty's effort to rebut the charge that his philosophical views provide an "apologia for the status quo" by putting forth an elaborate eight-point "political credo" similarly misses the thrust of the objection. Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists, "565-67, responding to Bernstein's "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back."
    • (1990) Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual , pp. 420
    • Westbrook1
  • 47
    • 0009925870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Westbrook often fails to grasp this distinction, leading him, for example, to find Mumford's criticism of James "less misleading than his criticism of Dewey; insofar as the issue is 'acquiescence' to industrial capitalism, James was a mugwump, Dewey a radical." But Mumford does not discuss James's political views (or, for that matter, Dewey's) at all; he cites rather his "lack of comprehensive ideas" and his "cultural adolescence." Compare Westbrook, "Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'Pragmatic Acquiescence, '" in Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual, ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 420, n. 4, and Mumford, Golden Day, 93, 95. Rorty's effort to rebut the charge that his philosophical views provide an "apologia for the status quo" by putting forth an elaborate eight-point "political credo" similarly misses the thrust of the objection. Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists, "565-67, responding to Bernstein's "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back."
    • Golden Day , pp. 93
    • Mumford1
  • 48
    • 0000695174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Westbrook often fails to grasp this distinction, leading him, for example, to find Mumford's criticism of James "less misleading than his criticism of Dewey; insofar as the issue is 'acquiescence' to industrial capitalism, James was a mugwump, Dewey a radical." But Mumford does not discuss James's political views (or, for that matter, Dewey's) at all; he cites rather his "lack of comprehensive ideas" and his "cultural adolescence." Compare Westbrook, "Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'Pragmatic Acquiescence, '" in Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual, ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 420, n. 4, and Mumford, Golden Day, 93, 95. Rorty's effort to rebut the charge that his philosophical views provide an "apologia for the status quo" by putting forth an elaborate eight-point "political credo" similarly misses the thrust of the objection. Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists, "565-67, responding to Bernstein's "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back."
    • Thugs and Theorists , pp. 565-567
    • Rorty1
  • 49
    • 84997907837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Westbrook often fails to grasp this distinction, leading him, for example, to find Mumford's criticism of James "less misleading than his criticism of Dewey; insofar as the issue is 'acquiescence' to industrial capitalism, James was a mugwump, Dewey a radical." But Mumford does not discuss James's political views (or, for that matter, Dewey's) at all; he cites rather his "lack of comprehensive ideas" and his "cultural adolescence." Compare Westbrook, "Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'Pragmatic Acquiescence, '" in Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual, ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 420, n. 4, and Mumford, Golden Day, 93, 95. Rorty's effort to rebut the charge that his philosophical views provide an "apologia for the status quo" by putting forth an elaborate eight-point "political credo" similarly misses the thrust of the objection. Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists, "565-67, responding to Bernstein's "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back."
    • One Step Forward, Two Steps Back
    • Bernstein1
  • 50
    • 5644252695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus Peirce's celebrated maxim: "The whole function of thought is to produce habits of action; and … whatever there is connected with a thought, but irrelevant to its purpose, is an accretion to it, but no part of it…. Thus, we come down to what is tangible and conceivably practical, as the root of every real distinction of thought, no matter how subtile it may be; and there is no distinction of meaning so fine as to consist in anything but a possible difference of practice." "How to Make Our Ideas Clear, "256-57.
    • How to Make Our Ideas Clear , pp. 256-257
  • 51
    • 4243231369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The future of liberalism" (1935)
    • Dewey, "The Future of Liberalism" (1935), Later Works, 11:293. Dewey's own radical critique of the social, political, and economic practices of his day is extensively documented in Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy. 35. Dewey, "Philosophy and Civilization" (1927), Later Works, 3:10.
    • Later Works , vol.11 , pp. 293
    • Dewey1
  • 52
    • 84989359024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dewey, "The Future of Liberalism" (1935), Later Works, 11:293. Dewey's own radical critique of the social, political, and economic practices of his day is extensively documented in Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy. 35. Dewey, "Philosophy and Civilization" (1927), Later Works, 3:10.
    • John Dewey and American Democracy , pp. 35
    • Westbrook1
  • 53
    • 4243241849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Philosophy and civilization" (1927)
    • Dewey, "The Future of Liberalism" (1935), Later Works, 11:293. Dewey's own radical critique of the social, political, and economic practices of his day is extensively documented in Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy. 35. Dewey, "Philosophy and Civilization" (1927), Later Works, 3:10.
    • Later Works , vol.3 , pp. 10
    • Dewey1
  • 55
    • 0040337335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • William James's conception of truth
    • Russell, "William James's Conception of Truth, "Philosophical Essays, 129.
    • Philosophical Essays , pp. 129
    • Russell1
  • 56
    • 0009157649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foundationalism and democracy
    • Benhabib
    • Benjamin R. Barber, "Foundationalism and Democracy, "in Benhabib, Democracy and Difference, 352. See also his Strong Democracy, esp. chaps. 6-8.
    • Democracy and Difference , pp. 352
    • Barber, B.R.1
  • 57
    • 84881894600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp. chaps. 6-8
    • Benjamin R. Barber, "Foundationalism and Democracy, "in Benhabib, Democracy and Difference, 352. See also his Strong Democracy, esp. chaps. 6-8.
    • Strong Democracy
  • 58
    • 84928458515 scopus 로고
    • Foundationalism and the structure of ethical justification
    • See, for example, Mark Timmons, "Foundationalism and the Structure of Ethical Justification, "Ethics 97 (1987): 595-609. Arthur Ripstein has offered a similar definition of political foundationalism: "Foundationalist political theories attempt to justify political institutions without presupposing any political considerations." However, he goes on to insist that foundations "avoid presuming anything accidental to some particular social setting" and that they "justify institutions in terms that nobody can reject"; conditions that, as I argue below, are adventitious to his original formulation. Ripstein, "Foundationalism in Political Theory, "Philosophy and Public Affairs 16(1987): 115, 116.
    • (1987) Ethics , vol.97 , pp. 595-609
    • Timmons, M.1
  • 59
    • 84925682406 scopus 로고
    • Foundationalism in political theory
    • See, for example, Mark Timmons, "Foundationalism and the Structure of Ethical Justification, "Ethics 97 (1987): 595-609. Arthur Ripstein has offered a similar definition of political foundationalism: "Foundationalist political theories attempt to justify political institutions without presupposing any political considerations." However, he goes on to insist that foundations "avoid presuming anything accidental to some particular social setting" and that they "justify institutions in terms that nobody can reject"; conditions that, as I argue below, are adventitious to his original formulation. Ripstein, "Foundationalism in Political Theory, "Philosophy and Public Affairs 16(1987): 115, 116.
    • (1987) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.16 , pp. 115
    • Ripstein1
  • 61
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis removed
    • In James's words, pragmatism entails "the attitude of looking away from first things, principles, 'categories, ' supposed necessities; and of looking toward last things, fruits, consequences, facts." Pragmatism, 32 (emphasis removed). See also Dewey, The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action (1929), Later Works, vol. 4.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 32
  • 63
    • 0004224658 scopus 로고
    • ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, trans. Denis Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe New York: Basil Blackwell
    • See, for example, Ludwig Wittgenstein's On Certainty, ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, trans. Denis Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1969), and the discussion in Williams, Unnatural Doubts, 22 ff.
    • (1969) Certainty
    • Wittgenstein, L.1
  • 64
    • 0039395203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 22 ff
    • See, for example, Ludwig Wittgenstein's On Certainty, ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, trans. Denis Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1969), and the discussion in Williams, Unnatural Doubts, 22 ff.
    • Unnatural Doubts
    • Williams1
  • 66
    • 0004347851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As if, as Peirce sardonically remarks, "to start an inquiry it was only necessary to utter a question." Ibid., 232.
    • Fixation of Belief , pp. 232
  • 67
    • 0345867599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy, philosophy, and justification
    • Amy Gutmann has likewise argued that "foundationalism in political philosophy … is the claim that justification must rest upon truths about human nature, human rights, rationality, or politics that are self-evident, rationally incontestable, or axiomatic." "Democracy, Philosophy, and Justification, "in Benhabib, Democracy and Difference, 340.
    • Democracy and Difference , pp. 340
    • Benhabib1
  • 68
    • 0002214963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A proposition is neither true because it stands fast nor stands fast because it is true
    • As Williams puts it, paraphrasing Wittgenstein, "a proposition is neither true because it stands fast nor stands fast because it is true"; Unnatural Doubts, 124. Williams is uncertain whether to call this view "foundationalist" or not, because his critique of skepticism requires that he equate foundationalism with what he calls "epistemological realism." See ibid., 114-15, 124, 221-24.
    • Unnatural Doubts , pp. 124
    • Wittgenstein1
  • 69
    • 0039395203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Williams puts it, paraphrasing Wittgenstein, "a proposition is neither true because it stands fast nor stands fast because it is true"; Unnatural Doubts, 124. Williams is uncertain whether to call this view "foundationalist" or not, because his critique of skepticism requires that he equate foundationalism with what he calls "epistemological realism." See ibid., 114-15, 124, 221-24.
    • Unnatural Doubts , pp. 114-115
  • 71
    • 0002100509 scopus 로고
    • John Dewey's philosophy
    • Bourne, "John Dewey's Philosophy, "New Republic 2 (1915): 154.
    • (1915) New Republic , vol.2 , pp. 154
    • Bourne1
  • 72
    • 4243325278 scopus 로고
    • "Conscience and intelligence in war" (1917)
    • Indianapolis: Hackett
    • In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
    • (1993) John Dewey: The Political Writings , pp. 200
    • Morris, D.1    Shapiro, I.2
  • 73
    • 84923759624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
    • John Dewey: The Political Writings , pp. 199
  • 74
    • 0002203902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The war and the intellectuals
    • In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
    • Collected Essays , pp. 12
  • 75
    • 84875314405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
    • Twilight of Idols , pp. 62
  • 76
    • 0002378885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
    • Conscience and Intelligence in War , pp. 201
  • 77
    • 84989359024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chaps. 7-8
    • In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
    • John Dewey and American Democracy
    • Westbrook1
  • 79
    • 0030511484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" 1659, 1670. For a critique of Posner's view of pragmatism, see Jack Knight and James Johnson, "Political Consequences of Pragmatism, "Political Theory 24 (1996): 68-96.
    • What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law? , pp. 1659
    • Posner1
  • 80
    • 0030511484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political consequences of pragmatism
    • Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" 1659, 1670. For a critique of Posner's view of pragmatism, see Jack Knight and James Johnson, "Political Consequences of Pragmatism, "Political Theory 24 (1996): 68-96.
    • (1996) Political Theory , vol.24 , pp. 68-96
    • Knight, J.1    Johnson, J.2
  • 81
    • 0004347851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, among many possible examples, Peirce, "Fixation of Belief'; James, Pragmatism, chap. 2; Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy. 53. James, Pragmatism, 32, 137.
    • Fixation of Belief
    • Peirce1
  • 82
    • 84878140284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • See, among many possible examples, Peirce, "Fixation of Belief'; James, Pragmatism, chap. 2; Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy. 53. James, Pragmatism, 32, 137.
    • Pragmatism
    • James1
  • 83
    • 0004222329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, among many possible examples, Peirce, "Fixation of Belief'; James, Pragmatism, chap. 2; Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy. 53. James, Pragmatism, 32, 137.
    • Reconstruction in Philosophy , pp. 53
    • Dewey1
  • 84
    • 84878140284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, among many possible examples, Peirce, "Fixation of Belief'; James, Pragmatism, chap. 2; Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy. 53. James, Pragmatism, 32, 137.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 32
    • James1
  • 85
    • 0002078661 scopus 로고
    • Neutrality in political science
    • New York: Cambridge University Press, Taylor does not link this idea to foundationalism, as I have here
    • Charles Taylor has shown that explanatory frameworks inevitably "secrete a certain value position": "The framework gives us as it were the geography of the range of phenomena in question, it tells us how they can vary, what are the major dimensions of variation. But since we are dealing with matters which are of great importance to human beings, a given map will have, as it were, its own built-in value slope. That is to say, a given dimension of variation will usually determine for itself how we are to judge of good and bad, because of its relation to obvious human wants and needs." "Neutrality in Political Science, "in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 73. Taylor does not link this idea to foundationalism, as I have here.
    • (1985) Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers , vol.2 , pp. 73
  • 87
    • 0004347851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus Peirce: "Scientific investigation has had the most wonderful triumphs in the way of settling opinion. These afford the explanation of my not doubting the method or the hypothesis which it supposes; and not having any doubt, nor believing that anybody else whom I could influence has, it would be the merest babble for me to say more about it. If there be anybody with a living doubt upon the subject, let him consider it." "Fixation of Belief, "244.
    • Fixation of Belief , pp. 244
  • 88
    • 0033238820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Experience as experiment: Some consequences of pragmatism for democratic theory
    • I begin to address these issues in my "Experience as Experiment: Some Consequences of Pragmatism for Democratic Theory, "American Journal of Political Science 43 (1999): 542-65.
    • (1999) American Journal of Political Science , vol.43 , pp. 542-565
  • 89
    • 85013277713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It follows that there are no de jure barriers to participation in scientific discourse. The fact that there are nearly insurmountable de facto barriers reflects, as I have suggested, the trade-off (necessary in principle but in need of justification in its particulars) between the ideal of openness and the need to define a manageable field of inquiry.
  • 90
    • 0004028916 scopus 로고
    • reprint, New York: Free Press, is an elegant attempt to argue otherwise
    • Walter Lippmann's Public Opinion (1922; reprint, New York: Free Press, 1965) is an elegant attempt to argue otherwise.
    • (1922) Public Opinion
    • Lippmann, W.1
  • 91
    • 84989359024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 402 ff
    • See Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, 402 ff. Dewey's most significant engagement with logical positivism, in the person of A. J. Ayer, came in his Theory of Valuation (1939), Later Works, 13:189-251. Ironically, this highly critical assessment was originally published as a contribution to Otto Neurath's positivist flagship, the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science.
    • John Dewey and American Democracy
    • Westbrook1
  • 92
    • 0342443204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, 402 ff. Dewey's most significant engagement with logical positivism, in the person of A. J. Ayer, came in his Theory of Valuation (1939), Later Works, 13:189-251. Ironically, this highly critical assessment was originally published as a contribution to Otto Neurath's positivist flagship, the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science.
    • Theory of Valuation (1939), Later Works , vol.13 , pp. 189-251
    • Ayer, A.J.1
  • 93
    • 16044364211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, 402 ff. Dewey's most significant engagement with logical positivism, in the person of A. J. Ayer, came in his Theory of Valuation (1939), Later Works, 13:189-251. Ironically, this highly critical assessment was originally published as a contribution to Otto Neurath's positivist flagship, the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science.
    • The International Encyclopedia of Unified Science
    • Neurath, O.1
  • 94
  • 97
    • 0003945869 scopus 로고
    • reprint, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, though it is somewhat unclear whether he is willing to endorse some of the more radical implications that have been drawn from it
    • The paradigmatic example of this "sociological" approach to the study of scientific inquiry is Thomas S. Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (1962; reprint, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), though it is somewhat unclear whether he is willing to endorse some of the more radical implications that have been drawn from it.
    • (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d Ed.
    • Kuhn, T.S.1
  • 98
    • 0002479337 scopus 로고
    • Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes
    • ed. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave New York: Cambridge University Press
    • For a theoretical reconstruction of scientific inquiry that is broadly consonant with this view, see Imre Lakatos, "Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, "in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, ed. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1970), 91-195.
    • (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge , pp. 91-195
    • Lakatos, I.1
  • 99
    • 0004247997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the central claim of Dewey's Theory of Valuation. See also Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, chap. 6.
    • Theory of Valuation
    • Dewey1
  • 100
    • 0004235120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 6
    • This is the central claim of Dewey's Theory of Valuation. See also Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, chap. 6.
    • Reason, Truth and History
    • Putnam1
  • 101
    • 0002378891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and for an historical account
    • See my "Experience as Experiment, "and for an historical account, see Edward A. Purcell Jr., The Crisis of Democratic Theory: Scientific Naturalism and the Problem of Value (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1973).
    • Experience as Experiment
  • 107
    • 84954666676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hilary Putnam defines "metaphysical realism" as that position which "view[s] the aim of science simply as trying to get our notional world to 'match' the world in itself." Reason, Truth and History, 134.
    • Reason, Truth and History , pp. 134
  • 108
    • 0002378893 scopus 로고
    • Philosophy and democracy
    • As Dewey puts it, "How shall we read what we call reality … so that we may essay our deepest political and social problems with a conviction that they are to a reasonable extent sanctioned and sustained by the nature of things?" "Philosophy and Democracy" (1919), Middle Works, 11:48.
    • (1919) Middle Works , vol.11 , pp. 48
  • 109
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press, lecture 1
    • See, for example, John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), lecture 1.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.