메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 4, 1999, Pages 379-405

Harmful thoughts

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0033483707     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3505231     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (10)

References (30)
  • 1
    • 0043085015 scopus 로고
    • Punishment for Thoughts
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • "Punishment for Thoughts," in Herbert Morris, On Guilt and Innocence (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976), pp. 1-29.
    • (1976) On Guilt and Innocence , pp. 1-29
    • Morris, H.1
  • 2
    • 0041675563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield
    • For some further reflections on this theme see Douglas Husak, Philosophy of Criminal Law (Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield, 1987), pp. 99-97, 103-105.
    • (1987) Philosophy of Criminal Law , pp. 99-197
    • Husak, D.1
  • 3
    • 0003991395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon press, "even practical thought [deliberation, intention-formation, choices] does not, by itself, impinge on the world: it must be translated into action; and we can say that it is by action (as distinct from mere thought) that agents impinge on or make a difference to the world
    • For an explicit statement of this assumption, see, e.g., R.A. Duff, Criminal Attempts (Oxford: Clarendon press, 1996), pp. 313-314: "even practical thought [deliberation, intention-formation, choices] does not, by itself, impinge on the world: it must be translated into action; and we can say that it is by action (as distinct from mere thought) that agents impinge on or make a difference to the world."
    • (1996) Criminal Attempts , pp. 313-314
    • Duff, R.A.1
  • 4
    • 0011531404 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • See, for example, Joseph Tussman, Government and the Mind (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 88.
    • (1977) Government and the Mind , pp. 88
    • Tussman, J.1
  • 5
    • 0004157494 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • See, e.g., Joel Feinberg, Harmless Wrongdoing (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 23-24; D. Husak, Philosophy of Criminal Law, supra, note 2, at p. 105; R.A. Duff, Criminal Attempts, supra, note 3, at p. 314.
    • (1988) Harmless Wrongdoing , pp. 23-24
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 6
    • 0041675563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra, note 2
    • See, e.g., Joel Feinberg, Harmless Wrongdoing (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 23-24; D. Husak, Philosophy of Criminal Law, supra, note 2, at p. 105; R.A. Duff, Criminal Attempts, supra, note 3, at p. 314.
    • Philosophy of Criminal Law , pp. 105
    • Husak, D.1
  • 7
    • 0003991395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra, note 3
    • See, e.g., Joel Feinberg, Harmless Wrongdoing (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 23-24; D. Husak, Philosophy of Criminal Law, supra, note 2, at p. 105; R.A. Duff, Criminal Attempts, supra, note 3, at p. 314.
    • Criminal Attempts , pp. 314
    • Duff, R.A.1
  • 8
    • 0003799915 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, chs. 1-2
    • Cf. Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1960), chs. 1-2.
    • (1960) Word and Object
    • Van Quine, W.O.1
  • 11
    • 0042083241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 352 U.S. 432 (1956)
    • 352 U.S. 432 (1956).
  • 12
    • 0042584227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 204 Cal. App. 2nd 832; 23 Cal. Rptr. 92 (1962)
    • 204 Cal. App. 2nd 832; 23 Cal. Rptr. 92 (1962).
  • 13
    • 0001466690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Misfortunes of the Dead
    • The example is discussed by George Pitcher in "The Misfortunes of the Dead," American Philosophical Quarterly 21, pp. 183-188 and by Joel Feinberg, Harm to Others (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), pp. 90-91.
    • American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.21 , pp. 183-188
    • Pitcher, G.1
  • 14
    • 0003439620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • The example is discussed by George Pitcher in "The Misfortunes of the Dead," American Philosophical Quarterly 21, pp. 183-188 and by Joel Feinberg, Harm to Others (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), pp. 90-91.
    • (1984) Harm to Others , pp. 90-91
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 15
    • 0003439620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • diagnoses the problem this case poses in similar terms. I propose a different solution from his, though the two, I think, are consistent. Mine, however, leads more directly to the claim I seek to establish concerning the extra-personal effects of thoughts
    • Pitcher, ibid., diagnoses the problem this case poses in similar terms. I propose a different solution from his, though the two, I think, are consistent. Mine, however, leads more directly to the claim I seek to establish concerning the extra-personal effects of thoughts.
    • Harm to Others
    • Pitcher1
  • 16
    • 0003439620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra, note 11
    • For a discussion of "vicarious harms" along such lines see Feinberg, Harm to Others, supra, note 11, at pp. 70-79.
    • Harm to Others , pp. 70-79
    • Feinberg1
  • 18
    • 0043085018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Guy de Maupassant famously stated that the tower was his favorite lunch place in Paris, being the one place from which the tower could not be seen; he is also said to have left Paris permanently to avoid looking at the tower.
  • 19
    • 0041582224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I don't mean to raise the separate question whether there is a useful logical or ontological sense that would admit the "properties" ordinary speech implicitly excludes, or, for that matter, exclude "properties" that the latter takes for granted.
  • 20
    • 0043085020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This example is actually somewhat out of date: the external floodlighting was replaced in 1986 by a system of illumination that is within the tower's structure. The change corroborates my main point: the significant property of the tower in this case is its being illuminated at night; it doesn't seem to matter much, relative to this property, whether the light comes from within, making it an intrinsic property, or from without, thus rendering it relational.
  • 21
    • 0003439620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra, note 11
    • Feinberg considers a similar case, and reaches a similar conclusion: the wife's sinking into a depression can all by itself count as a harm to her loving husband. The reason for Feinberg lies simply in the intensity and duration of the husband's love, which give him a vicarious interest in his wife's well-being. But here again the account seems to leave a conceptual gap: no matter how intense and enduring my love or admiration for, say, Queen Elizabeth, her mood swings, of which I know not, will hardly be said to affect me. See Feinberg, Harm to Others, supra, note 11, at p. 71.
    • Harm to Others , pp. 71
    • Feinberg1
  • 22
    • 0038014282 scopus 로고
    • Two Conceptions of Happiness
    • Cases of this kind are also sometimes discussed in connection with the concept of happiness. See, for example, Richard Kraut, "Two Conceptions of Happiness," Philosophical Review 88 (1979), pp. 167-197.
    • (1979) Philosophical Review , vol.88 , pp. 167-197
    • Kraut, R.1
  • 23
    • 0042083244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These two categories are not exhaustive: physical objects, such as geographic locations, can also play the part of a relational term. They are however irrelevant to our present concerns.
  • 24
    • 0042584229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Indeed, strictly speaking, the second belief may suffice to establish L as the leader, and it need not even be a true belief. L may possess a salient characteristic, an imposing appearance perhaps, which on close inspection is not charisma, but resembles it sufficiently to lead most members of the group to believe that the others are bound to be misled by that characteristic into believing that L is charismatic, and hence view her as the leader. Notice that for such mental bootstrapping to successfully establish L as the leader requires the absence of any communication among the members. In the terminology I propose, what we witness here is a situation in which the convergent thoughts of a group of people, uncommunicated and unexpressed, serve as a collective relational property of L, by constituting her as the group's leader.
  • 25
    • 0041582222 scopus 로고
    • Of the Dignity and Meanness of Human Nature
    • Charles Hendel, (ed.) New York: Liberal Arts Press
    • Cf. David Hume, "Of the Dignity and Meanness of Human Nature," in Political Essays, Charles Hendel, (ed.) (New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1953).
    • (1953) Political Essays
    • Hume, D.1
  • 26
    • 0043085019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I have distinguished relational properties from comparative ones, but some properties are a composite of both. Being a popular member of the class is, as we saw earlier, a relational property that depends on what the other members of the class think of one. But being the most popular member is also comparative. One can accordingly lose this accolade in three different ways: through a change in the person herself, becoming, say, mean and nasty; through a change in the others' attitudes - they simply grew tired of her; or by the fact that a new member, more attractive than the heretofore favorite, joined the group.
  • 27
    • 85080838551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Concealment and Exposure
    • Hence, the examples recently adduced by Thomas Nagel to demonstrate the perils of excessive candor in social interactions fall outside the purview of my argument. See his "Concealment and Exposure," Philosophy and Public Affairs 27(3) (1998), pp. 10-17.
    • (1998) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.27 , Issue.3 , pp. 10-17
  • 28
    • 0000692309 scopus 로고
    • The Meaning of 'Meaning'
    • London: Cambridge University Press
    • The main papers are, Hilary Putnam, "The Meaning of 'Meaning'," in Philosophical Papers 2 (London: Cambridge University Press, 1975), p. 215; Tyler Burge, "Individualism and the Mental," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1979), pp. 73-121, and "Other Bodies," in Andrew Woodfield, ed., Thought and Object (New York: Oxford University Press, 1982), p. 97.
    • (1975) Philosophical Papers , vol.2 , pp. 215
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 29
    • 84985362811 scopus 로고
    • Individualism and the Mental
    • The main papers are, Hilary Putnam, "The Meaning of 'Meaning'," in Philosophical Papers 2 (London: Cambridge University Press, 1975), p. 215; Tyler Burge, "Individualism and the Mental," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1979), pp. 73-121, and "Other Bodies," in Andrew Woodfield, ed., Thought and Object (New York: Oxford University Press, 1982), p. 97.
    • (1979) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.4 , pp. 73-121
    • Burge, T.1
  • 30
    • 0009092289 scopus 로고
    • Other Bodies
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • The main papers are, Hilary Putnam, "The Meaning of 'Meaning'," in Philosophical Papers 2 (London: Cambridge University Press, 1975), p. 215; Tyler Burge, "Individualism and the Mental," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1979), pp. 73-121, and "Other Bodies," in Andrew Woodfield, ed., Thought and Object (New York: Oxford University Press, 1982), p. 97.
    • (1982) Thought and Object , pp. 97
    • Woodfield, A.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.