메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 6, 1999, Pages 655-684

Addiction and criminal liability

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0033267529     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3505096     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (13)

References (63)
  • 1
    • 0347491017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am unsure what kinds of things should be described as the subject matters of addictions. I doubt that material objects such as drugs can be such subject matters. After all, no substance can addict a person unless he consumes it. Thus, I suppose that only behaviors (such as consumption) are literally the subject matters of addictions. Despite this uncertainty, I will describe material objects such as drugs as possible subject matters of addictions.
  • 2
    • 0346860517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Model Penal Code, Sec. 2.09(1)
    • Model Penal Code, Sec. 2.09(1).
  • 3
    • 0346230041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The leading case is U.S. v. Moore, 486 F.2d 1139 (D.C. Cir. 1973)
    • The leading case is U.S. v. Moore, 486 F.2d 1139 (D.C. Cir. 1973).
  • 4
    • 0347491014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Insofar as I use a name, I simply refer to this new defense as the addiction defense. Alternatives sometimes found in the literature - such as "psychological compulsion" or "pharmacological coercion" - are problematic. The former name fails to indicate that many psychological compulsions - those that do not involve the pain of withdrawal - do not give rise to the excuse I ultimately describe. The latter name fails to indicate that the nature and severity of withdrawal symptoms are not solely a matter of pharmacology.
  • 5
    • 0346230027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The 'But-Everyone-Does-that!' Defense
    • I do not pretend that these comments provide an especially deep rationale for the excuse of duress. How does the supposition that a person of reasonable firmness would assist the villain rather than endure the pain of a broken leg support the conclusion that we should not blame this particular defendant for committing the offense? Presumably, a person should not be blamed if he succumbs to a threat which persons of reasonable firmness would not resist. More generally, a person does not merit the condemnation of the criminal law when his behavior, although wrongful, conforms to that of the person of reasonable firmness, and standards of reasonableness are sensitive to the behavior of other persons. For a more detailed discussion, see Douglas Husak, "The 'But-Everyone-Does-that!' Defense," Public Affairs Quarterly 10 (1996), p. 307.
    • (1996) Public Affairs Quarterly , vol.10 , pp. 307
    • Husak, D.1
  • 6
    • 0346230042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Reservations about accepting the defense in this example might stem from features of duress that restrict its application in a few jurisdictions. Many states, for example, require a threat to be "imminent" before the excuse can arise. In my example, the defense may be precluded because the pains of withdrawal are not imminent. The requirement of imminence, however, seems dubious; it is not retained in the Model Penal Code formulation of duress.
  • 7
    • 0002180849 scopus 로고
    • St. Paul: West Publishing Company, sec. 177(e)(7)
    • Hence the alleged need for an excusing disability that is "gross and verifiable." See Paul Robinson, Criminal Law Defenses Vol. 2 (St. Paul: West Publishing Company, 1986), sec. 177(e)(7).
    • (1986) Criminal Law Defenses , vol.2
    • Robinson, P.1
  • 8
    • 0347491012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Commentators debate how this objective component should be formulated. A more fundamental issue, however, is why tests of duress should include an objective component at all. Why shouldn't the standard of duress be purely subjective? A given person, after all, may have a low threshold of pain. Why should he be required to resist a threat just because a person of reasonable firmness would do so? If the test of duress were purely subjective, the excuse would be available if the particular defendant, with his peculiar sensibilities, was unable to resist the threat. I do not pretend to address this issue, other than to point out that the criminal law has long recognized that persons vary greatly in their dispositions, circumstances, and in their ability to conform their conduct to law. Unless the burden of conformity reaches a critical threshold, these individual differences have long been thought to be immaterial.
  • 9
    • 0347491013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I will return to the subjective component of the defense of duress in Part III, especially in my discussion of cocaine.
  • 10
    • 0346860513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Part III
    • See Part III.
  • 11
    • 0348121122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • If I am mistaken, and some persons who resist snacks or sex experience severe pains, then the case for excusing their conduct seems comparable to that of the drug addict or the defendant who acts under duress.
  • 12
    • 0346230038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For better or worse, the Model Penal Code formulation of duress does not give rise to an excuse in this circumstance; the defendant must act in order to avoid force against a person.
  • 13
    • 0346230039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This generalization about the nonvoluntariness defense is subject to the culpability-in-causing exception I discuss in Part II.
  • 14
    • 0347536694 scopus 로고
    • Autonomy
    • Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit (eds.), Cambridge: Basil Blackwell
    • For a useful introduction to differing views about the nature and value of autonomy, see Gerald Dworkin: "Autonomy," in Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit (eds.), A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Basil Blackwell, 1995).
    • (1995) A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy
    • Dworkin, G.1
  • 15
    • 0346230040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ideally, one would identify several plausible senses of autonomy, and then analyze whether and to what extent addiction undermined autonomy in each sense. In what follows, I am well aware that my treatment of autonomy is superficial and cursory.
  • 16
    • 0348121120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The subsequent points about criminalization require not only that the state has an interest in preventing persons from becoming addicted, but that this interest is sufficiently strong to justify sentencing persons to jail. This determination depends, inter alia, on the importance of the value of autonomy - an issue on which I hope to avoid commitment.
  • 17
    • 0346230036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This claim is extremely controversial. I will not challenge it here, except to remark that alternative measures to discourage the use of addictive drugs - measures that do not resort to criminal punishment - may well be more efficacious.
  • 18
    • 0011874178 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • I believe that the state is selective in a variety of contexts involving illicit drug use. As James Bakalar and Lester Grinspoon point out: When we talk about the dangers to health caused by drugs, we tend to use the broadest possible definition of health to justify the strongest restrictions. When we establish legitimate purposes for using drugs, of which health is obviously one, we try to define health narrowly so that again we can justify severe restrictions. Health as positive liberty - total well being - is a legitimate reason for banning drugs but not for using them. Drug Control in a Free Society (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), p. 129.
    • (1984) Drug Control in a Free Society , pp. 129
  • 19
    • 0041161608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Process, the Constitution, and Substantive Criminal Law
    • When I say that a legislator "cannot" make such judgments, I should not be understood to suggest that courts would find that legislatures lack the constitutional authority to make them. Under current law, state legislatures appear to have almost unlimited authority to create criminal offenses or to refuse to recognize criminal law defenses. See Louis Bilionis, "Process, the Constitution, and Substantive Criminal Law," Michigan Law Review 96 (1998).
    • (1998) Michigan Law Review , vol.96
    • Bilionis, L.1
  • 20
    • 0003615787 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chap. 3
    • I do not mean to suggest that other possible replies are unavailable. 21 For a sustained effort to respond to harm-to-other rationales for drug proscriptions, see Douglas Husak, Drugs and Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), chap. 3.
    • (1992) Drugs and Rights
    • Husak, D.1
  • 21
    • 0004260399 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • The best way to proceed, I think, is to describe a paradigm of perfectly autonomous choice. Various factors (e.g., coercion) undermine the extent to which this paradigm is exemplified in actual choices. Somewhere along this continuum, a particular choice deviates from this paradigm to such a degree to become nonautonomous. No one should have a clear sense of exactly where this point should be located, or whether it should be located in the same place for all purposes for which a model of autonomous choice may be needed. Here I follow Joel Feinberg's suggestions about voluntariness in his Harm to Self (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 113-117.
    • (1986) Harm to Self , pp. 113-117
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 22
    • 85007607687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Partial Defenses
    • Suppose that the act of addictive drug use exemplifies a sufficient degree of autonomy to defeat the excuse of drug addiction. The question remains open, however, whether addiction should mitigate the quantum of justified punishment. No theory of mitigation is widely accepted. If mitigating circumstances are construed as "almost defenses," however, the case for mitigation would seem strong. For further thoughts, see Douglas Husak, "Partial Defenses" Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence 11 (1998), p. 167.
    • (1998) Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence , vol.11 , pp. 167
    • Husak, D.1
  • 23
    • 0346230037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Anyone who endorses this reply should be pressed to identify the degree of autonomy that is exemplified in the choice of the defendant who acts under duress in my paradigm case. Assignments of degrees of autonomy must not undermine the basis for granting an excuse of duress.
  • 24
    • 0242273664 scopus 로고
    • Causing the Conditions of One's Own Defense: A Study in the Limits of Criminal Law Doctrine
    • I borrow this term from Paul Robinson: "Causing the Conditions of One's Own Defense: A Study in the Limits of Criminal Law Doctrine," 71 Virginia Law Review 1 (1985).
    • (1985) Virginia Law Review , vol.71 , pp. 1
    • Robinson, P.1
  • 25
    • 0347491007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Model Penal Code, Sec. 2.09(2)
    • Model Penal Code, Sec. 2.09(2).
  • 26
    • 0347491005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See my subsequent discussions about the probabilities that users of addictive drugs will actually become addicted.
  • 27
    • 0347491006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This conception may or may not recognize as treatment the substitution of one addictive drug for another (e.g., methadone for heroin).
  • 28
    • 0030838641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Approaches in the Treatment of Substance Abuse
    • See, for example, "New Approaches in the Treatment of Substance Abuse," Journal of Drug Issues 27(1997), pp. 195-444.
    • (1997) Journal of Drug Issues , vol.27 , pp. 195-444
  • 29
    • 0348121117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This proposal encounters enormous practical problems. What modes of treatment would suffice to preclude liability? How recently must treatment have been sought? How sincere and conscientious must the addict have been in his attempt to quit? Of course, these same difficulties resurface in assessments of the claim that addicts are "really" to blame not for their actual drug use, but rather for their failure to seek treatment.
  • 30
    • 0346136079 scopus 로고
    • 397 U.S. 358
    • In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358 (1970) requires the state to bear the burden of proof with respect to all material elements of a criminal offense.
    • (1970) In re Winship
  • 31
    • 0346860512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Perhaps, however, the act of coercing the defendant is not as wrongful when the defendant is coerced to perform an act that is not itself wrongful.
  • 33
    • 0346860470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • On the other hand, addictive drug use has a second important dissimilarity from the two-party case of duress. In the two-party case, the act-type that coerces (viz., the threat) is a different act-type from the act-type performed under duress (viz., the driving of the getaway car). My fanciful example preserves this feature; the act-type of taking philoin makes the distinct act-type of studying philosophy irresistible. In real cases of drug use, however, the very act-type that creates the addiction - drug use - is the act-type subsequently performed as a result of that addiction. In other words, the same act-type that undermines autonomy is the act-type performed nonautonomously. This fact seems significant to the justification of criminalization.
  • 34
    • 0004956291 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chigao Press
    • See Robert Goodin, No Smoking (Chicago: University of Chigao Press, 1989), p. 99.
    • (1989) No Smoking , pp. 99
    • Goodin, R.1
  • 35
    • 0348121115 scopus 로고
    • Nonharmful Drug Use
    • See Charles Winick, "Nonharmful Drug Use," Milbank Quarterly 69 (1991).
    • (1991) Milbank Quarterly , vol.69
    • Winick, C.1
  • 36
    • 0003635146 scopus 로고
    • New Haven: Yale University Press
    • The variables that affect the probability that a given person will become addicted to a given drug involve set and setting in the classic work of Norman Zinberg, Drug, Set and Setting (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984).
    • (1984) Drug, Set and Setting
    • Zinberg, N.1
  • 37
    • 0346860508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These facts complicate the culpability-in-causing rationale for denying a defense of drug addiction. Although the initial act of drug use may be a culpable act that causes the subsequent lack of autonomy, it is not at all clear that it is a "reckless" act that makes the subsequent loss of autonomy "likely" - as is required to withhold the defense of duress.
  • 38
    • 0348121109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Recall that Odysseus does lose his autonomy in Homer's version, but is unsuccessful in steering the ship toward the sirens because his sailors have been disabled from hearing his commands.
  • 39
    • 0030663102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Integration of Generalized Vulnerability to Drug and Alcohol Addiction
    • The punishment of persons who will not become addicts would be easier to justify if we suppose that such persons are unlike Greeks in that they cannot be identified. But this supposition is dubious. First, those persons who have used addictive drugs for many years without already becoming addicted must be members of this class. Recall that Odysseus has already proved his ability to resist the siren's song. Moreover, even first-time users can employ various strategies to greatly reduce their risk of addiction. Finally, familial and genetic studies are helpful in predicting susceptibility to addiction. See Norman Miller, Jane Guttman, and Sonya Chawla, "Integration of Generalized Vulnerability to Drug and Alcohol Addiction," Journal of Addictive Diseases 16(1997), p. 7.
    • (1997) Journal of Addictive Diseases , vol.16 , pp. 7
    • Miller, N.1    Guttman, J.2    Chawla, S.3
  • 40
    • 0346860472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasonable Risk Creation and Overinclusive Legislation
    • See Douglas Husak, "Reasonable Risk Creation and Overinclusive Legislation," Buffalo Criminal Law Review 1 (1998), p. 599.
    • (1998) Buffalo Criminal Law Review , vol.1 , pp. 599
    • Husak, D.1
  • 41
    • 0346223275 scopus 로고
    • Gauging Criminal Harm: A Living-Standard Analysis
    • Perhaps the best framework is defended in Nils Jareborg and Andrew von Hirsch, "Gauging Criminal Harm: A Living-Standard Analysis," Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 11 (1991). I am unaware, however, how such an account could be applied to assess the seriousness of various drug offenses.
    • (1991) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol.11
    • Jareborg, N.1    Von Hirsch, A.2
  • 42
    • 0347490954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Presumably, there are no constitutional limits (short of the death penalty) on the severity of punishment for drug possession. See Harmelin v. Michigan, 111 S.Ct. 2680 (1991)
    • Presumably, there are no constitutional limits (short of the death penalty) on the severity of punishment for drug possession. See Harmelin v. Michigan, 111 S.Ct. 2680 (1991).
  • 43
    • 0346860456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Desert, Proportionality, and the Seriousness of Drug Offences
    • Andrew Ashworth and Martin Wasik (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • For further thoughts, see Douglas Husak, "Desert, Proportionality, and the Seriousness of Drug Offences," in Andrew Ashworth and Martin Wasik (eds.), Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), p. 187.
    • (1998) Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory , pp. 187
    • Husak, D.1
  • 44
    • 0346860443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Again, the classic work - on which countless researchers have expanded - is Zinberg, supra note 37.
  • 45
    • 0347490946 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Although the facts to which I will appeal are familiar to researchers, I am quite aware that they are contrary to public opinion about drugs. These claims may represent what Herbert Fingarette called "an open secret" in the context of his insightful discussion of alcoholism. See his Heavy Drinking (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988), p. 1.
    • (1988) Heavy Drinking , pp. 1
    • Fingarette, H.1
  • 47
    • 0003846876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Lindesmith Center, especially footnote 12
    • See Lynn Zimmer and John Morgan, Marijuana Myths, Marijuana Facts (New York: Lindesmith Center, 1997), p. 28, especially footnote 12.
    • (1997) Marijuana Myths, Marijuana Facts , pp. 28
    • Zimmer, L.1    Morgan, J.2
  • 48
    • 0346229945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., pp. 28-29, especially footnotes 13 and 21
    • Id., pp. 28-29, especially footnotes 13 and 21.
  • 49
    • 0348121044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • See Craig Reinarman and Harry Levine (eds.), Crack in America (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1997).
    • (1997) Crack in America
    • Reinarman, C.1    Levine, H.2
  • 50
    • 0022591327 scopus 로고
    • Abstinence Symptomatology and Psychiatric Diagnosis in Cocaine Abusers
    • See F. Gawin and H. Klebner, "Abstinence Symptomatology and Psychiatric Diagnosis in Cocaine Abusers," Archives of General Psychiatry 43 (1986).
    • (1986) Archives of General Psychiatry , vol.43
    • Gawin, F.1    Klebner, H.2
  • 51
    • 0003739168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press, Chapter Three
    • See Jerome Platt, Cocaine Addiction (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997), Chapter Three.
    • (1997) Cocaine Addiction
    • Platt, J.1
  • 52
    • 0026345701 scopus 로고
    • Addiction: The Troublesome Concept
    • See Ronald Akers: "Addiction: The Troublesome Concept," Journal of Drug Issues 21(1991), p. 777.
    • (1991) Journal of Drug Issues , vol.21 , pp. 777
    • Akers, R.1
  • 54
    • 0027971952 scopus 로고
    • Overview: A Comparison of Withdrawal Symptoms from Different Drug Classes
    • See R. West and M. Gossop, "Overview: A Comparison of Withdrawal Symptoms from Different Drug Classes," Addiction 89 (1994), p. 1483.
    • (1994) Addiction , vol.89 , pp. 1483
    • West, R.1    Gossop, M.2
  • 55
    • 0023426876 scopus 로고
    • A Psychomotor Stimulant Theory of Addiction
    • R. Wise and M. Bozarth, "A Psychomotor Stimulant Theory of Addiction," Psychological Review 94 (1987), p. 469.
    • (1987) Psychological Review , vol.94 , pp. 469
    • Wise, R.1    Bozarth, M.2
  • 56
    • 0346860422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Part I
    • See Part I.
  • 57
    • 0346860421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There is no reason to presuppose that only illicit drugs satisfy my criterion. The case for recognizing a defense for nicotine addicts - or for proscribing the use of tobacco to protect the autonomy of potential addicts - cannot be ruled out of hand.
  • 58
    • 0031940520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is Craving the Source of Compulsive Drug Use?
    • S. Tiffany and B. Carter, "Is Craving the Source of Compulsive Drug Use?" Journal of Psychopharmacology 12 (1998), p. 23.
    • (1998) Journal of Psychopharmacology , vol.12 , pp. 23
    • Tiffany, S.1    Carter, B.2
  • 60
    • 0028149603 scopus 로고
    • Nicotine Withdrawal Versus Other Drug Withdrawal Symptoms: Similarities and Dissimilarities
    • See J. Hughes, S. Higgins, and W. Bickel, "Nicotine Withdrawal Versus Other Drug Withdrawal Symptoms: Similarities and Dissimilarities," Addiction 89(1994), p. 1461.
    • (1994) Addiction , vol.89 , pp. 1461
    • Hughes, J.1    Higgins, S.2    Bickel, W.3
  • 61
    • 0024490514 scopus 로고
    • Comparing Tobacco Cigarette Dependence with Other Drug Dependencies
    • In one study, 74% of persons who sought treatment for drug dependence and who both smoked and used one or more illegal drugs reported that cigarettes would be at least as hard to give up as the substance for which they sought treatment. 57% said that cigarettes would be even harder to give up. See Lynn Kozlowski, et.al., "Comparing Tobacco Cigarette Dependence with Other Drug Dependencies," Journal of the American Medical Association 261 (1989), p. 898.
    • (1989) Journal of the American Medical Association , vol.261 , pp. 898
    • Kozlowski, L.1
  • 62
    • 21344453473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Other Prohibition: The Cigarette Crisis in Post-war Germany
    • See Henner Hess, "The Other Prohibition: The Cigarette Crisis in Post-war Germany," Crime, Law & Social Change 25 (1996), p. 43.
    • (1996) Crime, Law & Social Change , vol.25 , pp. 43
    • Hess, H.1
  • 63
    • 0024384981 scopus 로고
    • Drug Prohibition in the United States: Costs, Consequences, and Alternatives
    • I conclude only that the state interest in protecting the autonomy of potential addicts may provide a good reason to proscribe opiate use. Of course, this reason is not dispositive; many other conditions must also be satisfied. In addition, the enforcement of such proscriptions must do more good than harm. I am skeptical that the criminalization of any drug satisfies this latter condition. See Ethan Nadelmann: "Drug Prohibition in the United States: Costs, Consequences, and Alternatives," Science 245 (1989), p. 939.
    • (1989) Science , vol.245 , pp. 939
    • Nadelmann, E.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.