메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 45, Issue 4, 1999, Pages 506-524

The disciplined citizen: Thomas Hobbes, neostoicism and the critique of classical citizenship

(1)  Burchell, David a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0033249152     PISSN: 00049522     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1467-8497.00078     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (33)

References (129)
  • 1
    • 0009306988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for their thorough comments and excellent critical suggestions
    • Thanks to Jeffrey Minson and Duncan Ivison for helpful thoughts and advice. Thanks also to the reviewers for the Australian Journal of Politics and History for their thorough comments and excellent critical suggestions.
    • Australian Journal of Politics and History
    • Minson, J.1    Ivison, D.2
  • 4
    • 0004260025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Q. Skinner, Liberty Before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 3-11, 59-60; Q. Skinner, "Two Concepts of Citizenship", Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 55 (1993), pp. 403-419. Cf. Q. Skinner, "The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives", in R. Rorty, J.B. Schneedwind and Q. Skinner eds., Philosophy in History: Essays in the Historiography of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984). See also Skinner's parallel work on Hobbes and rhetoric, especially Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), interestingly presents a somewhat more ambivalent view of Hobbes' engagement with neo-classical "civil science".
    • (1998) Liberty before Liberalism , pp. 3-11
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 5
    • 0009433367 scopus 로고
    • Two concepts of citizenship
    • Q. Skinner, Liberty Before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 3-11, 59-60; Q. Skinner, "Two Concepts of Citizenship", Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 55 (1993), pp. 403-419. Cf. Q. Skinner, "The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives", in R. Rorty, J.B. Schneedwind and Q. Skinner eds., Philosophy in History: Essays in the Historiography of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984). See also Skinner's parallel work on Hobbes and rhetoric, especially Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), interestingly presents a somewhat more ambivalent view of Hobbes' engagement with neo-classical "civil science".
    • (1993) Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie , vol.55 , pp. 403-419
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 6
    • 0001996443 scopus 로고
    • The idea of negative liberty: Philosophical and historical perspectives
    • R. Rorty, J.B. Schneedwind and Q. Skinner eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Q. Skinner, Liberty Before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 3-11, 59-60; Q. Skinner, "Two Concepts of Citizenship", Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 55 (1993), pp. 403-419. Cf. Q. Skinner, "The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives", in R. Rorty, J.B. Schneedwind and Q. Skinner eds., Philosophy in History: Essays in the Historiography of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984). See also Skinner's parallel work on Hobbes and rhetoric, especially Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), interestingly presents a somewhat more ambivalent view of Hobbes' engagement with neo-classical "civil science".
    • (1984) Philosophy in History: Essays in the Historiography of Philosophy
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 7
    • 0003650067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, interestingly presents a somewhat more ambivalent view of Hobbes' engagement with neo-classical "civil science"
    • Q. Skinner, Liberty Before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 3-11, 59-60; Q. Skinner, "Two Concepts of Citizenship", Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 55 (1993), pp. 403-419. Cf. Q. Skinner, "The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives", in R. Rorty, J.B. Schneedwind and Q. Skinner eds., Philosophy in History: Essays in the Historiography of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984). See also Skinner's parallel work on Hobbes and rhetoric, especially Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), interestingly presents a somewhat more ambivalent view of Hobbes' engagement with neo-classical "civil science".
    • (1996) Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Skinner1
  • 8
    • 0009410260 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes' subject as citizen
    • M.G. Dietz ed., Lawrence, Kansas: University of Kansas Press
    • M.G. Dietz, "Hobbes' Subject as Citizen", in M.G. Dietz ed., Thomas Hobbes and Political Theory (Lawrence, Kansas: University of Kansas Press, 1990), pp. 92, 96 and 104-107.
    • (1990) Thomas Hobbes and Political Theory , pp. 92
    • Dietz, M.G.1
  • 9
    • 0004077791 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Oddly, Hobbes' views on citizenship have been given little emphasis in the major collections on his political thought such as K.C. Brown ed., Hobbes Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965) and G.A.J. Rogers and A. Ryan eds., Perspectives on Thomas Hobbes (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988) One of the few substantial recent discussions is in C. Condren, The Language of Politics in Seventeenth-Century England (London: Macmillan, 1994) chapter 3, passim but especially pp. 99-100. Condren's argument is that Hobbes, as part of a wider trend, systematically subsumes the concept "citizen" within the concept "subject": as my argument here may suggest, my own hunch is that for Hobbes citizenship is a particular form of the wider category of subjection.
    • (1965) Hobbes Studies
    • Brown, K.C.1
  • 10
    • 0009364031 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Oddly, Hobbes' views on citizenship have been given little emphasis in the major collections on his political thought such as K.C. Brown ed., Hobbes Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965) and G.A.J. Rogers and A. Ryan eds., Perspectives on Thomas Hobbes (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988) One of the few substantial recent discussions is in C. Condren, The Language of Politics in Seventeenth-Century England (London: Macmillan, 1994) chapter 3, passim but especially pp. 99-100. Condren's argument is that Hobbes, as part of a wider trend, systematically subsumes the concept "citizen" within the concept "subject": as my argument here may suggest, my own hunch is that for Hobbes citizenship is a particular form of the wider category of subjection.
    • (1988) Perspectives on Thomas Hobbes
    • Rogers, G.A.J.1    Ryan, A.2
  • 11
    • 0009364032 scopus 로고
    • London: Macmillan, chapter 3, passim but especially Condren's argument is that Hobbes, as part of a wider trend, systematically subsumes the concept "citizen" within the concept "subject": as my argument here may suggest, my own hunch is that for Hobbes citizenship is a particular form of the wider category of subjection
    • Oddly, Hobbes' views on citizenship have been given little emphasis in the major collections on his political thought such as K.C. Brown ed., Hobbes Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965) and G.A.J. Rogers and A. Ryan eds., Perspectives on Thomas Hobbes (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988) One of the few substantial recent discussions is in C. Condren, The Language of Politics in Seventeenth-Century England (London: Macmillan, 1994) chapter 3, passim but especially pp. 99-100. Condren's argument is that Hobbes, as part of a wider trend, systematically subsumes the concept "citizen" within the concept "subject": as my argument here may suggest, my own hunch is that for Hobbes citizenship is a particular form of the wider category of subjection.
    • (1994) The Language of Politics in Seventeenth-Century England , pp. 99-100
    • Condren, C.1
  • 12
    • 84936451680 scopus 로고
    • (introduction by M.M. Goldsmith). London: Frank Cass
    • The passages from De Cive I examine here have no direct parallels in any of Hobbes' earlier or later works, so far as I am aware. The Elements of Law contains extended discussions of the equality of humans in the state of nature, and of the formation of the social contract, but there is no direct reference to the classical claim about "man" as a "social animal". F. Tönnies ed. (introduction by M.M. Goldsmith). Thomas Hobbbes: The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic (London: Frank Cass, 1969), pp. 94-5. In Leviathan there are of course a number of celebrated polemics against Aristotle and "the Greek and Latin authors" in relation to classical doctrines of freedom and tyranny. R. Tuck ed., Thomas Hobbes: Leviathan (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 150; cf. pp. 470-471. But again Hobbes passes directly from the well-known chapter on "the natural condition of man" to his equally celebrated passages on the original contract without any mention of the classical doctrine of the "social animal". Tuck ed., Leviathan, pp. 86-100.
    • (1969) Thomas Hobbbes: The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic , pp. 94-95
    • Tönnies, F.1
  • 13
    • 0009365268 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, cf. pp. 470-471
    • The passages from De Cive I examine here have no direct parallels in any of Hobbes' earlier or later works, so far as I am aware. The Elements of Law contains extended discussions of the equality of humans in the state of nature, and of the formation of the social contract, but there is no direct reference to the classical claim about "man" as a "social animal". F. Tönnies ed. (introduction by M.M. Goldsmith). Thomas Hobbbes: The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic (London: Frank Cass, 1969), pp. 94-5. In Leviathan there are of course a number of celebrated polemics against Aristotle and "the Greek and Latin authors" in relation to classical doctrines of freedom and tyranny. R. Tuck ed., Thomas Hobbes: Leviathan (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 150; cf. pp. 470-471. But again Hobbes passes directly from the well-known chapter on "the natural condition of man" to his equally celebrated passages on the original contract without any mention of the classical doctrine of the "social animal". Tuck ed., Leviathan, pp. 86-100.
    • (1991) Thomas Hobbes: Leviathan , pp. 150
    • Tuck, R.1
  • 14
    • 0007075428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The passages from De Cive I examine here have no direct parallels in any of Hobbes' earlier or later works, so far as I am aware. The Elements of Law contains extended discussions of the equality of humans in the state of nature, and of the formation of the social contract, but there is no direct reference to the classical claim about "man" as a "social animal". F. Tönnies ed. (introduction by M.M. Goldsmith). Thomas Hobbbes: The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic (London: Frank Cass, 1969), pp. 94-5. In Leviathan there are of course a number of celebrated polemics against Aristotle and "the Greek and Latin authors" in relation to classical doctrines of freedom and tyranny. R. Tuck ed., Thomas Hobbes: Leviathan (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 150; cf. pp. 470-471. But again Hobbes passes directly from the well-known chapter on "the natural condition of man" to his equally celebrated passages on the original contract without any mention of the classical doctrine of the "social animal". Tuck ed., Leviathan, pp. 86-100.
    • Leviathan , pp. 86-100
    • Tuck1
  • 15
    • 0009364033 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • It is worth noting that Hobbes' depiction on Aristotle, like the great bulk of his polemical assault on the "nonsense" and "gibberish" of the schools, is something of a caricature. Here I am using the standard English translation of 1651, available in H. Warrender ed., Thomas Hobbes: De Cive: The English Version (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983) and B. Gert ed., Thomas Hobbes: Man and Citizen (London, 1978), the latter contains the full text of De Cive and selections from De Homine. However, contra Gert and Warrender, Richard Tuck has recently demonstrated that this was almost certainly an unauthorised translation. See R. Tuck, Philosophy and Government, 1572-1651 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 316 and R. Tuck, "A New Date for Filmer's Patriarcha", Historical Journal 29 (1986). Accordingly, where the exact wording of Hobbes' original text is important, I have returned to the Latin original.
    • (1983) Thomas Hobbes: De Cive: The English Version
    • Warrender, H.1
  • 16
    • 0009306721 scopus 로고
    • London, the latter contains the full text of De Cive and selections from De Homine. However, contra Gert and Warrender, Richard Tuck has recently demonstrated that this was almost certainly an unauthorised translation
    • It is worth noting that Hobbes' depiction on Aristotle, like the great bulk of his polemical assault on the "nonsense" and "gibberish" of the schools, is something of a caricature. Here I am using the standard English translation of 1651, available in H. Warrender ed., Thomas Hobbes: De Cive: The English Version (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983) and B. Gert ed., Thomas Hobbes: Man and Citizen (London, 1978), the latter contains the full text of De Cive and selections from De Homine. However, contra Gert and Warrender, Richard Tuck has recently demonstrated that this was almost certainly an unauthorised translation. See R. Tuck, Philosophy and Government, 1572-1651 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 316 and R. Tuck, "A New Date for Filmer's Patriarcha", Historical Journal 29 (1986). Accordingly, where the exact wording of Hobbes' original text is important, I have returned to the Latin original.
    • (1978) Thomas Hobbes: Man and Citizen
    • Gert, B.1
  • 17
    • 0003803168 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • It is worth noting that Hobbes' depiction on Aristotle, like the great bulk of his polemical assault on the "nonsense" and "gibberish" of the schools, is something of a caricature. Here I am using the standard English translation of 1651, available in H. Warrender ed., Thomas Hobbes: De Cive: The English Version (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983) and B. Gert ed., Thomas Hobbes: Man and Citizen (London, 1978), the latter contains the full text of De Cive and selections from De Homine. However, contra Gert and Warrender, Richard Tuck has recently demonstrated that this was almost certainly an unauthorised translation. See R. Tuck, Philosophy and Government, 1572-1651 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 316 and R. Tuck, "A New Date for Filmer's Patriarcha", Historical Journal 29 (1986). Accordingly, where the exact wording of Hobbes' original text is important, I have returned to the Latin original.
    • (1993) Philosophy and Government, 1572-1651 , pp. 316
    • Tuck, R.1
  • 18
    • 84974085407 scopus 로고
    • A new date for Filmer's Patriarcha
    • Accordingly, where the exact wording of Hobbes' original text is important, I have returned to the Latin original
    • It is worth noting that Hobbes' depiction on Aristotle, like the great bulk of his polemical assault on the "nonsense" and "gibberish" of the schools, is something of a caricature. Here I am using the standard English translation of 1651, available in H. Warrender ed., Thomas Hobbes: De Cive: The English Version (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983) and B. Gert ed., Thomas Hobbes: Man and Citizen (London, 1978), the latter contains the full text of De Cive and selections from De Homine. However, contra Gert and Warrender, Richard Tuck has recently demonstrated that this was almost certainly an unauthorised translation. See R. Tuck, Philosophy and Government, 1572-1651 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 316 and R. Tuck, "A New Date for Filmer's Patriarcha", Historical Journal 29 (1986). Accordingly, where the exact wording of Hobbes' original text is important, I have returned to the Latin original.
    • (1986) Historical Journal , vol.29
    • Tuck, R.1
  • 20
    • 0007075428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tuck ed., Leviathan, pp. 463-5.
    • Leviathan , pp. 463-465
    • Tuck1
  • 21
    • 0009404228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Short tract on first principles
    • By "accident" here Hobbes is gesturing to a more precise sense of the word in medieval logical disputation in which it designated a non-necessary attribute of a phenomenon
    • By "accident" here Hobbes is gesturing to a more precise sense of the word in medieval logical disputation in which it designated a non-necessary attribute of a phenomenon. See his Short Tract on First Principles, in Tönnies ed., Elements of Law, p. 194.
    • Elements of Law , pp. 194
  • 22
    • 0004349405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The phrase forensis quaedam amicitia in Hobbes' Latin original might equally mean "friendship of the forum" - the implication is not a narrowly commercial one
    • Gert ed., Man and Citizen, p. 111. The phrase forensis quaedam amicitia in Hobbes' Latin original might equally mean "friendship of the forum" - the implication is not a narrowly commercial one.
    • Man and Citizen , pp. 111
    • Gert1
  • 24
    • 0004343480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Warrender, De Cive: English Version, p. 44; Howard Warrender, De Cive: Latin Version. Elementa philosophica de cive (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), p. 92. Gerhard Oestreich's translation from the Latin original is more in tune with my arguments here: "Man is not fitted for society by nature, but by discipline". G. Oestreich, Neostoicism and the Early Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), p. 269.
    • De Cive: English Version , pp. 44
    • Warrender1
  • 25
    • 2642577166 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press. Gerhard Oestreich's translation from the Latin original is more in tune with my arguments here: "Man is not fitted for society by nature, but by discipline"
    • Warrender, De Cive: English Version, p. 44; Howard Warrender, De Cive: Latin Version. Elementa philosophica de cive (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), p. 92. Gerhard Oestreich's translation from the Latin original is more in tune with my arguments here: "Man is not fitted for society by nature, but by discipline". G. Oestreich, Neostoicism and the Early Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), p. 269.
    • (1983) De Cive: Latin Version. Elementa Philosophica de Cive , pp. 92
    • Warrender, H.1
  • 26
    • 0003500321 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Warrender, De Cive: English Version, p. 44; Howard Warrender, De Cive: Latin Version. Elementa philosophica de cive (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), p. 92. Gerhard Oestreich's translation from the Latin original is more in tune with my arguments here: "Man is not fitted for society by nature, but by discipline". G. Oestreich, Neostoicism and the Early Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), p. 269.
    • (1982) Neostoicism and the Early Modern State , pp. 269
    • Oestreich, G.1
  • 27
    • 0007075428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A point made clear in the "Review and Conclusion" to Leviathan, where Hobbes speaks distinctly of "contrary faculties" such as reason and eloquence being reconciled by a combination of "education and discipline", Tuck ed., Leviathan, p. 483.
    • Leviathan , pp. 483
    • Tuck1
  • 28
    • 0009364034 scopus 로고
    • Disciplina: The monastic and cleric origins of European civility
    • J. Monfasani and R.G. Musto eds., New York: Italica Press
    • See D. Knox, "Disciplina: The Monastic and Cleric Origins of European Civility", in J. Monfasani and R.G. Musto eds., Renaissance Society and Culture (New York: Italica Press, 1991), pp. 107-35.
    • (1991) Renaissance Society and Culture , pp. 107-135
    • Knox, D.1
  • 29
    • 0009410262 scopus 로고
    • New York: n.d. Here "natural" men follows his instincts of obedience, without understanding "why it is their duty to do so"; the presumed but unstated opposite is the "disciplined" man, who is both obedient and mindful of the sound reasons for his obedience
    • This is certainly what he meant in a strikingly similar formulation in the English-language Behemoth, written some twenty years later, where he mobilised the same dichotomy, using the English terms "nature" and "discipline": "Every man by nature, without discipline, does in all his actions look upon, as far as he can see, the benefit that shall redound to himself from his obedience". W. Molesworth ed., Thomas Hobbes: Behemoth: The History of the Causes of the Civil Wars of England (New York: n.d. 1682), p. 69. Here "natural" men follows his instincts of obedience, without understanding "why it is their duty to do so"; the presumed but unstated opposite is the "disciplined" man, who is both obedient and mindful of the sound reasons for his obedience.
    • (1682) Thomas Hobbes: Behemoth: The History of the Causes of the Civil Wars of England , pp. 69
    • Molesworth, W.1
  • 30
    • 0004349405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gert ed., Man and Citizen, p. 68; Warrender ed., De Cive: English Version, pp. 145-6. Compare Hobbes' use of the term "manners" in Leviathan, Tuck ed., Leviathan, pp. 69-70.
    • Man and Citizen , pp. 68
    • Gert1
  • 31
    • 0004343480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gert ed., Man and Citizen, p. 68; Warrender ed., De Cive: English Version, pp. 145-6. Compare Hobbes' use of the term "manners" in Leviathan, Tuck ed., Leviathan, pp. 69-70.
    • De Cive: English Version , pp. 145-146
    • Warrender1
  • 32
    • 0009365407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbes' use of the term "manners" in Leviathan
    • Gert ed., Man and Citizen, p. 68; Warrender ed., De Cive: English Version, pp. 145-6. Compare Hobbes' use of the term "manners" in Leviathan, Tuck ed., Leviathan, pp. 69-70.
    • Leviathan , pp. 69-70
    • Tuck1
  • 36
    • 0003476414 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge, 1948; new edition
    • I have no space here to consider the wider modern historical and theoretical literature on social discipline, or its strengths and limitations. Here the locus classicus is still Weber's discussion in Economy and Society. Weber sees military discipline as the source of all early modern social discipline, but does not discuss the ethical or political origins of these military techniques: H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills eds., From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (London: Routledge, 1948; new edition 1991), pp. 253-264. More recently Michel Foucault stressed the emergence of "the disciplines" in the eighteenth century as the source of modern social discipline - though he again had little or no interest in the prehistory of this story: M. Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (London: Allen Lane, 1977). M. Foucault, The Care of the Self (The History of Sexuality), vol. 3 (New York: Random House, 1986), partly remedies this absence by focusing on classical Stoic techniques of self-cultivation, while M. Foucault, "Governmentality", in G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P. Miller eds., The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality (London: Harvester, 1991), explicitly it briefly links techniques of self-government to the government of populations.
    • (1991) From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology , pp. 253-264
    • Gerth, H.H.1    Mills, C.W.2
  • 37
    • 0003823523 scopus 로고
    • London: Allen Lane
    • I have no space here to consider the wider modern historical and theoretical literature on social discipline, or its strengths and limitations. Here the locus classicus is still Weber's discussion in Economy and Society. Weber sees military discipline as the source of all early modern social discipline, but does not discuss the ethical or political origins of these military techniques: H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills eds., From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (London: Routledge, 1948; new edition 1991), pp. 253-264. More recently Michel Foucault stressed the emergence of "the disciplines" in the eighteenth century as the source of modern social discipline - though he again had little or no interest in the prehistory of this story: M. Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (London: Allen Lane, 1977). M. Foucault, The Care of the Self (The History of Sexuality), vol. 3 (New York: Random House, 1986), partly remedies this absence by focusing on classical Stoic techniques of self-cultivation, while M. Foucault, "Governmentality", in G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P. Miller eds., The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality (London: Harvester, 1991), explicitly it briefly links techniques of self-government to the government of populations.
    • (1977) Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison
    • Foucault, M.1
  • 38
    • 0009308156 scopus 로고
    • New York: Random House
    • I have no space here to consider the wider modern historical and theoretical literature on social discipline, or its strengths and limitations. Here the locus classicus is still Weber's discussion in Economy and Society. Weber sees military discipline as the source of all early modern social discipline, but does not discuss the ethical or political origins of these military techniques: H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills eds., From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (London: Routledge, 1948; new edition 1991), pp. 253-264. More recently Michel Foucault stressed the emergence of "the disciplines" in the eighteenth century as the source of modern social discipline - though he again had little or no interest in the prehistory of this story: M. Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (London: Allen Lane, 1977). M. Foucault, The Care of the Self (The History of Sexuality), vol. 3 (New York: Random House, 1986), partly remedies this absence by focusing on classical Stoic techniques of self-cultivation, while M. Foucault, "Governmentality", in G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P. Miller eds., The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality (London: Harvester, 1991), explicitly it briefly links techniques of self-government to the government of populations.
    • (1986) The Care of the Self (The History of Sexuality) , vol.3
    • Foucault, M.1
  • 39
    • 0003756219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (London: Harvester, 1991), explicitly it briefly links techniques of self-government to the government of populations
    • I have no space here to consider the wider modern historical and theoretical literature on social discipline, or its strengths and limitations. Here the locus classicus is still Weber's discussion in Economy and Society. Weber sees military discipline as the source of all early modern social discipline, but does not discuss the ethical or political origins of these military techniques: H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills eds., From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (London: Routledge, 1948; new edition 1991), pp. 253-264. More recently Michel Foucault stressed the emergence of "the disciplines" in the eighteenth century as the source of modern social discipline - though he again had little or no interest in the prehistory of this story: M. Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (London: Allen Lane, 1977). M. Foucault, The Care of the Self (The History of Sexuality), vol. 3 (New York: Random House, 1986), partly remedies this absence by focusing on classical Stoic techniques of self-cultivation, while M. Foucault, "Governmentality", in G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P. Miller eds., The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality (London: Harvester, 1991), explicitly it briefly links techniques of self-government to the government of populations.
    • The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality
    • Burchell, G.1    Gordon, C.2    Miller, P.3
  • 41
    • 0004351473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chapters 2-3 passim
    • Ibid., chapters 2-3 passim; cf. M. Viroli, From Politics to Reason of State, 1250-1500 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), chapters 3-6. Viroli's argument is that Machiavelli was fundamentally a Ciceronian humanist fallen among reason-of-state thieves: Viroli, From Politics, chapter 3.1 say "neo-Ciceronian" here because, as I have explained elsewhere, I believe Cicero's own conception of the "offices" of citizenship to be less distant from Hobbes' than is often supposed. See my "Civic Personae: MacIntyre, Cicero and Moral Personality", History of Political Thought 19 (1998), pp. 101-118.
    • Philosophy and Government
  • 42
    • 0003579853 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chapters 3-6. Viroli's argument is that Machiavelli was fundamentally a Ciceronian humanist fallen among reason-of-state thieves: Viroli, From Politics, chapter 3.1 say "neo-Ciceronian" here because, as I have explained elsewhere, I believe Cicero's own conception of the "offices" of citizenship to be less distant from Hobbes' than is often supposed
    • Ibid., chapters 2-3 passim; cf. M. Viroli, From Politics to Reason of State, 1250-1500 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), chapters 3-6. Viroli's argument is that Machiavelli was fundamentally a Ciceronian humanist fallen among reason-of-state thieves: Viroli, From Politics, chapter 3.1 say "neo-Ciceronian" here because, as I have explained elsewhere, I believe Cicero's own conception of the "offices" of citizenship to be less distant from Hobbes' than is often supposed. See my "Civic Personae: MacIntyre, Cicero and Moral Personality", History of Political Thought 19 (1998), pp. 101-118.
    • (1992) From Politics to Reason of State, 1250-1500
    • Viroli, M.1
  • 43
    • 0041633660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civic personae: MacIntyre, Cicero and moral personality
    • Ibid., chapters 2-3 passim; cf. M. Viroli, From Politics to Reason of State, 1250-1500 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), chapters 3-6. Viroli's argument is that Machiavelli was fundamentally a Ciceronian humanist fallen among reason-of-state thieves: Viroli, From Politics, chapter 3.1 say "neo-Ciceronian" here because, as I have explained elsewhere, I believe Cicero's own conception of the "offices" of citizenship to be less distant from Hobbes' than is often supposed. See my "Civic Personae: MacIntyre, Cicero and Moral Personality", History of Political Thought 19 (1998), pp. 101-118.
    • (1998) History of Political Thought , vol.19 , pp. 101-118
  • 45
    • 0009365269 scopus 로고
    • Immanuele Bekkero ed., Weidmann. The same passage contains the reference to similitudo temporo: "in qua similitudo et imago plurima temporum nostrorum"
    • The dedication is reproduced in Immanuele Bekkero ed., Cornelius Tacitus, ab J. Lipsio et.al., (Weidmann, 1831), pp. iv-v. The same passage contains the reference to similitudo temporo: "in qua similitudo et imago plurima temporum nostrorum".
    • (1831) Cornelius Tacitus
    • Lipsio, J.1
  • 47
    • 0009308157 scopus 로고
    • Princeton NJ: Prince ton University Press
    • On Lipsius' Tacitus, and its various editions, see Mark Morford, 'Tacitean Prudentia and the doctrines of Justus Lipsius", in T.J. Luce and A.J. Woodman eds., Tacitus and the Tacitean Tradition (Princeton NJ: Prince ton University Press, 1993), pp. 129-51.
    • (1993) Tacitus and the Tacitean Tradition , pp. 129-151
    • Luce, T.J.1    Woodman, A.J.2
  • 50
    • 0009368779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This reminder appears in Lipsius' "argument" for Seneca's eleventh epistle: Lodge, Workes, p. 182.
    • Workes , pp. 182
  • 51
    • 0041333540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From tacitism to reason of state
    • J.H. Burns ed., (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Peter Burke, "From Tacitism to Reason of State", in J.H. Burns ed., The Cambridge History of Political Thought, 1450-1700 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), p. 492.
    • The Cambridge History of Political Thought, 1450-1700 , pp. 492
    • Burke, P.1
  • 54
    • 0009410263 scopus 로고
    • (William Jones trans.), Amsterdam: De Capo, [1594]
    • J. Lipsius (William Jones trans.), Sixe Bookes of Politickes or Civil Doctrine (Amsterdam: De Capo, 1970 [1594]), p. 140. For the Latin original see J. Lipsius, Opera omnia, postremum ad ipso aucta et recensita (Antwerp: Plantin, 1637), volume pp. 1-116. Here I have mostly followed the admirable 1594 English translation, modernising the spelling so as not to unnecessarily complicate Lipsius' sparse Latin prose. I have also contracted antique forms (i.e. "foreeth" becomes "forces"), and removed capitals and emphases. Where a word is important I have put the Latin original after it in italics.
    • (1970) Sixe Bookes of Politickes or Civil Doctrine , pp. 140
    • Lipsius, J.1
  • 55
    • 0009306456 scopus 로고
    • Antwerp: Plantin, volume Here I have mostly followed the admirable 1594 English translation, modernising the spelling so as not to unnecessarily complicate Lipsius' sparse Latin prose. I have also contracted antique forms (i.e. "foreeth" becomes "forces"), and removed capitals and emphases. Where a word is important I have put the Latin original after it in italics
    • J. Lipsius (William Jones trans.), Sixe Bookes of Politickes or Civil Doctrine (Amsterdam: De Capo, 1970 [1594]), p. 140. For the Latin original see J. Lipsius, Opera omnia, postremum ad ipso aucta et recensita (Antwerp: Plantin, 1637), volume pp. 1-116. Here I have mostly followed the admirable 1594 English translation, modernising the spelling so as not to unnecessarily complicate Lipsius' sparse Latin prose. I have also contracted antique forms (i.e. "foreeth" becomes "forces"), and removed capitals and emphases. Where a word is important I have put the Latin original after it in italics.
    • (1637) Opera Omnia, Postremum Ad Ipso Aucta et Recensita , pp. 1-116
    • Lipsius, J.1
  • 56
    • 0009433368 scopus 로고
    • New York: New York Scholars Press
    • Lipsius later published much more on military questions, drawing on his understanding of Polybius. His De militia romana libri cinque was first published in Antwerp in 1595. See J.L. Saunders, Justus Lipsius: The Philosophy of Renaissance Stoicism (New York: New York Scholars Press, 1955), pp. 45-57.
    • (1955) Justus Lipsius: The Philosophy of Renaissance Stoicism , pp. 45-57
    • Saunders, J.L.1
  • 60
    • 0004350816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The term coercio also has implications of confinement, restraint, enclosure, and pruning - the last in particular echoing the horticultural "discipline" typical of the era: "Man ... disciplined nature too, with the artistically clipped trees and hedges of seventeenth-century parks and gardens". Oestreich, Neostoicism, pp. 269-70.
    • Neostoicism , pp. 269-270
    • Oestreich1
  • 62
  • 64
    • 0003228247 scopus 로고
    • Military organisation and the organisation of the state
    • F. Gilbert ed., New York: Oxford University Press
    • O. Hintze, "Military Organisation and the Organisation of the State", in F. Gilbert ed., The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975), pp. 198-202. On the English example, with both its differences and similarities, see J. Brewer, The Sinews of Power: War, Money and the English State, 1688-1776 (London: Allen and Unwin, 1989), passim.
    • (1975) The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze , pp. 198-202
    • Hintze, O.1
  • 65
    • 0003866505 scopus 로고
    • London: Allen and Unwin, passim
    • O. Hintze, "Military Organisation and the Organisation of the State", in F. Gilbert ed., The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975), pp. 198-202. On the English example, with both its differences and similarities, see J. Brewer, The Sinews of Power: War, Money and the English State, 1688-1776 (London: Allen and Unwin, 1989), passim.
    • (1989) The Sinews of Power: War, Money and the English State, 1688-1776
    • Brewer, J.1
  • 66
    • 0004350816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oestreich, Neostoicism, p. 271. Cf. W.H. McNeill, The Pursuit of Power: Technology, Armed force and Society since AD 1000 (Oxford: Blackwell, 1983), chapter 4.
    • Neostoicism , pp. 271
    • Oestreich1
  • 68
    • 0004178940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theatrum politicum: The genealogy of capital - Police and the state of prosperity
    • Burchell et.al. eds.
    • P. Pasquino, "Theatrum Politicum: The Genealogy of Capital - Police and the State of Prosperity", in Burchell et.al. eds., The Foucault Effect, pp. 109-110.
    • The Foucault Effect , pp. 109-110
    • Pasquino, P.1
  • 71
    • 0004178940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pasquino, "Theatrum Politicum", p. 114; on Petty, see T. Aspromourgos, "Political Economy and the Social Division of Labour: The Economics of Sir William Petty", Scottish Journal of Political Economy 33 (1986) and P. Buck, "Seventeenth Century political Arithmetic: Civil Strife and Vital Statistics", Isis 68 (1977).
    • Theatrum Politicum , pp. 114
    • Pasquino1
  • 72
    • 84974321164 scopus 로고
    • Political economy and the social division of labour: The economics of Sir William Petty
    • Pasquino, "Theatrum Politicum", p. 114; on Petty, see T. Aspromourgos, "Political Economy and the Social Division of Labour: The Economics of Sir William Petty", Scottish Journal of Political Economy 33 (1986) and P. Buck, "Seventeenth Century political Arithmetic: Civil Strife and Vital Statistics", Isis 68 (1977).
    • (1986) Scottish Journal of Political Economy , vol.33
    • Aspromourgos, T.1
  • 73
    • 0003271014 scopus 로고
    • Seventeenth century political arithmetic: Civil strife and vital statistics
    • Pasquino, "Theatrum Politicum", p. 114; on Petty, see T. Aspromourgos, "Political Economy and the Social Division of Labour: The Economics of Sir William Petty", Scottish Journal of Political Economy 33 (1986) and P. Buck, "Seventeenth Century political Arithmetic: Civil Strife and Vital Statistics", Isis 68 (1977).
    • (1977) Isis , vol.68
    • Buck, P.1
  • 75
    • 0004350996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am indebted to Duncan Ivison for pointing out to me the relevance of this passage in Leviathan for my wider argument
    • Mary Dietz also notes the importance of chapter 30 of Leviathan, but interprets it as a listing of civic virtues in the classical republican sense: Dietz, "Hobbes' Subject", pp. 107-111. I am indebted to Duncan Ivison for pointing out to me the relevance of this passage in Leviathan for my wider argument.
    • Hobbes' Subject , pp. 107-111
    • Dietz1
  • 76
    • 0007075428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tuck ed., Leviathan, pp. 233-36.
    • Leviathan , pp. 233-236
    • Tuck1
  • 77
    • 84875328384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 238-9.
    • Leviathan , pp. 238-239
  • 78
    • 0011969283 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, the corresponding passages (in Petty's Treatise of Taxes) are: on beggars, p. 20; on labour schemes, pp. 29-31; on taxation policy and its rationale
    • The standard edition of Petty's collected works is C.H. Hull ed., The Economic Writings of Sir William Petty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1899), the corresponding passages (in Petty's Treatise of Taxes) are: on beggars, p. 20; on labour schemes, pp. 29-31; on taxation policy and its rationale, pp. 91-95.
    • (1899) The Economic Writings of Sir William Petty , pp. 91-95
    • Hull, C.H.1
  • 79
    • 0002040952 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes' unAristotelian political rhetoric
    • See inter alia, Tom Sorell, "Hobbes' UnAristotelian Political Rhetoric", Philosophy and Rhetoric 23 (1990), pp. 96-108 and "Hobbes' Persuasive Civil Science", Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1990), pp. 342-51; Victoria Silver, "Hobbes on Rhetoric" in Tom Sorell ed., The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 329-45 and Conal Condren, "On the Rheotrical Foundations of Leviathan", History of Political Thought 11 (1990), pp. 703-20. Skinner's Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes, for all its great erudition, seems to me to miss much of this complexity.
    • (1990) Philosophy and Rhetoric , vol.23 , pp. 96-108
    • Sorell, T.1
  • 80
    • 84928830729 scopus 로고
    • Persuasive civil science
    • See inter alia, Tom Sorell, "Hobbes' UnAristotelian Political Rhetoric", Philosophy and Rhetoric 23 (1990), pp. 96-108 and "Hobbes' Persuasive Civil Science", Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1990), pp. 342-51; Victoria Silver, "Hobbes on Rhetoric" in Tom Sorell ed., The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 329-45 and Conal Condren, "On the Rheotrical Foundations of Leviathan", History of Political Thought 11 (1990), pp. 703-20. Skinner's Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes, for all its great erudition, seems to me to miss much of this complexity.
    • (1990) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.40 , pp. 342-351
    • Hobbes'1
  • 81
    • 0009433906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbes on rhetoric
    • Tom Sorell ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See inter alia, Tom Sorell, "Hobbes' UnAristotelian Political Rhetoric", Philosophy and Rhetoric 23 (1990), pp. 96-108 and "Hobbes' Persuasive Civil Science", Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1990), pp. 342-51; Victoria Silver, "Hobbes on Rhetoric" in Tom Sorell ed., The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 329-45 and Conal Condren, "On the Rheotrical Foundations of Leviathan", History of Political Thought 11 (1990), pp. 703-20. Skinner's Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes, for all its great erudition, seems to me to miss much of this complexity.
    • (1996) The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes , pp. 329-345
    • Silver, V.1
  • 82
    • 84930558500 scopus 로고
    • On the rheotrical foundations of Leviathan
    • See inter alia, Tom Sorell, "Hobbes' UnAristotelian Political Rhetoric", Philosophy and Rhetoric 23 (1990), pp. 96-108 and "Hobbes' Persuasive Civil Science", Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1990), pp. 342-51; Victoria Silver, "Hobbes on Rhetoric" in Tom Sorell ed., The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 329-45 and Conal Condren, "On the Rheotrical Foundations of Leviathan", History of Political Thought 11 (1990), pp. 703-20. Skinner's Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes, for all its great erudition, seems to me to miss much of this complexity.
    • (1990) History of Political Thought , vol.11 , pp. 703-720
    • Condren, C.1
  • 83
    • 0003650067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for all its great erudition, seems to me to miss much of this complexity
    • See inter alia, Tom Sorell, "Hobbes' UnAristotelian Political Rhetoric", Philosophy and Rhetoric 23 (1990), pp. 96-108 and "Hobbes' Persuasive Civil Science", Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1990), pp. 342-51; Victoria Silver, "Hobbes on Rhetoric" in Tom Sorell ed., The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 329-45 and Conal Condren, "On the Rheotrical Foundations of Leviathan", History of Political Thought 11 (1990), pp. 703-20. Skinner's Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes, for all its great erudition, seems to me to miss much of this complexity.
    • Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes
    • Skinner's1
  • 84
    • 0009308697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I support this claim in more detail in a forthcoming paper, "The Civis Perspicax: Rhetoric and Restraint in Early Modem Citizenship"
    • I support this claim in more detail in a forthcoming paper, "The Civis Perspicax: Rhetoric and Restraint in Early Modem Citizenship".
  • 85
    • 0004350816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have neither the space nor the expertise here to investigate these assertions, though it is worth noting that they would constitute a useful programme of scholarly research in their own right
    • Oestreich insists that several of Hobbes' key concepts in his mature works probably derived in the first instance from Lipsius: the distinction between inward faith and outward profession, and between reason and opinion (ratio and opinio), and the dangers of excessive liberty of thought, see Oestreich, Neostoicism, p. 115. I have neither the space nor the expertise here to investigate these assertions, though it is worth noting that they would constitute a useful programme of scholarly research in their own right.
    • Neostoicism , pp. 115
    • Oestreich1
  • 86
    • 0009435033 scopus 로고
    • Oxford; Clarendon Press, 2 volumes
    • On Gassendi, see Noel Malcolm ed., The Correspondence of Thomas Hobbes (Oxford; Clarendon Press, 1994), 2 volumes, p. 834; on Descartes, see Stephen Gaukroger, Descartes: An Intellectual Biography (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 65-7.
    • (1994) The Correspondence of Thomas Hobbes , pp. 834
    • Malcolm, N.1
  • 87
    • 0003425778 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • On Gassendi, see Noel Malcolm ed., The Correspondence of Thomas Hobbes (Oxford; Clarendon Press, 1994), 2 volumes, p. 834; on Descartes, see Stephen Gaukroger, Descartes: An Intellectual Biography (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 65-7.
    • (1995) Descartes: An Intellectual Biography , pp. 65-67
    • Gaukroger, S.1
  • 88
    • 0041183176 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes' study and the Hardwick library
    • This I have deduced from the information given in the lists unearthed by J.J. Hamilton, "Hobbes' Study and the Hardwick Library", Journal of the History of Philosophy 16 (1978), pp. 450-1.
    • (1978) Journal of the History of Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 450-451
    • Hamilton, J.J.1
  • 89
    • 0004351473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a 1656 letter to Hobbes, Henry Stubbes refers casually to Lipsius' arcane De recta pronunciatone, a work buried at the end of volume 1 of the Opera Omnia - clearly assuming that Hobbes understands the reference
    • Cf. Tuck, Philosophy and Government, p. 282. In a 1656 letter to Hobbes, Henry Stubbes refers casually to Lipsius' arcane De recta pronunciatone, a work buried at the end of volume 1 of the Opera Omnia - clearly assuming that Hobbes understands the reference.
    • Philosophy and Government , pp. 282
    • Tuck1
  • 91
    • 33747245462 scopus 로고
    • Stoicism and roman example: Seneca and Tacitus in Jacobean England
    • J.H.M. Salmon, "Stoicism and Roman Example: Seneca and Tacitus in Jacobean England", Journal of the History of Ideas 50 (1989), p. 212.
    • (1989) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.50 , pp. 212
    • Salmon, J.H.M.1
  • 92
    • 0009363157 scopus 로고
    • New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, This is one of the very few favourable references to any modern authority in any of Hobbes' major works
    • R. Schlatter ed., Hobbes' Thucydides (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1975), p. 27. This is one of the very few favourable references to any modern authority in any of Hobbes' major works.
    • (1975) Hobbes' Thucydides , pp. 27
    • Schlatter, R.1
  • 95
    • 0009307879 scopus 로고
    • Dialogua de oratoriubs
    • Harvard, Mass.: Harvard University Press, Tacitus' words are inflatus, tumens, superfluens and parum Atticus
    • C. Tacitus, "Dialogua de Oratoriubs", in Agricola, Germania, Dialogus (Harvard, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970), p. 278. Tacitus' words are inflatus, tumens, superfluens and parum Atticus. Cf. M.W. Croll, (J.M. Patrick and R.O. Evans eds.), "Attic" and Baroque Prose Style: The Anti-Ciceronian Movement (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1966), pp. 54-82.
    • (1970) Agricola, Germania, Dialogus , pp. 278
    • Tacitus, C.1
  • 96
    • 0009307880 scopus 로고
    • (J.M. Patrick and R.O. Evans eds.), Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • C. Tacitus, "Dialogua de Oratoriubs", in Agricola, Germania, Dialogus (Harvard, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970), p. 278. Tacitus' words are inflatus, tumens, superfluens and parum Atticus. Cf. M.W. Croll, (J.M. Patrick and R.O. Evans eds.), "Attic" and Baroque Prose Style: The Anti-Ciceronian Movement (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1966), pp. 54-82.
    • (1966) "Attic" and Baroque Prose Style: The Anti-Ciceronian Movement , pp. 54-82
    • Croll, M.W.1
  • 99
    • 0009306724 scopus 로고
    • (J. Stradling Irans.), [1594] New Brunswick NJ: Rutgers University Press
    • R. Kirk ed. (J. Stradling Irans.), Two Bookes of Constancie, Written in Latin by Iustus Lipsius (De constantia libri duo)[1594] (New Brunswick NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1939), pp. 20-32; Burke, "Tacitism", p. 493. Stradling was a member of Sidney's Neostoic circle: Salmon, "Stoicism and Roman Example", p. 206.
    • (1939) Two Bookes of Constancie, Written in Latin by Iustus Lipsius (De Constantia Libri Duo) , pp. 20-32
    • Kirk, R.1
  • 100
    • 84898476684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R. Kirk ed. (J. Stradling Irans.), Two Bookes of Constancie, Written in Latin by Iustus Lipsius (De constantia libri duo)[1594] (New Brunswick NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1939), pp. 20-32; Burke, "Tacitism", p. 493. Stradling was a member of Sidney's Neostoic circle: Salmon, "Stoicism and Roman Example", p. 206.
    • Tacitism , pp. 493
    • Burke1
  • 101
    • 0004339834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stradling was a member of Sidney's Neostoic circle
    • R. Kirk ed. (J. Stradling Irans.), Two Bookes of Constancie, Written in Latin by Iustus Lipsius (De constantia libri duo)[1594] (New Brunswick NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1939), pp. 20-32; Burke, "Tacitism", p. 493. Stradling was a member of Sidney's Neostoic circle: Salmon, "Stoicism and Roman Example", p. 206.
    • Stoicism and Roman Example , pp. 206
    • Salmon1
  • 102
    • 0009417636 scopus 로고
    • Seneca and the protestant mind: The influence of stoicism on puritan ethics
    • M. Todd, "Seneca and the Protestant Mind: The Influence of Stoicism on Puritan Ethics", Archiv für Reformationsgeschichte 74 (1983), p. 185.
    • (1983) Archiv für Reformationsgeschichte , vol.74 , pp. 185
    • Todd, M.1
  • 103
    • 84867396957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (London: William Stansby, 1614). Lodge's dedication is to Thomas, Earl of Suffolk - another Neostoic. See Salmon, "Stoicism and Roman Example"
    • Thomas Lodge ed., The Workes of Lucius Annaeus Seneca (London: William Stansby, 1614). Lodge's dedication is to Thomas, Earl of Suffolk - another Neostoic. See Salmon, "Stoicism and Roman Example", pp. 199-200.
    • The Workes of Lucius Annaeus Seneca , pp. 199-200
    • Lodge, T.1
  • 104
    • 0004350816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bacon was influenced both by the doctrines of Lipsius and the histories of Tacitus: Oestreich, Neostoicism, pp. 114-117. Ben Jonson was an inveterate Tacitian, and fashioned the house rules for his London club on Roman precepts collected by Lipsius: Salmon, "Stoicism and Roman Example", p. 219; J.E. Mason, Gentlefolk in the Making: Studies in the History of English Courtesy Literature and Related Topics from 1531-1774 (Philadelphia: Pennsylvania University Press, 1935), p. 284.
    • Neostoicism , pp. 114-117
    • Oestreich1
  • 105
    • 0004339834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bacon was influenced both by the doctrines of Lipsius and the histories of Tacitus: Oestreich, Neostoicism, pp. 114-117. Ben Jonson was an inveterate Tacitian, and fashioned the house rules for his London club on Roman precepts collected by Lipsius: Salmon, "Stoicism and Roman Example", p. 219; J.E. Mason, Gentlefolk in the Making: Studies in the History of English Courtesy Literature and Related Topics from 1531-1774 (Philadelphia: Pennsylvania University Press, 1935), p. 284.
    • Stoicism and Roman Example , pp. 219
    • Salmon1
  • 106
    • 0009306457 scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia: Pennsylvania University Press
    • Bacon was influenced both by the doctrines of Lipsius and the histories of Tacitus: Oestreich, Neostoicism, pp. 114-117. Ben Jonson was an inveterate Tacitian, and fashioned the house rules for his London club on Roman precepts collected by Lipsius: Salmon, "Stoicism and Roman Example", p. 219; J.E. Mason, Gentlefolk in the Making: Studies in the History of English Courtesy Literature and Related Topics from 1531-1774 (Philadelphia: Pennsylvania University Press, 1935), p. 284.
    • (1935) Gentlefolk in the Making: Studies in the History of English Courtesy Literature and Related Topics from 1531-1774 , pp. 284
    • Mason, J.E.1
  • 109
    • 0009365270 scopus 로고
    • London: Andrew Cook
    • T. Hobbes, The Questions Concerning Liberty, Necesity and Chance, Clearly Stated and Debated Between Dr Bramhall, Bishop of Derry, and Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury (London: Andrew Cook, 1656), p. 195. A recent scholarly assessment backs up Bramhall's view: see J.C. Kassler, "The paradox of power: Hobbes and Stoic Naturalism", in S. Gaukroger ed., The Uses of Antiquity: The Scientific Revolution and the Classical Tradition (Dordrecht, Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991). (In an otherwise stimulating article, Kassler misidentifies this quote as Hobbes' own self-description, when it is clearly attributed in the text to Bramhall.)
    • (1656) The Questions Concerning Liberty, Necesity and Chance, Clearly Stated and Debated Between Dr Bramhall, Bishop of Derry, and Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury , pp. 195
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 110
    • 0009307548 scopus 로고
    • The paradox of power: Hobbes and stoic naturalism
    • S. Gaukroger ed., Dordrecht, Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, (In an otherwise stimulating article, Kassler misidentifies this quote as Hobbes' own self-description, when it is clearly attributed in the text to Bramhall.)
    • T. Hobbes, The Questions Concerning Liberty, Necesity and Chance, Clearly Stated and Debated Between Dr Bramhall, Bishop of Derry, and Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury (London: Andrew Cook, 1656), p. 195. A recent scholarly assessment backs up Bramhall's view: see J.C. Kassler, "The paradox of power: Hobbes and Stoic Naturalism", in S. Gaukroger ed., The Uses of Antiquity: The Scientific Revolution and the Classical Tradition (Dordrecht, Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991). (In an otherwise stimulating article, Kassler misidentifies this quote as Hobbes' own self-description, when it is clearly attributed in the text to Bramhall.)
    • (1991) The Uses of Antiquity: The Scientific Revolution and the Classical Tradition
    • Kassler, J.C.1
  • 113
    • 0004346021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lipsius, Sixe Bookes, pp. 62-63; cf. Saunders, Justus Lipsius, pp. 30-31.
    • Sixe Bookes , pp. 62-63
    • Lipsius1
  • 114
    • 0004350034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lipsius, Sixe Bookes, pp. 62-63; cf. Saunders, Justus Lipsius, pp. 30-31.
    • Justus Lipsius , pp. 30-31
    • Saunders1
  • 115
    • 0004350034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Saunders, Justus Lipsius, pp. 11-42. There was another Lipsian "cult" in the quintessentially Catholic Spanish court in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries: T.G. Corbett, "The Cult of Lipsius: A Leading Source of Early Modern Spanish Statecraft", Journal of the History of Ideas 36 (1975).
    • Justus Lipsius , pp. 11-42
    • Saunders1
  • 116
    • 0009416556 scopus 로고
    • The cult of Lipsius: A leading source of early modern spanish statecraft
    • Saunders, Justus Lipsius, pp. 11-42. There was another Lipsian "cult" in the quintessentially Catholic Spanish court in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries: T.G. Corbett, "The Cult of Lipsius: A Leading Source of Early Modern Spanish Statecraft", Journal of the History of Ideas 36 (1975).
    • (1975) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.36
    • Corbett, T.G.1
  • 118
    • 0009368781 scopus 로고
    • Here again I have modernised the English translation (see footnote 39 above)
    • Kirk ed., Two Bookes of Constancie, pp. 92-93. Here again I have modernised the 1594 English translation (see footnote 39 above).
    • (1594) Two Bookes of Constancie , pp. 92-93
    • Kirk1
  • 120
    • 0009364039 scopus 로고
    • This was one of Lipsius' favourite metaphors: see the dedication to his Tacitus, where he writes of those "in whose hands are the rudder and tiller of the republic"
    • Ibid., pp. 96-98. This was one of Lipsius' favourite metaphors: see the 1581 dedication to his Tacitus, where he writes of those "in whose hands are the rudder and tiller of the republic". Bekkero, Cornelius Tacitus, p. iv; cf. Morford, "Tacitean Prudentia", pp. 138-9.
    • (1581) Two Bookes of Constancie , pp. 96-98
  • 121
    • 0009355919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 96-98. This was one of Lipsius' favourite metaphors: see the 1581 dedication to his Tacitus, where he writes of those "in whose hands are the rudder and tiller of the republic". Bekkero, Cornelius Tacitus, p. iv; cf. Morford, "Tacitean Prudentia", pp. 138-9.
    • Cornelius Tacitus
    • Bekkero1
  • 122
    • 0009363158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 96-98. This was one of Lipsius' favourite metaphors: see the 1581 dedication to his Tacitus, where he writes of those "in whose hands are the rudder and tiller of the republic". Bekkero, Cornelius Tacitus, p. iv; cf. Morford, "Tacitean Prudentia", pp. 138-9.
    • Tacitean Prudentia , pp. 138-139
    • Morford1
  • 123
    • 0004287799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tuck ed., Leviathan, pp. 150 and 461.
    • Leviathan , pp. 150
    • Tuck1
  • 124
    • 0009367115 scopus 로고
    • Civic life
    • Annie Romein-Verschoor ed., Amsterdam
    • I have no space to discuss this wider literature. Two examples are, however, the Civic Life or Vita Politica of Simon Stevin (CV Swits and Zeitlinger, 1590), and Samuel Pufendorf's much more well-known treatise on "man and citizen". It so happens that Stevin was a student and lecturer at the University of Leiden at precisely the moment when Lipsius was on of its "most respected and famous" scholars, and that Pufendorf was also (much later) a student of Leiden, where he was influenced by the Lipsian legacy of Stoic teaching, as well as by Hobbes' De Cive. See Simon Stevin, Civic Life in Annie Romein-Verschoor ed., The Principal Works of Simon Steven (Amsterdam: 1966) and James Tully ed., Samuel Pufendorf: on the Duty of Man and Citizen According to Natural Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). See also the discussion in my "The Attributes of Citizens; Virtue, Manners and the Activity of Citizenship", Economy and Society 24 (1995).
    • (1966) The Principal Works of Simon Steven
    • Stevin, S.1
  • 125
    • 0003946050 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • I have no space to discuss this wider literature. Two examples are, however, the Civic Life or Vita Politica of Simon Stevin (CV Swits and Zeitlinger, 1590), and Samuel Pufendorf's much more well-known treatise on "man and citizen". It so happens that Stevin was a student and lecturer at the University of Leiden at precisely the moment when Lipsius was on of its "most respected and famous" scholars, and that Pufendorf was also (much later) a student of Leiden, where he was influenced by the Lipsian legacy of Stoic teaching, as well as by Hobbes' De Cive. See Simon Stevin, Civic Life in Annie Romein-Verschoor ed., The Principal Works of Simon Steven (Amsterdam: 1966) and James Tully ed., Samuel Pufendorf: on the Duty of Man and Citizen According to Natural Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). See also the discussion in my "The Attributes of Citizens; Virtue, Manners and the Activity of Citizenship", Economy and Society 24 (1995).
    • (1991) Samuel Pufendorf: On the Duty of Man and Citizen According to Natural Law
    • Tully, J.1
  • 126
    • 0029521308 scopus 로고
    • The attributes of citizens; virtue, manners and the activity of citizenship
    • I have no space to discuss this wider literature. Two examples are, however, the Civic Life or Vita Politica of Simon Stevin (CV Swits and Zeitlinger, 1590), and Samuel Pufendorf's much more well-known treatise on "man and citizen". It so happens that Stevin was a student and lecturer at the University of Leiden at precisely the moment when Lipsius was on of its "most respected and famous" scholars, and that Pufendorf was also (much later) a student of Leiden, where he was influenced by the Lipsian legacy of Stoic teaching, as well as by Hobbes' De Cive. See Simon Stevin, Civic Life in Annie Romein-Verschoor ed., The Principal Works of Simon Steven (Amsterdam: 1966) and James Tully ed., Samuel Pufendorf: on the Duty of Man and Citizen According to Natural Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). See also the discussion in my "The Attributes of Citizens; Virtue, Manners and the Activity of Citizenship", Economy and Society 24 (1995).
    • (1995) Economy and Society , vol.24
  • 127
    • 0003353510 scopus 로고
    • Citizenship
    • Terence Ball, James Farr and Russell L. Hanson eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Michael Walzer, "Citizenship", in Terence Ball, James Farr and Russell L. Hanson eds., Political Innovation and Conceptual Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), p. 215.
    • (1989) Political Innovation and Conceptual Change , pp. 215
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 129
    • 0002248143 scopus 로고
    • Citizenship and social class
    • reprinted in Chicago: Chicago University Press, [1949]
    • TH Marshall, "Citizenship and Social Class", reprinted in Class, Citizenship and Social Development (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1977 [1949]).
    • (1977) Class, Citizenship and Social Development
    • Marshall, T.H.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.