메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 1, 1999, Pages 39-64

Political oratory and conversation: Cicero versus deliberative democracy

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0033483577     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591799027001003     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (51)

References (206)
  • 1
    • 0004294588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1996) Democracy and Disagreement
    • Gutmann, A.1    Thompson, D.2
  • 2
    • 0002247751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward a deliberative model of democratic legitimacy
    • ed. Seyla Benhabib Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political , pp. 67-94
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 3
    • 0002161865 scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and democratic legitimacy
    • ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1989) The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State , pp. 17-34
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 4
    • 0002805654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procedure and substance in deliberative democracy
    • ed. Benhabib
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • Democracy and Difference , pp. 95-119
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 5
    • 0003780112 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1990) Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science
    • Dryzek, J.1
  • 6
    • 0003974417 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1993) The Partial Constitution , pp. 133-145
    • Sunstein, C.1
  • 7
    • 0003573418 scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1991) Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms
    • Fishkin, J.1
  • 8
    • 0003903245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1998) Deliberative Democracy
    • Elster, J.1
  • 9
    • 0003464922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1997) Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics
    • Bohman, J.1    Rehg, W.2
  • 10
    • 84883931766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1996) Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse
    • Chambers, S.1
  • 11
    • 0003889601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1996) Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy
    • Bohman, J.1
  • 12
    • 0003739821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1996) The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy
    • Nino, C.S.1
  • 13
    • 0003891077 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1994) The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government
    • Besserte, J.M.1
  • 14
    • 84972609043 scopus 로고
    • On legitimacy and political deliberation
    • August
    • See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996); Seyla Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 67-94; Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, ed. Alan Hamlin and Philip Petit (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1989), 17-34; Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 95-119; John Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 133-45; and James Fishkin, Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reforms (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991). For other elaborations of deliberative democracy, see Deliberative Democracy, ed. Jon Elster (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998); Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, eds. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997) - this edited volume contains both of Joshua Cohen's previously listed essays; Simone Chambers, Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996); James Bohman, Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Carlos Santiago Nino, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996); Joseph M. Besserte, The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994); and Bernard Manin, "On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation," Political Theory 15 (August 1987): 338-68.
    • (1987) Political Theory , vol.15 , pp. 338-368
    • Manin, B.1
  • 18
    • 85033949706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • Aristotle, Rhetoric, Book 1, chap. 3; Cicero, De inventione 1.5.7 (all citations from Cicero, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]); Quintilian, Institutio oratorio 3.4.12-15 (all citations from Quintilian, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]). For a general discussion of the three genres of oratory, see Brian Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), 53-62.
    • Rhetoric, Book 1
    • Aristotle1
  • 19
    • 0007169228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • all citations from Cicero, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]
    • Aristotle, Rhetoric, Book 1, chap. 3; Cicero, De inventione 1.5.7 (all citations from Cicero, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]); Quintilian, Institutio oratorio 3.4.12-15 (all citations from Quintilian, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]). For a general discussion of the three genres of oratory, see Brian Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), 53-62.
    • De Inventione , pp. 157
    • Cicero1
  • 20
    • 0040034021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • all citations from Quintilian, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]
    • Aristotle, Rhetoric, Book 1, chap. 3; Cicero, De inventione 1.5.7 (all citations from Cicero, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]); Quintilian, Institutio oratorio 3.4.12-15 (all citations from Quintilian, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]). For a general discussion of the three genres of oratory, see Brian Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), 53-62.
    • Institutio Oratorio , pp. 3412-3415
    • Quintilian1
  • 21
    • 84941096208 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Aristotle, Rhetoric, Book 1, chap. 3; Cicero, De inventione 1.5.7 (all citations from Cicero, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]); Quintilian, Institutio oratorio 3.4.12-15 (all citations from Quintilian, unless otherwise indicated, are from the Loeb Classical Library editions [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]). For a general discussion of the three genres of oratory, see Brian Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), 53-62.
    • (1988) In Defence of Rhetoric , pp. 53-62
    • Vickers, B.1
  • 23
    • 85033943552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I do not intend this list to be exhaustive. I only list those characteristics relevant to my argument.
  • 24
    • 0040034021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutio oratorio 2.18.2-5. This relationship between rhetoric and action is explicit in the traditional three officia oratoris, or duties of an orator: to prove (probare) or instruct (docere), to please (delectare), and to stir (movere). Of the three officia, it is the last duty, focused on action, that receives Cicero's highest praise: "it is the one thing of all that avails most in winning verdicts," and in it "is summed up the entire virtue of the orator." See Cicero, Orator 21.69-70.
    • Institutio Oratorio , pp. 2182-2185
  • 25
    • 84871135963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutio oratorio 2.18.2-5. This relationship between rhetoric and action is explicit in the traditional three officia oratoris, or duties of an orator: to prove (probare) or instruct (docere), to please (delectare), and to stir (movere). Of the three officia, it is the last duty, focused on action, that receives Cicero's highest praise: "it is the one thing of all that avails most in winning verdicts," and in it "is summed up the entire virtue of the orator." See Cicero, Orator 21.69-70.
    • Orator , pp. 2169-2170
    • Cicero1
  • 30
    • 85033941184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orator 14.45-46; De oratore 3.30.120-121. Quintilian notes Cicero's change of heart in Institutio oratoria 3.5.14-15.
    • Orator , pp. 1445-1446
  • 31
    • 85033965655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orator 14.45-46; De oratore 3.30.120-121. Quintilian notes Cicero's change of heart in Institutio oratoria 3.5.14-15.
    • De Oratore , pp. 330120-330121
  • 32
    • 0004314329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orator 14.45-46; De oratore 3.30.120-121. Quintilian notes Cicero's change of heart in Institutio oratoria 3.5.14-15.
    • Institutio Oratoria , pp. 3514-3515
    • Quintilian1
  • 33
    • 85033968732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • An exception is the deliberative oratory appropriate to a smaller audience, like the senate.
  • 34
    • 85033968972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.3.12. See also Rhetoric 1355a 25-30.
    • De Oratore , pp. 1312
  • 35
    • 84872421184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.3.12. See also Rhetoric 1355a 25-30.
    • Rhetoric
  • 36
    • 84957002123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutio oratoria 3.4.15. See Peter France, Rhetoric and Truth in France: Descartes and Diderot (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972), 28-32.
    • Institutio Oratoria , pp. 3415
  • 39
    • 84957002123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And, as Quintilian argues, a prudent use of emotions will not only benefit the orator personally, but, if he is a good orator (a vir bonus dicendi peritus), truth and justice too. Institutio oratoria 12.1.1.
    • Institutio Oratoria , pp. 1211
  • 40
    • 84872421184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1356a 1-4. Ethos persuades when "the speech is so spoken as to make us think [the speaker] more credible, [since] we believe good men more fully and more readily than others" (1358a 3-13). Pathos succeeds "when the speech stirs the emotions," for "our judgments when we are pleased and friendly are not the same as when we are pained and hostile" (1356a 13-19). Logical explanation works "through the speech itself when we have proved a truth or an apparent truth by means of the persuasive arguments suitable to the case in question" (1356a 19-21). The original Aristotelian sense of ethos, however, changes under the Romans, and it comes to mean a gentler form of the emotions roused by pathos. See Orator 36.128; Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric, 74.
    • Rhetoric
  • 41
    • 85033957823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1356a 1-4. Ethos persuades when "the speech is so spoken as to make us think [the speaker] more credible, [since] we believe good men more fully and more readily than others" (1358a 3-13). Pathos succeeds "when the speech stirs the emotions," for "our judgments when we are pleased and friendly are not the same as when we are pained and hostile" (1356a 13-19). Logical explanation works "through the speech itself when we have proved a truth or an apparent truth by means of the persuasive arguments suitable to the case in question" (1356a 19-21). The original Aristotelian sense of ethos, however, changes under the Romans, and it comes to mean a gentler form of the emotions roused by pathos. See Orator 36.128; Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric, 74.
    • Orator , pp. 36128
  • 42
    • 0005385738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1356a 1-4. Ethos persuades when "the speech is so spoken as to make us think [the speaker] more credible, [since] we believe good men more fully and more readily than others" (1358a 3-13). Pathos succeeds "when the speech stirs the emotions," for "our judgments when we are pleased and friendly are not the same as when we are pained and hostile" (1356a 13-19). Logical explanation works "through the speech itself when we have proved a truth or an apparent truth by means of the persuasive arguments suitable to the case in question" (1356a 19-21). The original Aristotelian sense of ethos, however, changes under the Romans, and it comes to mean a gentler form of the emotions roused by pathos. See Orator 36.128; Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric, 74.
    • In Defence of Rhetoric , pp. 74
    • Vickers1
  • 44
    • 84880470284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cicero, Brutus 80.279. See also ibid. 93.22; Orator 36.127.
    • Brutus , pp. 80279
    • Cicero1
  • 45
    • 85033971902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cicero, Brutus 80.279. See also ibid. 93.22; Orator 36.127.
    • Brutus , pp. 9322
  • 46
    • 85033967197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cicero, Brutus 80.279. See also ibid. 93.22; Orator 36.127.
    • Orator , pp. 36127
  • 47
    • 85033962961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 2.42.178.
    • De Oratore , pp. 242178
  • 48
    • 0002250656 scopus 로고
    • trans. D. W. Robertson, Jr. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
    • St. Augustine, On Christian Doctrine, trans. D. W. Robertson, Jr. (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1958), 4.27.
    • (1958) On Christian Doctrine , pp. 427
    • Augustine, S.1
  • 49
    • 85033968384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orator 25.122. Although epideictic oratory is mainly celebratory, not contentious, it has also been used agonistically in both legal and political settings, Institutio oratoria 3.7.2.
    • Orator , pp. 25122
  • 50
    • 84957002123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orator 25.122. Although epideictic oratory is mainly celebratory, not contentious, it has also been used agonistically in both legal and political settings, Institutio oratoria 3.7.2.
    • Institutio Oratoria , pp. 372
  • 52
    • 84872421184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1354a 5-6. See George Kennedy's translation, On Rhetoric: A Theory of Civic Discourse (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), 29.
    • Rhetoric
  • 55
    • 0011357932 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • George Kennedy, The Art of Persuasion in Greece (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1974), 189.
    • (1974) The Art of Persuasion in Greece , pp. 189
    • Kennedy, G.1
  • 56
    • 85033948478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.24.157, 2.20.84;
    • De Oratore , pp. 124157
  • 57
    • 85033946387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orator 13.42;
    • Orator , pp. 1342
  • 61
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.37.132. Translation from Cicero, On Duties, Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought, ed. M. T. Griffin and E. M. Atkins (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 51. See also ibid. 2.14.48-49.
    • De Officiis , pp. 137132
  • 62
    • 0040034013 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought, ed. M. T. Griffin and E. M. Atkins Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • De officiis 1.37.132. Translation from Cicero, On Duties, Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought, ed. M. T. Griffin and E. M. Atkins (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 51. See also ibid. 2.14.48-49.
    • (1991) On Duties , pp. 51
    • Cicero1
  • 63
    • 85033941120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.37.132. Translation from Cicero, On Duties, Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought, ed. M. T. Griffin and E. M. Atkins (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 51. See also ibid. 2.14.48-49.
    • On Duties , pp. 21448-21449
  • 64
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.37.132. Translation from Cicero, On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 51.
    • De Officiis , pp. 137132
  • 65
    • 85033957367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Griffin and Atkins
    • De officiis 1.37.132. Translation from Cicero, On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 51.
    • On Duties , pp. 51
    • Cicero1
  • 66
    • 85033943977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Cicero's rhetorical dialogues include De oratore, De partitione oratoria, and Brutus; and his philosophical dialogues include De republica, De legibus, Academica, Definibus, Tusculan Disputations, De natura deorum, De senectute, De amicitia, and De divinatione.
  • 67
    • 84876078305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cicero De finibus 2.6.17; Tusculan Disputations 1.47.112.
    • De Finibus , pp. 2617
    • Cicero1
  • 68
  • 69
    • 85033944379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato 3.48, 1:319, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks, 2 vols. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972). See also David Marsh, The Quattrocento Dialogue: Classical Tradition and Humanist Innovation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980), 2; Rudolf Hirzel, Der Dialog: Ein literarhistorischer Versuch, 2 vols. (1895; reprint, Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1963), 1:2-7; Introduction to Loeb Classical Library Edition of Cicero's Brutus, trans. G. L. Hendrickson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 8-9.
    • Life of Plato , pp. 348
    • Laertius, D.1
  • 70
    • 0003548526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. R. D. Hicks, 2 vols. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato 3.48, 1:319, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks, 2 vols. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972). See also David Marsh, The Quattrocento Dialogue: Classical Tradition and Humanist Innovation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980), 2; Rudolf Hirzel, Der Dialog: Ein literarhistorischer Versuch, 2 vols. (1895; reprint, Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1963), 1:2-7; Introduction to Loeb Classical Library Edition of Cicero's Brutus, trans. G. L. Hendrickson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 8-9.
    • (1972) Lives of Eminent Philosophers
  • 71
    • 0001981452 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato 3.48, 1:319, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks, 2 vols. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972). See also David Marsh, The Quattrocento Dialogue: Classical Tradition and Humanist Innovation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980), 2; Rudolf Hirzel, Der Dialog: Ein literarhistorischer Versuch, 2 vols. (1895; reprint, Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1963), 1:2-7; Introduction to Loeb Classical Library Edition of Cicero's Brutus, trans. G. L. Hendrickson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 8-9.
    • (1980) The Quattrocento Dialogue: Classical Tradition and Humanist Innovation , pp. 2
    • Marsh, D.1
  • 72
    • 85033961935 scopus 로고
    • 2 vols. reprint, Hildesheim: Georg Olms
    • Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato 3.48, 1:319, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks, 2 vols. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972). See also David Marsh, The Quattrocento Dialogue: Classical Tradition and Humanist Innovation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980), 2; Rudolf Hirzel, Der Dialog: Ein literarhistorischer Versuch, 2 vols. (1895; reprint, Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1963), 1:2-7; Introduction to Loeb Classical Library Edition of Cicero's Brutus, trans. G. L. Hendrickson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 8-9.
    • (1895) Der Dialog: Ein Literarhistorischer Versuch , Issue.1 , pp. 2-7
    • Hirzel, R.1
  • 73
    • 0040033990 scopus 로고
    • trans. G. L. Hendrickson Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato 3.48, 1:319, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks, 2 vols. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972). See also David Marsh, The Quattrocento Dialogue: Classical Tradition and Humanist Innovation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980), 2; Rudolf Hirzel, Der Dialog: Ein literarhistorischer Versuch, 2 vols. (1895; reprint, Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1963), 1:2-7; Introduction to Loeb Classical Library Edition of Cicero's Brutus, trans. G. L. Hendrickson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 8-9.
    • (1971) Introduction to Loeb Classical Library Edition of Cicero's Brutus , pp. 8-9
  • 74
    • 85033969069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.7.27, 1.8.29.
    • De Oratore , pp. 1727
  • 75
    • 85033941099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.6.23. Disputatio does not mean dispute or disputation. By not equating dialogue with sermo, Cicero is presumably alluding to the artificial, mimetic character of his dialogues that stands in contrast to the naturalness and lack of artifice of genuine conversations. I would like to thank Professor Elaine Fantham for this observation.
    • De Oratore , pp. 1623
  • 77
    • 0007339638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Samuel Ijsseling, Rhetoric and Philosophy in Conflict: An Historical Survey (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1976), 35; France, Rhetoric and Truth in France, 32.
    • Rhetoric and Truth in France , pp. 32
    • France1
  • 78
    • 85033948493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orator 35.123.
    • Orator , pp. 35123
  • 79
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.37.134-135. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 52. See also De oratore 2.4.17-2.5.20, where Cicero's interlocutors recognize the need to adhere to "the demands of the occasion" in sermo. Those who fail to speak or act with decorum are labeled ineptus.
    • De Officiis , pp. 137134-137135
  • 80
    • 85033967091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Griffin and Atkins
    • De officiis 1.37.134-135. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 52. See also De oratore 2.4.17-2.5.20, where Cicero's interlocutors recognize the need to adhere to "the demands of the occasion" in sermo. Those who fail to speak or act with decorum are labeled ineptus.
    • On Duties , pp. 52
  • 81
    • 85033953745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where Cicero's interlocutors recognize the need to adhere to "the demands of the occasion" in sermo
    • De officiis 1.37.134-135. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 52. See also De oratore 2.4.17-2.5.20, where Cicero's interlocutors recognize the need to adhere to "the demands of the occasion" in sermo. Those who fail to speak or act with decorum are labeled ineptus.
    • De Oratore , pp. 2417-2520
  • 82
    • 85033944379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This linking of ideas to actual people and their circumstances is what, most fundamentally, separates conversation from dialectic. Although both are investigative arts in which opposing views are considered, dialectic deals with ideas without regard to the emotional state of those involved; from the dialectician's perspective, a valid syllogism is all the proof that is necessary. In conversation, by contrast, there is the recognition that even the best proofs do not persuade, unless they are accompanied by rhetorical propriety; each speaker must first accommodate himself to the conditions of the other speakers. See Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato 3.48, 1:319, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers.
    • Life of Plato , pp. 348
    • Laertius, D.1
  • 83
    • 0003548526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This linking of ideas to actual people and their circumstances is what, most fundamentally, separates conversation from dialectic. Although both are investigative arts in which opposing views are considered, dialectic deals with ideas without regard to the emotional state of those involved; from the dialectician's perspective, a valid syllogism is all the proof that is necessary. In conversation, by contrast, there is the recognition that even the best proofs do not persuade, unless they are accompanied by rhetorical propriety; each speaker must first accommodate himself to the conditions of the other speakers. See Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato 3.48, 1:319, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers.
    • Lives of Eminent Philosophers
  • 84
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.37.135. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 52.
    • De Officiis , pp. 137135
  • 85
    • 85033958144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Griffin and Atkins
    • De officiis 1.37.135. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 52.
    • On Duties , pp. 52
  • 86
    • 85033944505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De finibus 4.19.52.
    • De Finibus , pp. 41952
  • 87
    • 85033950248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 2.15.65-16.68. See also ibid. 2.10.41-43, 3.28.109; and Alain Michel, Rhétorique et Philosophie chez Cicéron: Essai sur les fondements philosophique de l'art persuader (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1960), 219.
    • De Oratore , pp. 21565-21668
  • 88
    • 85033959331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 2.15.65-16.68. See also ibid. 2.10.41-43, 3.28.109; and Alain Michel, Rhétorique et Philosophie chez Cicéron: Essai sur les fondements philosophique de l'art persuader (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1960), 219.
    • De Oratore , pp. 21041-21043
  • 90
    • 0038849155 scopus 로고
    • Toronto: University of Toronto Press
    • Although Cicero structured his philosophical work De officiis as a letter from the elder Cicero to his son, the letter was often categorized, classically, as a form of dialogue in which one of the participants is absent. See G.M.A. Grube, A Greek Critic: Demetrius on Style (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1961), 111; Libanius, Libanii opera, ed. Richard Foerster (Leipzig: B. G. Teubner, 1903-27), 9:27; Desiderius Erasmus, De conscribendis epistolis, in Collected Works of Erasmus (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1974), 25:20.
    • (1961) A Greek Critic: Demetrius on Style , pp. 111
    • Grube, G.M.A.1
  • 91
    • 0039441928 scopus 로고
    • ed. Richard Foerster Leipzig: B. G. Teubner
    • Although Cicero structured his philosophical work De officiis as a letter from the elder Cicero to his son, the letter was often categorized, classically, as a form of dialogue in which one of the participants is absent. See G.M.A. Grube, A Greek Critic: Demetrius on Style (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1961), 111; Libanius, Libanii opera, ed. Richard Foerster (Leipzig: B. G. Teubner, 1903-27), 9:27; Desiderius Erasmus, De conscribendis epistolis, in Collected Works of Erasmus (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1974), 25:20.
    • (1903) Libanii Opera , pp. 9
    • Libanius1
  • 92
    • 0038849052 scopus 로고
    • Toronto: University of Toronto Press
    • Although Cicero structured his philosophical work De officiis as a letter from the elder Cicero to his son, the letter was often categorized, classically, as a form of dialogue in which one of the participants is absent. See G.M.A. Grube, A Greek Critic: Demetrius on Style (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1961), 111; Libanius, Libanii opera, ed. Richard Foerster (Leipzig: B. G. Teubner, 1903-27), 9:27; Desiderius Erasmus, De conscribendis epistolis, in Collected Works of Erasmus (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1974), 25:20.
    • (1974) De Conscribendis Epistolis, in Collected Works of Erasmus , pp. 25
    • Erasmus, D.1
  • 93
    • 85033959034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 3.16.59-61. See also Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric, 163-4.
    • De Oratore , pp. 31659-31661
  • 95
    • 85033953912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De finibus 2.6.17.
    • De Finibus , pp. 2617
  • 96
    • 84968297726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De natura deorum 2.1.3; De officiis 1.4.13; De oratore 2.5.19; John F. Tinkler, "Renaissance Humanism and the genera eloquentiae," Rhetorica: A Journal of the History of Rhetoric 5 (1987): 287-8;
    • De Natura Deorum , pp. 213
  • 97
    • 84968297726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De natura deorum 2.1.3; De officiis 1.4.13; De oratore 2.5.19; John F. Tinkler, "Renaissance Humanism and the genera eloquentiae," Rhetorica: A Journal of the History of Rhetoric 5 (1987): 287-8;
    • De Officiis , pp. 1413
  • 98
    • 84968297726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De natura deorum 2.1.3; De officiis 1.4.13; De oratore 2.5.19; John F. Tinkler, "Renaissance Humanism and the genera eloquentiae," Rhetorica: A Journal of the History of Rhetoric 5 (1987): 287-8;
    • De Oratore , pp. 2519
  • 99
    • 84968297726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Renaissance humanism and the genera eloquentiae
    • De natura deorum 2.1.3; De officiis 1.4.13; De oratore 2.5.19; John F. Tinkler, "Renaissance Humanism and the genera eloquentiae," Rhetorica: A Journal of the History of Rhetoric 5 (1987): 287-8;
    • (1987) Rhetorica: A Journal of the History of Rhetoric , vol.5 , pp. 287-288
    • Tinkler, J.F.1
  • 102
    • 85033970468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • De republica and De legibus were his only philosophical dialogues written earlier.
  • 103
    • 85033946193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cicero's otium was not sought; it came as a consequence of his forced political retirement, his being "released from taking part in the government of the country." Academica 1.3.11. Cicero still preferred the life of the statesman to that of the philosopher, and it was his reentry into political life in 44, with his attack on Mark Antony, that led to his proscription and death in December 43.
    • Academica , pp. 1311
  • 104
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 2.10.35; De finibus 2.6.17, 2.25.80-81.
    • De Officiis , pp. 21035
  • 105
    • 85033953912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 2.10.35; De finibus 2.6.17, 2.25.80-81.
    • De Finibus , pp. 2617
  • 107
    • 0004281448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tusculan Disputations 2.1.4; Plato, Republic 494a.
    • Republic
    • Plato1
  • 108
  • 109
    • 0007208424 scopus 로고
    • Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press
    • Lily Ross Taylor, Roman Voting Assemblies: From the Hannibalic War to the Dictatorship of Caesar (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1966), 15-19. See also Chaim Wirszubski, Libertas as a Political Idea at Rome during the Late Republic and Early Principate (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1968), 18-19, n. 2: "The plain fact, from a political point of view, is that the Roman People went to the Assemblies to listen and to vote, not to speak. Magistrates, leading senators and barristers enjoyed freedom of speech and made the most of it; but they cannot be identified with the Roman People."
    • (1966) Roman Voting Assemblies: From the Hannibalic War to the Dictatorship of Caesar , pp. 15-19
    • Taylor, L.R.1
  • 110
    • 0007035798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1968
    • Lily Ross Taylor, Roman Voting Assemblies: From the Hannibalic War to the Dictatorship of Caesar (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1966), 15-19. See also Chaim Wirszubski, Libertas as a Political Idea at Rome during the Late Republic and Early Principate (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1968), 18-19, n. 2: "The plain fact, from a political point of view, is that the Roman People went to the Assemblies to listen and to vote, not to speak. Magistrates, leading senators and barristers enjoyed freedom of speech and made the most of it; but they cannot be identified with the Roman People."
    • Libertas As a Political Idea at Rome during the Late Republic and Early Principate , pp. 18-19
    • Wirszubski, C.1
  • 111
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.134. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 52; Tusculan Disputations 4.4.8.
    • De Officiis , pp. 1134
  • 112
    • 85033944947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Griffin and Atkins
    • De officiis 1.134. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 52; Tusculan Disputations 4.4.8.
    • On Duties , pp. 52
  • 113
    • 84870792806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.134. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins, 52; Tusculan Disputations 4.4.8.
    • Tusculan Disputations , pp. 448
  • 114
    • 84870792806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tusculan Disputations 4.4.7, 2.26.63, 5.29.83; De natura deorum 1.7.17, 3.40.95; De finibus 5.26.76.
    • Tusculan Disputations , pp. 447
  • 115
    • 0007298231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tusculan Disputations 4.4.7, 2.26.63, 5.29.83; De natura deorum 1.7.17, 3.40.95; De finibus 5.26.76.
    • De Natura Deorum , pp. 1717
  • 116
    • 85033944385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tusculan Disputations 4.4.7, 2.26.63, 5.29.83; De natura deorum 1.7.17, 3.40.95; De finibus 5.26.76.
    • De Finibus , pp. 52676
  • 118
    • 85033949935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.59.255; De officiis 1.1.3.
    • De Oratore , pp. 159255
  • 119
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.59.255; De officiis 1.1.3.
    • De Officiis , pp. 113
  • 120
    • 0007298231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De natura deorum 1.5.10. See also Tusculan Disputations 2.26.63.
    • De Natura Deorum , pp. 1510
  • 121
    • 84870792806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De natura deorum 1.5.10. See also Tusculan Disputations 2.26.63.
    • Tusculan Disputations , pp. 22663
  • 123
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.38.136. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins. In Tusculan Disputations (4.23.52) Cicero asks the question, "is there anything more like unsoundness of mind than anger?"
    • De Officiis , pp. 138136
  • 124
    • 85033962696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Griffin and Atkins
    • De officiis 1.38.136. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins. In Tusculan Disputations (4.23.52) Cicero asks the question, "is there anything more like unsoundness of mind than anger?"
    • On Duties
  • 125
    • 84870792806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.38.136. Translation from On Duties, ed. Griffin and Atkins. In Tusculan Disputations (4.23.52) Cicero asks the question, "is there anything more like unsoundness of mind than anger?"
    • Tusculan Disputations , pp. 42352
  • 126
    • 85033962027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 2.44.185, 189-190. Quintilian states (6.2.20) that "pathos is almost entirely concerned with anger, dislike, fear, hatred, and pity."
    • De Oratore , pp. 244185
  • 128
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.38.136.
    • De Officiis , pp. 138136
  • 130
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tusculan Disputations 4.25.55; De officiis 1.4.13.
    • De Officiis , pp. 1413
  • 131
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.16.50-17.56.
    • De Officiis , pp. 11650-11756
  • 133
    • 85033946686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De finibus 1.5.13. See also Tusculan Disputations 4.21.47. Aristotle, in Topics (159a 27-38), distinguishes between "those engaged in competition" and "those who discuss things together in the spirit of inquiry." The interlocutors in Ciceronian sermo belong to the latter.
    • De Finibus , pp. 1513
  • 134
    • 84870792806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De finibus 1.5.13. See also Tusculan Disputations 4.21.47. Aristotle, in Topics (159a 27-38), distinguishes between "those engaged in competition" and "those who discuss things together in the spirit of inquiry." The interlocutors in Ciceronian sermo belong to the latter.
    • Tusculan Disputations , pp. 42147
  • 135
    • 0346593305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • distinguishes between "those engaged in competition" and "those who discuss things together in the spirit of inquiry"
    • De finibus 1.5.13. See also Tusculan Disputations 4.21.47. Aristotle, in Topics (159a 27-38), distinguishes between "those engaged in competition" and "those who discuss things together in the spirit of inquiry." The interlocutors in Ciceronian sermo belong to the latter.
    • Topics
    • Aristotle1
  • 136
    • 84924502783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plato Letters, VII 344b. See also Gorgias 487a; Klosko, "Rational Persuasion in Plato's Political Theory," History of Political Thought 7 (1986): 18-19; and Martha C. Nussbaum's review of Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher, by Gregory Vlastos, The New Republic, 16 and 23 September 1991, 34-40.
    • Letters
    • Plato1
  • 137
    • 85033941069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plato Letters, VII 344b. See also Gorgias 487a; Klosko, "Rational Persuasion in Plato's Political Theory," History of Political Thought 7 (1986): 18-19; and Martha C. Nussbaum's review of Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher, by Gregory Vlastos, The New Republic, 16 and 23 September 1991, 34-40.
    • Gorgias
  • 138
    • 84928447824 scopus 로고
    • Rational persuasion in Plato's political theory
    • Plato Letters, VII 344b. See also Gorgias 487a; Klosko, "Rational Persuasion in Plato's Political Theory," History of Political Thought 7 (1986): 18-19; and Martha C. Nussbaum's review of Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher, by Gregory Vlastos, The New Republic, 16 and 23 September 1991, 34-40.
    • (1986) History of Political Thought , vol.7 , pp. 18-19
    • Klosko1
  • 139
    • 0039441846 scopus 로고
    • Socrates, ironist and moral philosopher
    • by Gregory Vlastos, 16 and 23 September
    • Plato Letters, VII 344b. See also Gorgias 487a; Klosko, "Rational Persuasion in Plato's Political Theory," History of Political Thought 7 (1986): 18-19; and Martha C. Nussbaum's review of Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher, by Gregory Vlastos, The New Republic, 16 and 23 September 1991, 34-40.
    • (1991) The New Republic , pp. 34-40
    • Nussbaum's, M.C.1
  • 147
  • 150
    • 0002832609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three normative models of democracy
    • ed. Seyla Benhabib Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Three Normative Models of Democracy," in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), 27, 29-30.
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political , pp. 27
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 152
    • 0002247753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The democratic moment and the problem of difference
    • ed. Benhabib
    • Seyla Benhabib, "The Democratic Moment and the Problem of Difference," in Democracy and Difference, ed. Benhabib, 7.
    • Democracy and Difference , pp. 7
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 154
    • 0004351752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," 22-3; Bohman, Public Deliberation, 16. See also Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," 99.
    • Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy , pp. 22-23
    • Cohen1
  • 155
    • 0004116605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," 22-3; Bohman, Public Deliberation, 16. See also Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," 99.
    • Public Deliberation , pp. 16
    • Bohman1
  • 166
    • 85033943551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics (New York: Routledge, 1992), 90-5; Benhabib, "The Democratic Moment," 7.
    • The Democratic Moment , pp. 7
    • Benhabib1
  • 167
    • 85033968246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Academica 2.48.147-48.
    • Academica , pp. 248147-248148
  • 168
    • 0003527892 scopus 로고
    • trans. Thomas McCarthy Boston: Beacon
    • See Jürgen Habermas, Communcation and the Evolution of Society, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon, 1979), 1; Chambers, Reasonable Democracy, 156-7.
    • (1979) Communcation and the Evolution of Society , pp. 1
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 169
    • 0004347849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jürgen Habermas, Communcation and the Evolution of Society, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon, 1979), 1; Chambers, Reasonable Democracy, 156-7.
    • Reasonable Democracy , pp. 156-157
    • Chambers1
  • 170
    • 0004347849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "A discursive approach to the dilemmas, conflicts, and tensions of modern society stands somewhere between the view that all problems are amenable to rational solutions (it is only a matter of time) and an approach that accentuates the intractability of the dilemmas, conflicts, and tensions of collective life. Discourse ethics offers no theoretical guarantee that discourse will be successful or somehow always could be successful if only we were all of goodwill. . . . Nevertheless, we cannot draw the conclusion that all the problems we face are tragic, insoluble, unbridgeable, or irreconcilable." Chambers, Reasonable Democracy, 158.
    • Reasonable Democracy , pp. 158
    • Chambers1
  • 172
    • 85033956305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De legibus 3.18.40.
    • De Legibus , pp. 31840
  • 173
    • 85033971900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.5.20-21.
    • De Oratore , pp. 1520-1521
  • 174
    • 69249176665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De officiis 1.43.153.
    • De Officiis , pp. 143153
  • 175
    • 0004080299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle Politics 1325b 14-33; De republica 1.2.2; Wood, Cicero's Social and Political Thought, 122-3.
    • Politics
    • Aristotle1
  • 176
    • 84878423247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle Politics 1325b 14-33; De republica 1.2.2; Wood, Cicero's Social and Political Thought, 122-3.
    • De Republica , pp. 122
  • 178
  • 180
    • 85033955681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.8-30-31.
    • De Oratore , pp. 1830-1831
  • 181
    • 85033958211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De oratore 1.8.33-34. Cicero offers a mythical account, in De inventione 1.2.2-3, of the creation of civilization. Initially, human beings lived in a brutish state of nature. They were led out of this primitive condition, however, by a great orator who persuaded his neighbors to abandon their lowly existence. It was this earliest of rhetoricians, Cicero posits, that transformed men "from wild savages into a kind and gentle folk."
    • De Oratore , pp. 1833-1834
  • 182
    • 85033949840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cicero offers a mythical account
    • of the creation of civilization
    • De oratore 1.8.33-34. Cicero offers a mythical account, in De inventione 1.2.2-3, of the creation of civilization. Initially, human beings lived in a brutish state of nature. They were led out of this primitive condition, however, by a great orator who persuaded his neighbors to abandon their lowly existence. It was this earliest of rhetoricians, Cicero posits, that transformed men "from wild savages into a kind and gentle folk."
    • De Inventione , pp. 122-123
  • 183
    • 0040627222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press
    • See Gary Remer, Humanism and the Rhetoric of Toleration (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996), 35-7.
    • (1996) Humanism and the Rhetoric of Toleration , pp. 35-37
    • Remer, G.1
  • 184
    • 84977044601 scopus 로고
    • Varieties of rationality, varieties of emotion
    • Amélie Rorty contends that the emotions involve evaluation and appraisal and are not, as such, either rational or irrational. Similarly, Nussbaum maintains that the emotions can be rational or irrational and that they are appropriate in deliberation. See Amélie Oksenberg Rorty, "Varieties of Rationality, Varieties of Emotion," Social Science Information 24 (1985): 343-53; Martha C. Nussbaum, "Emotions and Women's Capabilities," in Women, Culture, and Development, ed. Martha C. Nussbaum and Jonathan Glover (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 360-95.
    • (1985) Social Science Information , vol.24 , pp. 343-353
    • Rorty, A.O.1
  • 185
    • 84977044601 scopus 로고
    • Emotions and women's capabilities
    • ed. Martha C. Nussbaum and Jonathan Glover Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Amélie Rorty contends that the emotions involve evaluation and appraisal and are not, as such, either rational or irrational. Similarly, Nussbaum maintains that the emotions can be rational or irrational and that they are appropriate in deliberation. See Amélie Oksenberg Rorty, "Varieties of Rationality, Varieties of Emotion," Social Science Information 24 (1985): 343-53; Martha C. Nussbaum, "Emotions and Women's Capabilities," in Women, Culture, and Development, ed. Martha C. Nussbaum and Jonathan Glover (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 360-95.
    • (1995) Women, Culture, and Development , pp. 360-395
    • Nussbaum, M.C.1
  • 188
    • 0004348921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benhabib criticizes Rawls for eliminating "all contestatory, rhetorical, affective, impassioned elements of public discourse, with all their excesses and virtues.See Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model," 76. She does not, however, explain how rhetoric fits in her own model of discourse. Bohman also acknowledges the need for rhetoric in public deliberation. See Bohman, Public Deliberation, 7.
    • Toward a Deliberative Model , pp. 76
    • Benhabib1
  • 189
    • 0004116605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benhabib criticizes Rawls for eliminating "all contestatory, rhetorical, affective, impassioned elements of public discourse, with all their excesses and virtues.See Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model," 76. She does not, however, explain how rhetoric fits in her own model of discourse. Bohman also acknowledges the need for rhetoric in public deliberation. See Bohman, Public Deliberation, 7.
    • Public Deliberation , pp. 7
    • Bohman1
  • 190
    • 0004348921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model," 83. See also Chambers, Reasonable Democracy, 206. Habermas discusses rhetoric as display, but not as a part of deliberation. Structural Transformation, 8.
    • Toward a Deliberative Model , pp. 83
    • Benhabib1
  • 191
    • 0004347849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model," 83. See also Chambers, Reasonable Democracy, 206. Habermas discusses rhetoric as display, but not as a part of deliberation. Structural Transformation, 8.
    • Reasonable Democracy , pp. 206
    • Chambers1
  • 192
    • 0004342907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benhabib, "Toward a Deliberative Model," 83. See also Chambers, Reasonable Democracy, 206. Habermas discusses rhetoric as display, but not as a part of deliberation. Structural Transformation, 8.
    • Structural Transformation , pp. 8
  • 193
    • 84872421184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1354a 15-20, 1377b 21-25; Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric, 72-3.
    • Rhetoric
  • 195
    • 0031481266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against deliberation
    • June
    • Thus, I am not arguing, as does Lynn Sanders, against rationalist deliberation per se, but against deliberative democracy's conception of discourse as solely rationalist. See Lynn M. Sanders, "Against Deliberation," Political Theory 25 (June 1997): 347-76.
    • (1997) Political Theory , vol.25 , pp. 347-376
    • Sanders, L.M.1
  • 196
    • 85033953912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De finibus 2.6.17.
    • De Finibus , pp. 2617
  • 197
    • 84933490964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Chambers's discussion in Reasonable Democracy, 5-6, 232; Danns Villa, "Post-modernism and the Public Sphere," American Political Science Review 86 (September 1992): 712-21.
    • Reasonable Democracy , pp. 5-6
    • Chambers1
  • 198
    • 84933490964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Post-modernism and the public sphere
    • September
    • See Chambers's discussion in Reasonable Democracy, 5-6, 232; Danns Villa, "Post-modernism and the Public Sphere," American Political Science Review 86 (September 1992): 712-21.
    • (1992) American Political Science Review , vol.86 , pp. 712-721
    • Villa, D.1
  • 200
    • 85033971788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chambers acknowledges that "the major barrier to discursive resolution in liberal democracies usually comes in the form of political apathy, not conscious suppression. People have little interest in the decisions that affect them and are willing to allow others to debate the issues and find solutions." Reasonable Democracy, 198.
    • Reasonable Democracy , pp. 198
  • 201
    • 0004294588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Disadvantaged groups have usually found representatives from within their own ranks who could speak for them, and who could articulate their interests and ideals, at least as reasonably and effectively as representatives of established groups. Martin Luther King, Jr., exemplifies this kind of representation at its best." Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement, 132-3.
    • Democracy and Disagreement , pp. 132-133
    • Gutmann1    Thompson2
  • 203
    • 0004347849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My emphasis. Chambers, Reasonable Democracy, 184. Deliberative democracy has a "Kantian component [valuing individual autonomy] that is not usually found in republican models of democracy." Nevertheless, while it does "not require as high a level of civic virtue as republican models," it certainly requires "a higher level of civic virtue than is presently evident in the practice of democracy." Chambers, Reasonable Democracy.
    • Reasonable Democracy , pp. 184
    • Chambers1
  • 204
    • 0004347849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My emphasis. Chambers, Reasonable Democracy, 184. Deliberative democracy has a "Kantian component [valuing individual autonomy] that is not usually found in republican models of democracy." Nevertheless, while it does "not require as high a level of civic virtue as republican models," it certainly requires "a higher level of civic virtue than is presently evident in the practice of democracy." Chambers, Reasonable Democracy.
    • Reasonable Democracy
    • Chambers1
  • 205
    • 0007185574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also 23
    • "Discourse theory invests the democratic process with normative connotaions stronger than those found in the liberal model but weaker than those of the republican model. . . . it takes elements from both and fits them together in a new way." Habermas, "Three Normative Models," 27; see also 23.
    • Three Normative Models , pp. 27
    • Habermas1
  • 206
    • 0011596003 scopus 로고
    • A critique of philosophical conversation
    • fall-winter
    • See Michael Walzer, "A Critique of Philosophical Conversation," The Philosophical Forum 21 (fall-winter 1989-90): 189-91.
    • (1989) The Philosophical Forum , vol.21 , pp. 189-191
    • Walzer, M.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.