-
1
-
-
84936068266
-
-
Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press
-
Various forms of this argument appear in: R. Dworkin, Law's Empire. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1986, pp. 186-216; M. Gilbert, 'Group membership and political obligation', The Monist, 76 (January 1993), 119-31; M. O. Hardimon, 'Role obligations', The Journal of Philosophy, 91 (July 1994), 333-63; J. Horton, Political Obligation. Atlantic Highlands NJ: Humanities, 1992, ch. 6; and Y. Tamir, Liberal Nationalism. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993, chs 5 and 6. In 'Citizenship and Political Obligation' (in P. King (ed.), Socialism and the Common Good: New Fabian Essays. London: Frank Cass, 1996, pp. 259-89), Bhikhu Parekh also makes a case for 'organizational obligations'. In a related essay, however, Parekh claims that the obligation to obey the law is a matter of civil and legal rather than political obligation ('A misconceived discourse on political obligation', Political Studies, 41 (1993), 236-51, p. 239).
-
(1986)
Law's Empire
, pp. 186-216
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
2
-
-
84921941517
-
Group membership and political obligation
-
January
-
Various forms of this argument appear in: R. Dworkin, Law's Empire. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1986, pp. 186-216; M. Gilbert, 'Group membership and political obligation', The Monist, 76 (January 1993), 119-31; M. O. Hardimon, 'Role obligations', The Journal of Philosophy, 91 (July 1994), 333-63; J. Horton, Political Obligation. Atlantic Highlands NJ: Humanities, 1992, ch. 6; and Y. Tamir, Liberal Nationalism. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993, chs 5 and 6. In 'Citizenship and Political Obligation' (in P. King (ed.), Socialism and the Common Good: New Fabian Essays. London: Frank Cass, 1996, pp. 259-89), Bhikhu Parekh also makes a case for 'organizational obligations'. In a related essay, however, Parekh claims that the obligation to obey the law is a matter of civil and legal rather than political obligation ('A misconceived discourse on political obligation', Political Studies, 41 (1993), 236-51, p. 239).
-
(1993)
The Monist
, vol.76
, pp. 119-131
-
-
Gilbert, M.1
-
3
-
-
0000164463
-
Role obligations
-
July
-
Various forms of this argument appear in: R. Dworkin, Law's Empire. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1986, pp. 186-216; M. Gilbert, 'Group membership and political obligation', The Monist, 76 (January 1993), 119-31; M. O. Hardimon, 'Role obligations', The Journal of Philosophy, 91 (July 1994), 333-63; J. Horton, Political Obligation. Atlantic Highlands NJ: Humanities, 1992, ch. 6; and Y. Tamir, Liberal Nationalism. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993, chs 5 and 6. In 'Citizenship and Political Obligation' (in P. King (ed.), Socialism and the Common Good: New Fabian Essays. London: Frank Cass, 1996, pp. 259-89), Bhikhu Parekh also makes a case for 'organizational obligations'. In a related essay, however, Parekh claims that the obligation to obey the law is a matter of civil and legal rather than political obligation ('A misconceived discourse on political obligation', Political Studies, 41 (1993), 236-51, p. 239).
-
(1994)
The Journal of Philosophy
, vol.91
, pp. 333-363
-
-
Hardimon, M.O.1
-
4
-
-
0004295247
-
-
Atlantic Highlands NJ: Humanities, ch. 6
-
Various forms of this argument appear in: R. Dworkin, Law's Empire. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1986, pp. 186-216; M. Gilbert, 'Group membership and political obligation', The Monist, 76 (January 1993), 119-31; M. O. Hardimon, 'Role obligations', The Journal of Philosophy, 91 (July 1994), 333-63; J. Horton, Political Obligation. Atlantic Highlands NJ: Humanities, 1992, ch. 6; and Y. Tamir, Liberal Nationalism. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993, chs 5 and 6. In 'Citizenship and Political Obligation' (in P. King (ed.), Socialism and the Common Good: New Fabian Essays. London: Frank Cass, 1996, pp. 259-89), Bhikhu Parekh also makes a case for 'organizational obligations'. In a related essay, however, Parekh claims that the obligation to obey the law is a matter of civil and legal rather than political obligation ('A misconceived discourse on political obligation', Political Studies, 41 (1993), 236-51, p. 239).
-
(1992)
Political Obligation
-
-
Horton, J.1
-
5
-
-
0003929983
-
-
Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, chs 5 and 6
-
Various forms of this argument appear in: R. Dworkin, Law's Empire. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1986, pp. 186-216; M. Gilbert, 'Group membership and political obligation', The Monist, 76 (January 1993), 119-31; M. O. Hardimon, 'Role obligations', The Journal of Philosophy, 91 (July 1994), 333-63; J. Horton, Political Obligation. Atlantic Highlands NJ: Humanities, 1992, ch. 6; and Y. Tamir, Liberal Nationalism. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993, chs 5 and 6. In 'Citizenship and Political Obligation' (in P. King (ed.), Socialism and the Common Good: New Fabian Essays. London: Frank Cass, 1996, pp. 259-89), Bhikhu Parekh also makes a case for 'organizational obligations'. In a related essay, however, Parekh claims that the obligation to obey the law is a matter of civil and legal rather than political obligation ('A misconceived discourse on political obligation', Political Studies, 41 (1993), 236-51, p. 239).
-
(1993)
Liberal Nationalism
-
-
Tamir, Y.1
-
6
-
-
0001804843
-
-
London: Frank Cass
-
Various forms of this argument appear in: R. Dworkin, Law's Empire. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1986, pp. 186-216; M. Gilbert, 'Group membership and political obligation', The Monist, 76 (January 1993), 119-31; M. O. Hardimon, 'Role obligations', The Journal of Philosophy, 91 (July 1994), 333-63; J. Horton, Political Obligation. Atlantic Highlands NJ: Humanities, 1992, ch. 6; and Y. Tamir, Liberal Nationalism. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993, chs 5 and 6. In 'Citizenship and Political Obligation' (in P. King (ed.), Socialism and the Common Good: New Fabian Essays. London: Frank Cass, 1996, pp. 259-89), Bhikhu Parekh also makes a case for 'organizational obligations'. In a related essay, however, Parekh claims that the obligation to obey the law is a matter of civil and legal rather than political obligation ('A misconceived discourse on political obligation', Political Studies, 41 (1993), 236-51, p. 239).
-
(1996)
Socialism and the Common Good: New Fabian Essays
, pp. 259-289
-
-
Obligation, C.P.1
King, P.2
-
7
-
-
21144468983
-
A misconceived discourse on political obligation
-
also makes a case for 'organizational obligations'. In a related essay, however, Parekh claims that the obligation to obey the law is a matter of civil and legal rather than political obligation
-
Various forms of this argument appear in: R. Dworkin, Law's Empire. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1986, pp. 186-216; M. Gilbert, 'Group membership and political obligation', The Monist, 76 (January 1993), 119-31; M. O. Hardimon, 'Role obligations', The Journal of Philosophy, 91 (July 1994), 333-63; J. Horton, Political Obligation. Atlantic Highlands NJ: Humanities, 1992, ch. 6; and Y. Tamir, Liberal Nationalism. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993, chs 5 and 6. In 'Citizenship and Political Obligation' (in P. King (ed.), Socialism and the Common Good: New Fabian Essays. London: Frank Cass, 1996, pp. 259-89), Bhikhu Parekh also makes a case for 'organizational obligations'. In a related essay, however, Parekh claims that the obligation to obey the law is a matter of civil and legal rather than political obligation ('A misconceived discourse on political obligation', Political Studies, 41 (1993), 236-51, p. 239).
-
(1993)
Political Studies
, vol.41
, pp. 236-251
-
-
Parekh, B.1
-
8
-
-
0001556235
-
Associative political obligations
-
January
-
A. J. Simmons, 'Associative political obligations', Ethics, 106 (January 1996), 247-73; C. H. Wellman, 'Associative allegiances and political obligations', Social Theory and Practice, 23 (Summer 1997), 181-204.
-
(1996)
Ethics
, vol.106
, pp. 247-273
-
-
Simmons, A.J.1
-
9
-
-
0001556235
-
Associative allegiances and political obligations
-
Summer
-
A. J. Simmons, 'Associative political obligations', Ethics, 106 (January 1996), 247-73; C. H. Wellman, 'Associative allegiances and political obligations', Social Theory and Practice, 23 (Summer 1997), 181-204.
-
(1997)
Social Theory and Practice
, vol.23
, pp. 181-204
-
-
Wellman, C.H.1
-
10
-
-
0004163779
-
-
New York: Harper and Row
-
Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism. New York: Harper and Row, 1970; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979.
-
(1970)
Defense of Anarchism
-
-
Wolff1
-
11
-
-
0003890812
-
-
Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press
-
Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism. New York: Harper and Row, 1970; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979.
-
(1979)
Moral Principles and Political Obligations
-
-
Simmons1
-
12
-
-
0001753541
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Charles Taylor refers to 'the obligation to belong' in 'Atomism' but not to an obligation to obey the laws. See Taylor, Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985, pp. 197-8 and 206. In Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1996, Michael Sandel stresses the importance of 'obligations of solidarity' and 'obligations of membership' (esp. pp. 13-17), but without reference to legal or political obligation.
-
(1985)
Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers
, vol.2
, pp. 197-198
-
-
Taylor1
-
13
-
-
0003700672
-
-
Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press
-
Charles Taylor refers to 'the obligation to belong' in 'Atomism' but not to an obligation to obey the laws. See Taylor, Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985, pp. 197-8 and 206. In Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1996, Michael Sandel stresses the importance of 'obligations of solidarity' and 'obligations of membership' (esp. pp. 13-17), but without reference to legal or political obligation.
-
(1996)
Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy
-
-
-
14
-
-
85037783781
-
-
note
-
Charles Taylor refers to 'the obligation to belong' in 'Atomism' but not to an obligation to obey the laws. See Taylor, Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985, pp. 197-8 and 206. In Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1996, Michael Sandel stresses the importance of 'obligations of solidarity' and 'obligations of membership' (esp. pp. 13-17), but without reference to legal or political obligation.
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
0004330973
-
-
Gilbert, 'Group membership and political obligation', p. 126. This essay also appears, in slightly different form, in M. Gilbert, Living Together: Rationality, Sociality, and Obligation. Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996, pp. 361-74.
-
Group Membership and Political Obligation
, pp. 126
-
-
Gilbert1
-
16
-
-
0004106770
-
-
Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield
-
Gilbert, 'Group membership and political obligation', p. 126. This essay also appears, in slightly different form, in M. Gilbert, Living Together: Rationality, Sociality, and Obligation. Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996, pp. 361-74.
-
(1996)
Living Together: Rationality, Sociality, and Obligation
, pp. 361-374
-
-
Gilbert, M.1
-
20
-
-
0003929983
-
-
identification with a group apparently contains a voluntary element: 'One may have acquired associative membership in a particular social group by birth rather than through voluntary choice, but unless one identifies with this membership, it cannot generate obligations. In this restricted sense, we could approach associative obligations as voluntarily assumed'
-
For Yael Tamir, identification with a group apparently contains a voluntary element: 'One may have acquired associative membership in a particular social group by birth rather than through voluntary choice, but unless one identifies with this membership, it cannot generate obligations. In this restricted sense, we could approach associative obligations as voluntarily assumed'. Liberal Nationalism, p. 135.
-
Liberal Nationalism
, pp. 135
-
-
Tamir, Y.1
-
23
-
-
0004350013
-
-
In a footnote to this passage, Hardimon adds that 'I am assuming that the roles of family member and citizen exhaust the class of noncontractual social roles'
-
Hardimon, 'Role obligations', p. 347. In a footnote to this passage, Hardimon adds that 'I am assuming that the roles of family member and citizen exhaust the class of noncontractual social roles'.
-
Role Obligations
, pp. 347
-
-
Hardimon1
-
24
-
-
0004350013
-
-
Hardimon, 'Role obligations', p. 347; emphasis added. Dworkin makes the same point in a different way: 'If we arrange familiar fraternal communities along a spectrum ranging from full choice to no choice in membership, political communities fall somewhere in the center. Political obligations are less involuntary than many obligations of family, because political communities do allow people to emigrate, and though the practical value of this choice is often very small the choice itself is important, as we know when we contemplate tyrannies that deny it'. Law's Empire, p. 207; emphasis added.
-
Role Obligations
, pp. 347
-
-
Hardimon1
-
25
-
-
84936068266
-
-
makes the same point in a different way: 'If we arrange familiar fraternal communities along a spectrum ranging from full choice to no choice in membership, political communities fall somewhere in the center. Political obligations are less involuntary than many obligations of family, because political communities do allow people to emigrate, and though the practical value of this choice is often very small the choice itself is important, as we know when we contemplate tyrannies that deny it'. emphasis added
-
Hardimon, 'Role obligations', p. 347; emphasis added. Dworkin makes the same point in a different way: 'If we arrange familiar fraternal communities along a spectrum ranging from full choice to no choice in membership, political communities fall somewhere in the center. Political obligations are less involuntary than many obligations of family, because political communities do allow people to emigrate, and though the practical value of this choice is often very small the choice itself is important, as we know when we contemplate tyrannies that deny it'. Law's Empire, p. 207; emphasis added.
-
Law's Empire
, pp. 207
-
-
Dworkin1
-
26
-
-
0004070581
-
-
Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield, Appendix 2
-
For evidence bearing on this intuition, see G. Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation. Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992, Appendix 2; but cf. L. Green, 'Who Believes in Political Obligation?' in J. T. Sanders and J. Narveson (eds) For and Against the State. Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996, pp. 1-17.
-
(1992)
The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation
-
-
Klosko, G.1
-
27
-
-
0001809061
-
Who Believes in Political Obligation?
-
J. T. Sanders and J. Narveson (eds) Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield
-
For evidence bearing on this intuition, see G. Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation. Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992, Appendix 2; but cf. L. Green, 'Who Believes in Political Obligation?' in J. T. Sanders and J. Narveson (eds) For and Against the State. Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996, pp. 1-17.
-
(1996)
For and Against the State
, pp. 1-17
-
-
Green, L.1
-
35
-
-
85037772006
-
-
emphasis added. The four conditions are as follows (pp. 199-200; emphasis in original): 'First, [the members] must regard the group's obligations as special, holding distinctly within the group, rather than as general duties its members owe equally to persons outside it. Second, they must accept that these responsibilities are personal: that they run directly from each member to each other member, not just to the group as a whole in some collective sense ... 'Third, members must see these responsibilities as following from a more general responsibility each has of concern for the well-being of others in the group; ... 'Fourth, members must suppose that the group's practices show not only concern but an equal concern for all members'
-
Dworkin, Law's Empire, p. 204; emphasis added. The four conditions are as follows (pp. 199-200; emphasis in original): 'First, [the members] must regard the group's obligations as special, holding distinctly within the group, rather than as general duties its members owe equally to persons outside it. Second, they must accept that these responsibilities are personal: that they run directly from each member to each other member, not just to the group as a whole in some collective sense ... 'Third, members must see these responsibilities as following from a more general responsibility each has of concern for the well-being of others in the group; ... 'Fourth, members must suppose that the group's practices show not only concern but an equal concern for all members.'
-
Law's Empire
, pp. 204
-
-
Dworkin1
-
36
-
-
0004350013
-
-
Hardimon, 'Role obligations', p. 350. Horton presents a similar argument at pp. 156-7 of Political Obligation.
-
Role Obligations
, pp. 350
-
-
Hardimon1
-
37
-
-
0004295247
-
-
presents a similar argument at
-
Hardimon, 'Role obligations', p. 350. Horton presents a similar argument at pp. 156-7 of Political Obligation.
-
Political Obligation
, pp. 156-157
-
-
Horton1
-
38
-
-
84936068266
-
-
emphasis in original
-
Dworkin, Law's Empire, p. 200 (emphasis in original).
-
Law's Empire
, pp. 200
-
-
Dworkin1
-
41
-
-
85037752177
-
-
when she turns directly to questions of political obligation, seems to insist that one can have a political obligation only to a reasonably just polity: 'The main advantage of the approach presented here is its ability to place normative evaluation within a context. It can explain why most of us assume, and rightly so, that our obligations are not to the state that is the most just of all, but to our own state, as long as it is reasonably just'. emphasis added; (see also p. 134)
-
Even Tamir, when she turns directly to questions of political obligation, seems to insist that one can have a political obligation only to a reasonably just polity: 'The main advantage of the approach presented here is its ability to place normative evaluation within a context. It can explain why most of us assume, and rightly so, that our obligations are not to the state that is the most just of all, but to our own state, as long as it is reasonably just'. Liberal Nationalism, p. 139; emphasis added; (see also p. 134).
-
Liberal Nationalism
, pp. 139
-
-
Tamir, E.1
-
42
-
-
0001207085
-
The principle of fairness and free-rider problems
-
July
-
See esp. R. Arneson, 'The principle of fairness and free-rider problems,' Ethics, 92 (July 1982), 616-33; Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation; and, for a more qualified defence, J. Wolff, 'Political obligation, fairness, and independence', Ratio, 8 (April 1995), 87-99. For criticism, see esp. R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic, 1974, pp. 90-5; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, ch. 5; M. B. E. Smith, 'Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?', Yale Law Journal, 82 (1973), 950-76; and J. Horton, Political Obligation, esp. pp. 89-98. I develop my own position in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, ch. 5, and in 'Playing fair with punishment'. Ethics, 103 (April 1993), 473-88, where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment.
-
(1982)
Ethics
, vol.92
, pp. 616-633
-
-
Arneson, R.1
-
43
-
-
0004070581
-
-
See esp. R. Arneson, 'The principle of fairness and free-rider problems,' Ethics, 92 (July 1982), 616-33; Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation; and, for a more qualified defence, J. Wolff, 'Political obligation, fairness, and independence', Ratio, 8 (April 1995), 87-99. For criticism, see esp. R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic, 1974, pp. 90-5; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, ch. 5; M. B. E. Smith, 'Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?', Yale Law Journal, 82 (1973), 950-76; and J. Horton, Political Obligation, esp. pp. 89-98. I develop my own position in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, ch. 5, and in 'Playing fair with punishment'. Ethics, 103 (April 1993), 473-88, where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment.
-
The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation
-
-
Klosko1
-
44
-
-
84984059574
-
Political obligation, fairness, and independence
-
April
-
See esp. R. Arneson, 'The principle of fairness and free-rider problems,' Ethics, 92 (July 1982), 616-33; Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation; and, for a more qualified defence, J. Wolff, 'Political obligation, fairness, and independence', Ratio, 8 (April 1995), 87-99. For criticism, see esp. R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic, 1974, pp. 90-5; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, ch. 5; M. B. E. Smith, 'Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?', Yale Law Journal, 82 (1973), 950-76; and J. Horton, Political Obligation, esp. pp. 89-98. I develop my own position in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, ch. 5, and in 'Playing fair with punishment'. Ethics, 103 (April 1993), 473-88, where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment.
-
(1995)
Ratio
, vol.8
, pp. 87-99
-
-
Wolff, J.1
-
45
-
-
0004273805
-
-
New York: Basic
-
See esp. R. Arneson, 'The principle of fairness and free-rider problems,' Ethics, 92 (July 1982), 616-33; Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation; and, for a more qualified defence, J. Wolff, 'Political obligation, fairness, and independence', Ratio, 8 (April 1995), 87-99. For criticism, see esp. R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic, 1974, pp. 90-5; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, ch. 5; M. B. E. Smith, 'Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?', Yale Law Journal, 82 (1973), 950-76; and J. Horton, Political Obligation, esp. pp. 89-98. I develop my own position in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, ch. 5, and in 'Playing fair with punishment'. Ethics, 103 (April 1993), 473-88, where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment.
-
(1974)
Anarchy, State, and Utopia
, pp. 90-95
-
-
Nozick, R.1
-
46
-
-
0003890812
-
-
ch. 5
-
See esp. R. Arneson, 'The principle of fairness and free-rider problems,' Ethics, 92 (July 1982), 616-33; Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation; and, for a more qualified defence, J. Wolff, 'Political obligation, fairness, and independence', Ratio, 8 (April 1995), 87-99. For criticism, see esp. R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic, 1974, pp. 90-5; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, ch. 5; M. B. E. Smith, 'Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?', Yale Law Journal, 82 (1973), 950-76; and J. Horton, Political Obligation, esp. pp. 89-98. I develop my own position in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, ch. 5, and in 'Playing fair with punishment'. Ethics, 103 (April 1993), 473-88, where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment.
-
Moral Principles and Political Obligations
-
-
Simmons1
-
47
-
-
0000516383
-
Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?
-
See esp. R. Arneson, 'The principle of fairness and free-rider problems,' Ethics, 92 (July 1982), 616-33; Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation; and, for a more qualified defence, J. Wolff, 'Political obligation, fairness, and independence', Ratio, 8 (April 1995), 87-99. For criticism, see esp. R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic, 1974, pp. 90-5; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, ch. 5; M. B. E. Smith, 'Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?', Yale Law Journal, 82 (1973), 950-76; and J. Horton, Political Obligation, esp. pp. 89-98. I develop my own position in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, ch. 5, and in 'Playing fair with punishment'. Ethics, 103 (April 1993), 473-88, where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment.
-
(1973)
Yale Law Journal
, vol.82
, pp. 950-976
-
-
Smith, M.B.E.1
-
48
-
-
0004295247
-
-
esp.
-
See esp. R. Arneson, 'The principle of fairness and free-rider problems,' Ethics, 92 (July 1982), 616-33; Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation; and, for a more qualified defence, J. Wolff, 'Political obligation, fairness, and independence', Ratio, 8 (April 1995), 87-99. For criticism, see esp. R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic, 1974, pp. 90-5; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, ch. 5; M. B. E. Smith, 'Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?', Yale Law Journal, 82 (1973), 950-76; and J. Horton, Political Obligation, esp. pp. 89-98. I develop my own position in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, ch. 5, and in 'Playing fair with punishment'. Ethics, 103 (April 1993), 473-88, where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment.
-
Political Obligation
, pp. 89-98
-
-
Horton, J.1
-
49
-
-
0003619441
-
-
I develop my own position New York: Oxford University Press, ch. 5
-
See esp. R. Arneson, 'The principle of fairness and free-rider problems,' Ethics, 92 (July 1982), 616-33; Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation; and, for a more qualified defence, J. Wolff, 'Political obligation, fairness, and independence', Ratio, 8 (April 1995), 87-99. For criticism, see esp. R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic, 1974, pp. 90-5; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, ch. 5; M. B. E. Smith, 'Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?', Yale Law Journal, 82 (1973), 950-76; and J. Horton, Political Obligation, esp. pp. 89-98. I develop my own position in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, ch. 5, and in 'Playing fair with punishment'. Ethics, 103 (April 1993), 473-88, where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment.
-
(1997)
Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism
-
-
-
50
-
-
85050051553
-
Playing fair with punishment
-
April where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment
-
See esp. R. Arneson, 'The principle of fairness and free-rider problems,' Ethics, 92 (July 1982), 616-33; Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation; and, for a more qualified defence, J. Wolff, 'Political obligation, fairness, and independence', Ratio, 8 (April 1995), 87-99. For criticism, see esp. R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic, 1974, pp. 90-5; Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, ch. 5; M. B. E. Smith, 'Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?', Yale Law Journal, 82 (1973), 950-76; and J. Horton, Political Obligation, esp. pp. 89-98. I develop my own position in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, ch. 5, and in 'Playing fair with punishment'. Ethics, 103 (April 1993), 473-88, where I offer an account of fair play as the justification for legal punishment.
-
(1993)
Ethics
, vol.103
, pp. 473-488
-
-
-
52
-
-
0004002174
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
I develop the argument that people may grow into an obligation to obey the law in Civic Virtues, esp. pp. 76-8. For an explanation of the 'quasi-contractual' nature of the fair play argument, see D. Miller, On Nationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995, pp. 60-2.
-
(1995)
On Nationality
, pp. 60-62
-
-
Miller, D.1
-
53
-
-
0004240568
-
-
Chicago IL: University of Chicago Press, esp. §3.4
-
On this point, note the defence of 'the social contribution thesis' in A. Gewirth, The Community of Rights. Chicago IL: University of Chicago Press, 1996, esp. §3.4.
-
(1996)
The Community of Rights
-
-
Gewirth, A.1
-
55
-
-
0004002174
-
-
esp.
-
For the mutually reinforcing nature of 'obligations of citizenship' and 'obligations of nationality', see Miller, On Nationality, esp. pp. 70-3.
-
On Nationality
, pp. 70-73
-
-
Miller1
-
56
-
-
85037762857
-
-
For helpful comments on earlier drafts of this essay, I am grateful to Daniel McDermott, David Miller, and my colleagues in the ASUMPL Reading Group, especially Jack Crittenden and Jeffrie Murphy. John Horton deserves special thanks for his generous and thoughtful response to my criticism of his views
-
For helpful comments on earlier drafts of this essay, I am grateful to Daniel McDermott, David Miller, and my colleagues in the ASUMPL Reading Group, especially Jack Crittenden and Jeffrie Murphy. John Horton deserves special thanks for his generous and thoughtful response to my criticism of his views.
-
-
-
|