-
1
-
-
0002092540
-
Pragmatism (1907)
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
William James, Pragmatism (1907), in Pragmatism and the Meaning of Truth (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), 95.
-
(1978)
Pragmatism and the Meaning of Truth
, pp. 95
-
-
James, W.1
-
2
-
-
84936526619
-
-
Berkeley: University of California Press
-
These positions are most closely associated with Benjamin Barber and Richard Rorty, respectively. See, for example, Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), and Rorty, Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).
-
(1984)
Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age
-
-
Barber1
-
3
-
-
0003900058
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
These positions are most closely associated with Benjamin Barber and Richard Rorty, respectively. See, for example, Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), and Rorty, Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).
-
(1998)
Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century America
-
-
Rorty1
-
4
-
-
0002820563
-
Two dogmas of empiricism
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
W.V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism, "in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), 20-46. The essay first appeared in Philosophical Review in 1951. Two recent critiques of the notion of a "rediscovered" pragmatic tradition are found in Richard J. Bernstein, "The Resurgence of Pragmatism, "Social Research 59 (1992): 813-40, and Richard A. Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" Southern California Law Review 63 (1990): 1653-70.
-
(1953)
From a Logical Point of View
, pp. 20-46
-
-
Quine, W.V.O.1
-
5
-
-
53249114013
-
-
W.V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism, "in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), 20-46. The essay first appeared in Philosophical Review in 1951. Two recent critiques of the notion of a "rediscovered" pragmatic tradition are found in Richard J. Bernstein, "The Resurgence of Pragmatism, "Social Research 59 (1992): 813-40, and Richard A. Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" Southern California Law Review 63 (1990): 1653-70.
-
(1951)
Philosophical Review
-
-
-
6
-
-
77957568691
-
The resurgence of pragmatism
-
W.V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism, "in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), 20-46. The essay first appeared in Philosophical Review in 1951. Two recent critiques of the notion of a "rediscovered" pragmatic tradition are found in Richard J. Bernstein, "The Resurgence of Pragmatism, "Social Research 59 (1992): 813-40, and Richard A. Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" Southern California Law Review 63 (1990): 1653-70.
-
(1992)
Social Research
, vol.59
, pp. 813-840
-
-
Bernstein, R.J.1
-
7
-
-
0002271337
-
What has pragmatism to offer law?
-
W.V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism, "in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953), 20-46. The essay first appeared in Philosophical Review in 1951. Two recent critiques of the notion of a "rediscovered" pragmatic tradition are found in Richard J. Bernstein, "The Resurgence of Pragmatism, "Social Research 59 (1992): 813-40, and Richard A. Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" Southern California Law Review 63 (1990): 1653-70.
-
(1990)
Southern California Law Review
, vol.63
, pp. 1653-1670
-
-
Posner, R.A.1
-
9
-
-
84923478336
-
"The pragmatic acquiescence" (1927)
-
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
-
Dewey's reply to Mumford is found in "The Pragmatic Acquiescence" (1927), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1981-91), 3:145-51. Sidney Hook reports that Dewey vowed "never [to] forgive" Bertrand Russell for his role in propagating a similar view; a rare lapse, as Hook saw it, from his "genuine, constant and sustained, even … somewhat oppressive" goodness. Sidney Hook, "Some Memories of John Dewey, "in Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 106-7, 108. For his part, Russell professed "regret and surprise" at Dewey's hostile reaction, going on to say, "I am accustomed to having my opinions explained… as due to my connection with the British aristocracy, and I am quite willing to suppose that my views, like other men's, are influenced by social environment." A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1945), 827.
-
(1981)
John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953
, vol.3
, pp. 145-151
-
-
Boydston, J.A.1
-
10
-
-
0002269805
-
Some memories of John Dewey
-
New York: Basic Books
-
Dewey's reply to Mumford is found in "The Pragmatic Acquiescence" (1927), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1981-91), 3:145-51. Sidney Hook reports that Dewey vowed "never [to] forgive" Bertrand Russell for his role in propagating a similar view; a rare lapse, as Hook saw it, from his "genuine, constant and sustained, even … somewhat oppressive" goodness. Sidney Hook, "Some Memories of John Dewey, "in Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 106-7, 108. For his part, Russell professed "regret and surprise" at Dewey's hostile reaction, going on to say, "I am accustomed to having my opinions explained… as due to my connection with the British aristocracy, and I am quite willing to suppose that my views, like other men's, are influenced by social environment." A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1945), 827.
-
(1974)
Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life
, pp. 106-107
-
-
Hook, S.1
-
11
-
-
0004077535
-
-
New York: Simon & Schuster
-
Dewey's reply to Mumford is found in "The Pragmatic Acquiescence" (1927), in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925-1953, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1981-91), 3:145-51. Sidney Hook reports that Dewey vowed "never [to] forgive" Bertrand Russell for his role in propagating a similar view; a rare lapse, as Hook saw it, from his "genuine, constant and sustained, even … somewhat oppressive" goodness. Sidney Hook, "Some Memories of John Dewey, "in Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 106-7, 108. For his part, Russell professed "regret and surprise" at Dewey's hostile reaction, going on to say, "I am accustomed to having my opinions explained… as due to my connection with the British aristocracy, and I am quite willing to suppose that my views, like other men's, are influenced by social environment." A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1945), 827.
-
(1945)
A History of Western Philosophy
, pp. 827
-
-
-
12
-
-
0003546431
-
-
New York: Knopf, chap. 14
-
Two notable examples of this line of argument are found in Richard Hofstadter, Anti-Intellectualism in American Life (New York: Knopf, 1962), chap. 14, and Christopher Lasch, The New Radicalism in America, 1889-1963: The Intellectual as a Social Type (New York: Knopf, 1965), chap. 5. On Dewey's opposition to the war, see Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), chap. 14.
-
(1962)
Anti-Intellectualism in American Life
-
-
Hofstadter, R.1
-
13
-
-
0003857880
-
-
New York: Knopf, chap. 5
-
Two notable examples of this line of argument are found in Richard Hofstadter, Anti-Intellectualism in American Life (New York: Knopf, 1962), chap. 14, and Christopher Lasch, The New Radicalism in America, 1889-1963: The Intellectual as a Social Type (New York: Knopf, 1965), chap. 5. On Dewey's opposition to the war, see Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), chap. 14.
-
(1965)
The New Radicalism in America, 1889-1963: The Intellectual As a Social Type
-
-
Lasch, C.1
-
14
-
-
0004067080
-
-
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, chap. 14
-
Two notable examples of this line of argument are found in Richard Hofstadter, Anti-Intellectualism in American Life (New York: Knopf, 1962), chap. 14, and Christopher Lasch, The New Radicalism in America, 1889-1963: The Intellectual as a Social Type (New York: Knopf, 1965), chap. 5. On Dewey's opposition to the war, see Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), chap. 14.
-
(1991)
John Dewey and American Democracy
-
-
Westbrook, R.B.1
-
16
-
-
0002350569
-
Idealizations, foundations, and social practices
-
ed. Seyla Benhabib Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
Richard Rorty, "Idealizations, Foundations, and Social Practices, "in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 334.
-
(1996)
Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political
, pp. 334
-
-
Rorty, R.1
-
17
-
-
84972770679
-
One step forward, two steps back: Richard Rorty on liberal democracy and philosophy
-
quoted at 541
-
See, for example, Richard J. Bernstein, "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back: Richard Rorty on Liberal Democracy and Philosophy, "Political Theory 15 (1987): quoted at 541.
-
(1987)
Political Theory
, vol.15
-
-
Bernstein, R.J.1
-
18
-
-
85199533319
-
-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
See, for example, Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981); Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy; Cornel West, The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989).
-
(1979)
Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature
-
-
Rorty, R.1
-
19
-
-
0004235120
-
-
New York: Cambridge University Press
-
See, for example, Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981); Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy; Cornel West, The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989).
-
(1981)
Reason, Truth, and History
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
20
-
-
84989359024
-
-
See, for example, Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981); Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy; Cornel West, The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989).
-
John Dewey and American Democracy
-
-
Westbrook1
-
21
-
-
0003968693
-
-
Madison: University of Wisconsin Press
-
See, for example, Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981); Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy; Cornel West, The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989).
-
(1989)
The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism
-
-
West, C.1
-
22
-
-
84878140284
-
-
The quoted phrase is the subtitle of James's Pragmatism.
-
Pragmatism
-
-
James1
-
23
-
-
84929225642
-
Pragmatic inquiry and social conflict: A critical reconstruction of dewey's model of democracy
-
Marion Smiley has argued, by contrast, that "political processes, and not scientific inquiry per se, enable Dewey to generate evaluative criteria out of social conflict." "Pragmatic Inquiry and Social Conflict: A Critical Reconstruction of Dewey's Model of Democracy, "Praxis International 9 (1990): 373.
-
(1990)
Praxis International
, vol.9
, pp. 373
-
-
Smiley, M.1
-
24
-
-
85164861867
-
-
Los Angeles: University of California Press, chaps. 7-9
-
See, for example, Ian Shapiro, Political Criticism (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1990), chaps. 7-9.
-
(1990)
Political Criticism
-
-
Shapiro, I.1
-
25
-
-
0001260436
-
The priority of democracy to philosophy
-
New York: Cambridge University Press
-
Richard Rorty, "The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy, "in Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 175-96.
-
(1991)
Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers
, vol.1
, pp. 175-196
-
-
Rorty, R.1
-
26
-
-
0002378879
-
Dewey's naturalistic metaphysics
-
ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp and Lewis Edwin Hahn La Salle, IL: Open Court, James does not entirely escape censure; "too spontaneous and rare a person to be a good mirror of any general movement, "he is said to be "more representative of America in the past than in the future." (p. 247)
-
George Santayana, "Dewey's Naturalistic Metaphysics, "in The Philosophy of John Dewey, ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp and Lewis Edwin Hahn (La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1939), 247-48. James does not entirely escape censure; "too spontaneous and rare a person to be a good mirror of any general movement, "he is said to be "more representative of America in the past than in the future." (p. 247).
-
(1939)
The Philosophy of John Dewey
, pp. 247-248
-
-
Santayana, G.1
-
27
-
-
0038756039
-
Pragmatism
-
London: George Allen & Unwin
-
Bertrand Russell, "Pragmatism, "in Philosophical Essays (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1910), 110.
-
(1910)
Philosophical Essays
, pp. 110
-
-
Russell, B.1
-
30
-
-
0347845950
-
Pragmatism, relativism, and irrationalism
-
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
-
Rorty, "Pragmatism, Relativism, and Irrationalism, "in Consequences of Pragmatism: Essays, 1972-1980 (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), 166.
-
(1982)
Consequences of Pragmatism: Essays, 1972-1980
, pp. 166
-
-
Rorty1
-
31
-
-
0039356491
-
Solidarity or objectivity?
-
Rorty, "Solidarity or Objectivity?" Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, 25; "Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism, "ibid., 198-99.
-
Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth
, pp. 25
-
-
Rorty1
-
32
-
-
0002203899
-
Postmodernist bourgeois liberalism
-
Rorty, "Solidarity or Objectivity?" Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, 25; "Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism, "ibid., 198-99.
-
Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth
, pp. 198-199
-
-
-
33
-
-
0040931347
-
Introduction: Pragmatism and philosophy
-
Rorty, "Introduction: Pragmatism and Philosophy, "Consequences of Pragmatism, xxx.
-
Consequences of Pragmatism
, pp. xxx
-
-
Rorty1
-
34
-
-
4243218248
-
"The fixation of belief" (1877) and "How to make our ideas clear" (1878)
-
ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
This model is laid out by Peirce in what are now considered to be the founding papers of the pragmatic movement: "The Fixation of Belief" (1877) and "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (1878), in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1932-35), 5:223-71.
-
(1932)
Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce
, vol.5
, pp. 223-271
-
-
-
35
-
-
84923520631
-
"Pragmatic america" (1922)
-
ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
-
John Dewey, "Pragmatic America" (1922), in John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1976-83), 13:307.
-
(1976)
John Dewey: The Middle Works, 1899-1924
, vol.13
, pp. 307
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
36
-
-
0003386206
-
-
Peirce makes a similarly unfavorable comparison between the "scientific" viewpoint and that of traditional philosophy in "The Fixation of Belief."
-
See especially Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920), Middle Works, 12:77-201. Peirce makes a similarly unfavorable comparison between the "scientific" viewpoint and that of traditional philosophy in "The Fixation of Belief."
-
Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920), Middle Works
, vol.12
, pp. 77-201
-
-
Dewey1
-
37
-
-
85013283936
-
-
note
-
This is not to deny that, as an empirical matter, the range of solutions considered will be limited to those with which we have some familiarity, but merely to point out that pragmatism does not require that we give greater normative weight to traditional approaches.
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
0003857880
-
-
Lasch, New Radicalism in America, 14. Lasch offers a more balanced assessment of Dewey and pragmatism in The True and Only Heaven: Progress and Its Critics (New York: Norton, 1991), esp. chaps. 7-8.
-
New Radicalism in America
, pp. 14
-
-
Lasch1
-
41
-
-
84936824205
-
-
New York: Norton, esp. chaps. 7-8
-
Lasch, New Radicalism in America, 14. Lasch offers a more balanced assessment of Dewey and pragmatism in The True and Only Heaven: Progress and Its Critics (New York: Norton, 1991), esp. chaps. 7-8.
-
(1991)
The True and Only Heaven: Progress and Its Critics
-
-
-
42
-
-
0004162070
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Richard A. Posner, The Problems of Jurisprudence (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990); Rorty, "Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism, "202.
-
(1990)
The Problems of Jurisprudence
-
-
Posner, R.A.1
-
43
-
-
0002378883
-
-
Richard A. Posner, The Problems of Jurisprudence (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990); Rorty, "Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism, "202.
-
Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism
, pp. 202
-
-
Rorty1
-
45
-
-
0000695174
-
Thugs and theorists: A reply to bernstein
-
Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists: A Reply to Bernstein, "Political Theory 15 (1987): 573.
-
(1987)
Political Theory
, vol.15
, pp. 573
-
-
Rorty1
-
46
-
-
0003214062
-
Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'pragmatic acquiescence, '
-
ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes New York: Oxford University Press, n. 4
-
Robert Westbrook often fails to grasp this distinction, leading him, for example, to find Mumford's criticism of James "less misleading than his criticism of Dewey; insofar as the issue is 'acquiescence' to industrial capitalism, James was a mugwump, Dewey a radical." But Mumford does not discuss James's political views (or, for that matter, Dewey's) at all; he cites rather his "lack of comprehensive ideas" and his "cultural adolescence." Compare Westbrook, "Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'Pragmatic Acquiescence, '" in Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual, ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 420, n. 4, and Mumford, Golden Day, 93, 95. Rorty's effort to rebut the charge that his philosophical views provide an "apologia for the status quo" by putting forth an elaborate eight-point "political credo" similarly misses the thrust of the objection. Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists, "565-67, responding to Bernstein's "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back."
-
(1990)
Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual
, pp. 420
-
-
Westbrook1
-
47
-
-
0009925870
-
-
Robert Westbrook often fails to grasp this distinction, leading him, for example, to find Mumford's criticism of James "less misleading than his criticism of Dewey; insofar as the issue is 'acquiescence' to industrial capitalism, James was a mugwump, Dewey a radical." But Mumford does not discuss James's political views (or, for that matter, Dewey's) at all; he cites rather his "lack of comprehensive ideas" and his "cultural adolescence." Compare Westbrook, "Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'Pragmatic Acquiescence, '" in Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual, ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 420, n. 4, and Mumford, Golden Day, 93, 95. Rorty's effort to rebut the charge that his philosophical views provide an "apologia for the status quo" by putting forth an elaborate eight-point "political credo" similarly misses the thrust of the objection. Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists, "565-67, responding to Bernstein's "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back."
-
Golden Day
, pp. 93
-
-
Mumford1
-
48
-
-
0000695174
-
-
Robert Westbrook often fails to grasp this distinction, leading him, for example, to find Mumford's criticism of James "less misleading than his criticism of Dewey; insofar as the issue is 'acquiescence' to industrial capitalism, James was a mugwump, Dewey a radical." But Mumford does not discuss James's political views (or, for that matter, Dewey's) at all; he cites rather his "lack of comprehensive ideas" and his "cultural adolescence." Compare Westbrook, "Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'Pragmatic Acquiescence, '" in Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual, ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 420, n. 4, and Mumford, Golden Day, 93, 95. Rorty's effort to rebut the charge that his philosophical views provide an "apologia for the status quo" by putting forth an elaborate eight-point "political credo" similarly misses the thrust of the objection. Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists, "565-67, responding to Bernstein's "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back."
-
Thugs and Theorists
, pp. 565-567
-
-
Rorty1
-
49
-
-
84997907837
-
-
Robert Westbrook often fails to grasp this distinction, leading him, for example, to find Mumford's criticism of James "less misleading than his criticism of Dewey; insofar as the issue is 'acquiescence' to industrial capitalism, James was a mugwump, Dewey a radical." But Mumford does not discuss James's political views (or, for that matter, Dewey's) at all; he cites rather his "lack of comprehensive ideas" and his "cultural adolescence." Compare Westbrook, "Lewis Mumford, John Dewey, and the 'Pragmatic Acquiescence, '" in Lewis Mumford: Public Intellectual, ed. Thomas and Agatha Hughes (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 420, n. 4, and Mumford, Golden Day, 93, 95. Rorty's effort to rebut the charge that his philosophical views provide an "apologia for the status quo" by putting forth an elaborate eight-point "political credo" similarly misses the thrust of the objection. Rorty, "Thugs and Theorists, "565-67, responding to Bernstein's "One Step Forward, Two Steps Back."
-
One Step Forward, Two Steps Back
-
-
Bernstein1
-
50
-
-
5644252695
-
-
Thus Peirce's celebrated maxim: "The whole function of thought is to produce habits of action; and … whatever there is connected with a thought, but irrelevant to its purpose, is an accretion to it, but no part of it…. Thus, we come down to what is tangible and conceivably practical, as the root of every real distinction of thought, no matter how subtile it may be; and there is no distinction of meaning so fine as to consist in anything but a possible difference of practice." "How to Make Our Ideas Clear, "256-57.
-
How to Make Our Ideas Clear
, pp. 256-257
-
-
-
51
-
-
4243231369
-
"The future of liberalism" (1935)
-
Dewey, "The Future of Liberalism" (1935), Later Works, 11:293. Dewey's own radical critique of the social, political, and economic practices of his day is extensively documented in Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy. 35. Dewey, "Philosophy and Civilization" (1927), Later Works, 3:10.
-
Later Works
, vol.11
, pp. 293
-
-
Dewey1
-
52
-
-
84989359024
-
-
Dewey, "The Future of Liberalism" (1935), Later Works, 11:293. Dewey's own radical critique of the social, political, and economic practices of his day is extensively documented in Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy. 35. Dewey, "Philosophy and Civilization" (1927), Later Works, 3:10.
-
John Dewey and American Democracy
, pp. 35
-
-
Westbrook1
-
53
-
-
4243241849
-
"Philosophy and civilization" (1927)
-
Dewey, "The Future of Liberalism" (1935), Later Works, 11:293. Dewey's own radical critique of the social, political, and economic practices of his day is extensively documented in Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy. 35. Dewey, "Philosophy and Civilization" (1927), Later Works, 3:10.
-
Later Works
, vol.3
, pp. 10
-
-
Dewey1
-
55
-
-
0040337335
-
William James's conception of truth
-
Russell, "William James's Conception of Truth, "Philosophical Essays, 129.
-
Philosophical Essays
, pp. 129
-
-
Russell1
-
56
-
-
0009157649
-
Foundationalism and democracy
-
Benhabib
-
Benjamin R. Barber, "Foundationalism and Democracy, "in Benhabib, Democracy and Difference, 352. See also his Strong Democracy, esp. chaps. 6-8.
-
Democracy and Difference
, pp. 352
-
-
Barber, B.R.1
-
57
-
-
84881894600
-
-
esp. chaps. 6-8
-
Benjamin R. Barber, "Foundationalism and Democracy, "in Benhabib, Democracy and Difference, 352. See also his Strong Democracy, esp. chaps. 6-8.
-
Strong Democracy
-
-
-
58
-
-
84928458515
-
Foundationalism and the structure of ethical justification
-
See, for example, Mark Timmons, "Foundationalism and the Structure of Ethical Justification, "Ethics 97 (1987): 595-609. Arthur Ripstein has offered a similar definition of political foundationalism: "Foundationalist political theories attempt to justify political institutions without presupposing any political considerations." However, he goes on to insist that foundations "avoid presuming anything accidental to some particular social setting" and that they "justify institutions in terms that nobody can reject"; conditions that, as I argue below, are adventitious to his original formulation. Ripstein, "Foundationalism in Political Theory, "Philosophy and Public Affairs 16(1987): 115, 116.
-
(1987)
Ethics
, vol.97
, pp. 595-609
-
-
Timmons, M.1
-
59
-
-
84925682406
-
Foundationalism in political theory
-
See, for example, Mark Timmons, "Foundationalism and the Structure of Ethical Justification, "Ethics 97 (1987): 595-609. Arthur Ripstein has offered a similar definition of political foundationalism: "Foundationalist political theories attempt to justify political institutions without presupposing any political considerations." However, he goes on to insist that foundations "avoid presuming anything accidental to some particular social setting" and that they "justify institutions in terms that nobody can reject"; conditions that, as I argue below, are adventitious to his original formulation. Ripstein, "Foundationalism in Political Theory, "Philosophy and Public Affairs 16(1987): 115, 116.
-
(1987)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.16
, pp. 115
-
-
Ripstein1
-
61
-
-
0004275191
-
-
emphasis removed
-
In James's words, pragmatism entails "the attitude of looking away from first things, principles, 'categories, ' supposed necessities; and of looking toward last things, fruits, consequences, facts." Pragmatism, 32 (emphasis removed). See also Dewey, The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action (1929), Later Works, vol. 4.
-
Pragmatism
, pp. 32
-
-
-
62
-
-
85013336457
-
-
In James's words, pragmatism entails "the attitude of looking away from first things, principles, 'categories, ' supposed necessities; and of looking toward last things, fruits, consequences, facts." Pragmatism, 32 (emphasis removed). See also Dewey, The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action (1929), Later Works, vol. 4.
-
The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action (1929), Later Works
, vol.4
-
-
Dewey1
-
63
-
-
0004224658
-
-
ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, trans. Denis Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe New York: Basil Blackwell
-
See, for example, Ludwig Wittgenstein's On Certainty, ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, trans. Denis Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1969), and the discussion in Williams, Unnatural Doubts, 22 ff.
-
(1969)
Certainty
-
-
Wittgenstein, L.1
-
64
-
-
0039395203
-
-
22 ff
-
See, for example, Ludwig Wittgenstein's On Certainty, ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, trans. Denis Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1969), and the discussion in Williams, Unnatural Doubts, 22 ff.
-
Unnatural Doubts
-
-
Williams1
-
66
-
-
0004347851
-
-
As if, as Peirce sardonically remarks, "to start an inquiry it was only necessary to utter a question." Ibid., 232.
-
Fixation of Belief
, pp. 232
-
-
-
67
-
-
0345867599
-
Democracy, philosophy, and justification
-
Amy Gutmann has likewise argued that "foundationalism in political philosophy … is the claim that justification must rest upon truths about human nature, human rights, rationality, or politics that are self-evident, rationally incontestable, or axiomatic." "Democracy, Philosophy, and Justification, "in Benhabib, Democracy and Difference, 340.
-
Democracy and Difference
, pp. 340
-
-
Benhabib1
-
68
-
-
0002214963
-
A proposition is neither true because it stands fast nor stands fast because it is true
-
As Williams puts it, paraphrasing Wittgenstein, "a proposition is neither true because it stands fast nor stands fast because it is true"; Unnatural Doubts, 124. Williams is uncertain whether to call this view "foundationalist" or not, because his critique of skepticism requires that he equate foundationalism with what he calls "epistemological realism." See ibid., 114-15, 124, 221-24.
-
Unnatural Doubts
, pp. 124
-
-
Wittgenstein1
-
69
-
-
0039395203
-
-
As Williams puts it, paraphrasing Wittgenstein, "a proposition is neither true because it stands fast nor stands fast because it is true"; Unnatural Doubts, 124. Williams is uncertain whether to call this view "foundationalist" or not, because his critique of skepticism requires that he equate foundationalism with what he calls "epistemological realism." See ibid., 114-15, 124, 221-24.
-
Unnatural Doubts
, pp. 114-115
-
-
-
71
-
-
0002100509
-
John Dewey's philosophy
-
Bourne, "John Dewey's Philosophy, "New Republic 2 (1915): 154.
-
(1915)
New Republic
, vol.2
, pp. 154
-
-
Bourne1
-
72
-
-
4243325278
-
"Conscience and intelligence in war" (1917)
-
Indianapolis: Hackett
-
In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
-
(1993)
John Dewey: The Political Writings
, pp. 200
-
-
Morris, D.1
Shapiro, I.2
-
73
-
-
84923759624
-
-
In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
-
John Dewey: The Political Writings
, pp. 199
-
-
-
74
-
-
0002203902
-
The war and the intellectuals
-
In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
-
Collected Essays
, pp. 12
-
-
-
75
-
-
84875314405
-
-
In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
-
Twilight of Idols
, pp. 62
-
-
-
76
-
-
0002378885
-
-
In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
-
Conscience and Intelligence in War
, pp. 201
-
-
-
77
-
-
84989359024
-
-
chaps. 7-8
-
In fact, a careful reading of Bourne's wartime essays shows that his criticism is directed not at Deweyan philosophy per se but more narrowly at Dewey's contention (later recanted) that American intervention in the First World War was an "intelligent" response to international circumstances. Bourne's central thesis, stated again and again, is that the use of war as a means of intelligent reconstruction is impossible: "War is just that absolute situation which is its own end and its own means." "Conscience and Intelligence in War" (1917), in John Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 200. His diagnosis is not that pragmatism is incapable of projecting ends, as is commonly held, but rather that in wartime all ends are subordinated to those of war itself: war is "precisely the one situation in which [Dewey's] philosophy will no longer work." Ibid., 199, emphasis mine. What is more, Bourne argues that the key to resisting the degenerate logic of war is to "keep [the intellect] supple and pliable, "to avoid the "premature crystallization" of thought ("The War and the Intellectuals, "in Collected Essays, 12, 14) - prescriptions that appeal directly to the pragmatic conception of experimental inquiry. "Vision must constantly outshoot technique" in the building of a democratic society; in wartime, technique literally outshoots vision. The only recourse is to "wait and hope for wisdom when the world becomes pragmatic and flexible again" ("Twilight of Idols, "62; "Conscience and Intelligence in War, "201). Bourne paid a steep professional price for his antiwar sentiments, perhaps in part at Dewey's hands, but to make him a martyr to the antipragmatist cause, as Mumford and others have aimed to do, flies in the face of the facts. On Dewey's involvement in the debates over American intervention, his treatment of Bourne, and his later pacifism, see Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, chaps. 7-8.
-
John Dewey and American Democracy
-
-
Westbrook1
-
79
-
-
0030511484
-
-
Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" 1659, 1670. For a critique of Posner's view of pragmatism, see Jack Knight and James Johnson, "Political Consequences of Pragmatism, "Political Theory 24 (1996): 68-96.
-
What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?
, pp. 1659
-
-
Posner1
-
80
-
-
0030511484
-
Political consequences of pragmatism
-
Posner, "What Has Pragmatism to Offer Law?" 1659, 1670. For a critique of Posner's view of pragmatism, see Jack Knight and James Johnson, "Political Consequences of Pragmatism, "Political Theory 24 (1996): 68-96.
-
(1996)
Political Theory
, vol.24
, pp. 68-96
-
-
Knight, J.1
Johnson, J.2
-
81
-
-
0004347851
-
-
See, among many possible examples, Peirce, "Fixation of Belief'; James, Pragmatism, chap. 2; Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy. 53. James, Pragmatism, 32, 137.
-
Fixation of Belief
-
-
Peirce1
-
82
-
-
84878140284
-
-
chap. 2
-
See, among many possible examples, Peirce, "Fixation of Belief'; James, Pragmatism, chap. 2; Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy. 53. James, Pragmatism, 32, 137.
-
Pragmatism
-
-
James1
-
83
-
-
0004222329
-
-
See, among many possible examples, Peirce, "Fixation of Belief'; James, Pragmatism, chap. 2; Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy. 53. James, Pragmatism, 32, 137.
-
Reconstruction in Philosophy
, pp. 53
-
-
Dewey1
-
84
-
-
84878140284
-
-
See, among many possible examples, Peirce, "Fixation of Belief'; James, Pragmatism, chap. 2; Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy. 53. James, Pragmatism, 32, 137.
-
Pragmatism
, pp. 32
-
-
James1
-
85
-
-
0002078661
-
Neutrality in political science
-
New York: Cambridge University Press, Taylor does not link this idea to foundationalism, as I have here
-
Charles Taylor has shown that explanatory frameworks inevitably "secrete a certain value position": "The framework gives us as it were the geography of the range of phenomena in question, it tells us how they can vary, what are the major dimensions of variation. But since we are dealing with matters which are of great importance to human beings, a given map will have, as it were, its own built-in value slope. That is to say, a given dimension of variation will usually determine for itself how we are to judge of good and bad, because of its relation to obvious human wants and needs." "Neutrality in Political Science, "in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 73. Taylor does not link this idea to foundationalism, as I have here.
-
(1985)
Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers
, vol.2
, pp. 73
-
-
-
87
-
-
0004347851
-
-
Thus Peirce: "Scientific investigation has had the most wonderful triumphs in the way of settling opinion. These afford the explanation of my not doubting the method or the hypothesis which it supposes; and not having any doubt, nor believing that anybody else whom I could influence has, it would be the merest babble for me to say more about it. If there be anybody with a living doubt upon the subject, let him consider it." "Fixation of Belief, "244.
-
Fixation of Belief
, pp. 244
-
-
-
88
-
-
0033238820
-
Experience as experiment: Some consequences of pragmatism for democratic theory
-
I begin to address these issues in my "Experience as Experiment: Some Consequences of Pragmatism for Democratic Theory, "American Journal of Political Science 43 (1999): 542-65.
-
(1999)
American Journal of Political Science
, vol.43
, pp. 542-565
-
-
-
89
-
-
85013277713
-
-
note
-
It follows that there are no de jure barriers to participation in scientific discourse. The fact that there are nearly insurmountable de facto barriers reflects, as I have suggested, the trade-off (necessary in principle but in need of justification in its particulars) between the ideal of openness and the need to define a manageable field of inquiry.
-
-
-
-
90
-
-
0004028916
-
-
reprint, New York: Free Press, is an elegant attempt to argue otherwise
-
Walter Lippmann's Public Opinion (1922; reprint, New York: Free Press, 1965) is an elegant attempt to argue otherwise.
-
(1922)
Public Opinion
-
-
Lippmann, W.1
-
91
-
-
84989359024
-
-
402 ff
-
See Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, 402 ff. Dewey's most significant engagement with logical positivism, in the person of A. J. Ayer, came in his Theory of Valuation (1939), Later Works, 13:189-251. Ironically, this highly critical assessment was originally published as a contribution to Otto Neurath's positivist flagship, the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science.
-
John Dewey and American Democracy
-
-
Westbrook1
-
92
-
-
0342443204
-
-
See Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, 402 ff. Dewey's most significant engagement with logical positivism, in the person of A. J. Ayer, came in his Theory of Valuation (1939), Later Works, 13:189-251. Ironically, this highly critical assessment was originally published as a contribution to Otto Neurath's positivist flagship, the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science.
-
Theory of Valuation (1939), Later Works
, vol.13
, pp. 189-251
-
-
Ayer, A.J.1
-
93
-
-
16044364211
-
-
See Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy, 402 ff. Dewey's most significant engagement with logical positivism, in the person of A. J. Ayer, came in his Theory of Valuation (1939), Later Works, 13:189-251. Ironically, this highly critical assessment was originally published as a contribution to Otto Neurath's positivist flagship, the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science.
-
The International Encyclopedia of Unified Science
-
-
Neurath, O.1
-
97
-
-
0003945869
-
-
reprint, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, though it is somewhat unclear whether he is willing to endorse some of the more radical implications that have been drawn from it
-
The paradigmatic example of this "sociological" approach to the study of scientific inquiry is Thomas S. Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (1962; reprint, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), though it is somewhat unclear whether he is willing to endorse some of the more radical implications that have been drawn from it.
-
(1962)
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d Ed.
-
-
Kuhn, T.S.1
-
98
-
-
0002479337
-
Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes
-
ed. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave New York: Cambridge University Press
-
For a theoretical reconstruction of scientific inquiry that is broadly consonant with this view, see Imre Lakatos, "Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, "in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, ed. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1970), 91-195.
-
(1970)
Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge
, pp. 91-195
-
-
Lakatos, I.1
-
99
-
-
0004247997
-
-
This is the central claim of Dewey's Theory of Valuation. See also Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, chap. 6.
-
Theory of Valuation
-
-
Dewey1
-
100
-
-
0004235120
-
-
chap. 6
-
This is the central claim of Dewey's Theory of Valuation. See also Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, chap. 6.
-
Reason, Truth and History
-
-
Putnam1
-
101
-
-
0002378891
-
-
and for an historical account
-
See my "Experience as Experiment, "and for an historical account, see Edward A. Purcell Jr., The Crisis of Democratic Theory: Scientific Naturalism and the Problem of Value (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1973).
-
Experience as Experiment
-
-
-
107
-
-
84954666676
-
-
Hilary Putnam defines "metaphysical realism" as that position which "view[s] the aim of science simply as trying to get our notional world to 'match' the world in itself." Reason, Truth and History, 134.
-
Reason, Truth and History
, pp. 134
-
-
-
108
-
-
0002378893
-
Philosophy and democracy
-
As Dewey puts it, "How shall we read what we call reality … so that we may essay our deepest political and social problems with a conviction that they are to a reasonable extent sanctioned and sustained by the nature of things?" "Philosophy and Democracy" (1919), Middle Works, 11:48.
-
(1919)
Middle Works
, vol.11
, pp. 48
-
-
-
109
-
-
0003624191
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press, lecture 1
-
See, for example, John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), lecture 1.
-
(1993)
Political Liberalism
-
-
Rawls, J.1
|