-
1
-
-
0040010474
-
International society: Theoretical promises unfulfilled?
-
Consider Ole Waever, "International Society: Theoretical Promises Unfulfilled?" Cooperation and Conflict 26 (1991), 97-128; and Pierre Hassner, La violence et la paix: De la bombe atomique au nettoyage ethnique (Paris: Éditions Esprit, 1995), 343-54, 385.
-
(1991)
Cooperation and Conflict
, vol.26
, pp. 97-128
-
-
Waever, O.1
-
2
-
-
0040010474
-
-
Paris: Éditions Esprit
-
Consider Ole Waever, "International Society: Theoretical Promises Unfulfilled?" Cooperation and Conflict 26 (1991), 97-128; and Pierre Hassner, La violence et la paix: De la bombe atomique au nettoyage ethnique (Paris: Éditions Esprit, 1995), 343-54, 385.
-
(1995)
La Violence et la Paix: De la Bombe Atomique au Nettoyage Ethnique
, pp. 343-354
-
-
Hassner, P.1
-
3
-
-
84927107254
-
Distant compassion: CNN and Borrioboola-Gha
-
See Clifford Orwin, "Distant Compassion: CNN and Borrioboola-Gha," The National Interest 43 (1996), 42-49.
-
(1996)
The National Interest
, vol.43
, pp. 42-49
-
-
Orwin, C.1
-
4
-
-
0003416045
-
-
Paris: Galilée
-
Jacques Derrida, Cosmopolites de tous les pays, encore un effort! (Paris: Galilée, 1997), 20. Derrida cites Hannah Arendt's discussion in Les origines du totalitarisme. L'impérialisme, trans. by Martine Leiris (Paris: Fayard-Seuil, 1984), 239ff., of the decline of the ancient, fundamental ius gentium right of asylum as a major step on the road to the conditions that made totalitarianism possible. Writing in 1950, Arendt notes in particular that this ancient right finds no expression in written international law or the various United Nations declarations of human rights, since they derive from wholly modern and un-Stoic conceptions of the human community and the cosmopolitan principles of justice.
-
(1997)
Cosmopolites de Tous les Pays, Encore Un Effort!
, pp. 20
-
-
Derrida, J.1
-
5
-
-
26144459192
-
-
cites Hannah Arendt's discussion trans. by Martine Leiris (Paris: Fayard-Seuil)
-
Jacques Derrida, Cosmopolites de tous les pays, encore un effort! (Paris: Galilée, 1997), 20. Derrida cites Hannah Arendt's discussion in Les origines du totalitarisme. L'impérialisme, trans. by Martine Leiris (Paris: Fayard-Seuil, 1984), 239ff., of the decline of the ancient, fundamental ius gentium right of asylum as a major step on the road to the conditions that made totalitarianism possible. Writing in 1950, Arendt notes in particular that this ancient right finds no expression in written international law or the various United Nations declarations of human rights, since they derive from wholly modern and un-Stoic conceptions of the human community and the cosmopolitan principles of justice.
-
(1984)
Les Origines du Totalitarisme. L'Impérialisme
-
-
Derrida1
-
6
-
-
0002881433
-
The making of global citizenship
-
Jeremy Brecher, John Brown Childs and Jill Cutler, eds., Boston: South End Press
-
See especially Richard Falk, "The Making of Global Citizenship," in Jeremy Brecher, John Brown Childs and Jill Cutler, eds., Global Visions: Beyond the New World Order (Boston: South End Press, 1993).
-
(1993)
Global Visions: Beyond the New World Order
-
-
Falk, R.1
-
9
-
-
0040603738
-
On the common saying, 'this may be true in theory, but it does not apply in practice
-
Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying, 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice," Part 3 ("On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right"); "Idea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent," Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant's Political Writings, trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), esp. 103, where Grotius is explicitly dismissed as a "sorry comforter"; "Doctrine of Right," Part 2 ("Public Right"), Metaphysics of Morals, secs. 2 and 3. Derrida's invocation of Kant (Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 47-52) seems to indicate an insufficient appreciation of Kant's severe reservations about the sort of cosmopolitanism Derrida is championing; Derrida is eventually forced to recognize that there is at least a considerable tension between his position and that of Kant (53-57).
-
On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right
, Issue.3 PART
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
10
-
-
0003020378
-
Idea for a universal history with cosmopolitan intent
-
Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," Hans Reiss, ed., trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying, 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice," Part 3 ("On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right"); "Idea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent," Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant's Political Writings, trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), esp. 103, where Grotius is explicitly dismissed as a "sorry comforter"; "Doctrine of Right," Part 2 ("Public Right"), Metaphysics of Morals, secs. 2 and 3. Derrida's invocation of Kant (Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 47-52) seems to indicate an insufficient appreciation of Kant's severe reservations about the sort of cosmopolitanism Derrida is championing; Derrida is eventually forced to recognize that there is at least a considerable tension between his position and that of Kant (53-57).
-
(1970)
Kant's Political Writings
, pp. 103
-
-
-
11
-
-
0041197796
-
"Doctrine of right," part 2 ("Public right")
-
secs. 2 and 3
-
Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying, 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice," Part 3 ("On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right"); "Idea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent," Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant's Political Writings, trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), esp. 103, where Grotius is explicitly dismissed as a "sorry comforter"; "Doctrine of Right," Part 2 ("Public Right"), Metaphysics of Morals, secs. 2 and 3. Derrida's invocation of Kant (Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 47-52) seems to indicate an insufficient appreciation of Kant's severe reservations about the sort of cosmopolitanism Derrida is championing; Derrida is eventually forced to recognize that there is at least a considerable tension between his position and that of Kant (53-57).
-
Metaphysics of Morals
-
-
-
12
-
-
0003416045
-
-
Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying, 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice," Part 3 ("On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right"); "Idea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent," Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant's Political Writings, trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), esp. 103, where Grotius is explicitly dismissed as a "sorry comforter"; "Doctrine of Right," Part 2 ("Public Right"), Metaphysics of Morals, secs. 2 and 3. Derrida's invocation of Kant (Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 47-52) seems to indicate an insufficient appreciation of Kant's severe reservations about the sort of cosmopolitanism Derrida is championing; Derrida is eventually forced to recognize that there is at least a considerable tension between his position and that of Kant (53-57).
-
Cosmopolites de Tous les Pays
, pp. 47-52
-
-
Derrida1
-
13
-
-
0004039689
-
-
Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press
-
Raymond Aron (who has himself been sometimes identified as a leading "realist" - Michael Joseph Smith, Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger [Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986], 2) has observed that it is the tendency of all contemporary realist thought to "think against" (Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, trans. by Richard Howard and Annette Baker Fox [New York: Praeger, 1967], 596).
-
(1986)
Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger
, pp. 2
-
-
Smith, M.J.1
-
14
-
-
0039418299
-
-
New York: Praeger
-
Raymond Aron (who has himself been sometimes identified as a leading "realist" - Michael Joseph Smith, Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger [Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986], 2) has observed that it is the tendency of all contemporary realist thought to "think against" (Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, trans. by Richard Howard and Annette Baker Fox [New York: Praeger, 1967], 596).
-
(1967)
Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations
, pp. 596
-
-
Howard, R.1
Fox, A.B.2
-
15
-
-
0003700672
-
-
Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
Sandel is responding directly to an earlier, more popular, version of the Nussbaum thesis: see Michael J. Sandel, Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996), 338-46; Sandel cites Nussbaum, "Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism," Boston Review (October-November 1994), 3.
-
(1996)
Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy
, pp. 338-346
-
-
Sandel, M.J.1
-
16
-
-
0001858860
-
Patriotism and cosmopolitanism
-
October-November
-
Sandel is responding directly to an earlier, more popular, version of the Nussbaum thesis: see Michael J. Sandel, Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996), 338-46; Sandel cites Nussbaum, "Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism," Boston Review (October-November 1994), 3.
-
(1994)
Boston Review
, pp. 3
-
-
Sandel1
-
17
-
-
84876041711
-
-
Cicero On Duties 3.69, 3.74. I cite the works of Cicero and other classical authors according to standard form, using recognized critical editions; unless otherwise noted, all translations from these and other sources are my own.
-
On Duties
, pp. 369
-
-
Cicero1
-
18
-
-
0041197800
-
-
Ibid., 1.1-3, 2.2-6, 2.23, 2.29, 2.65, 2.67, 2.75-76, 3.1-4; Cicero On the Nature of the Gods 1.7; Cicero Republic 1.6-7; and Cicero On Divination 1.2; 2.6-7.
-
On Duties
, pp. 11-13
-
-
-
19
-
-
0041197815
-
-
Ibid., 1.1-3, 2.2-6, 2.23, 2.29, 2.65, 2.67, 2.75-76, 3.1-4; Cicero On the Nature of the Gods 1.7; Cicero Republic 1.6-7; and Cicero On Divination 1.2; 2.6-7.
-
On the Nature of the Gods
, pp. 17
-
-
Cicero1
-
20
-
-
0040010470
-
-
Ibid., 1.1-3, 2.2-6, 2.23, 2.29, 2.65, 2.67, 2.75-76, 3.1-4; Cicero On the Nature of the Gods 1.7; Cicero Republic 1.6-7; and Cicero On Divination 1.2; 2.6-7.
-
Cicero Republic
, pp. 16-17
-
-
-
21
-
-
0041197817
-
-
Ibid., 1.1-3, 2.2-6, 2.23, 2.29, 2.65, 2.67, 2.75-76, 3.1-4; Cicero On the Nature of the Gods 1.7; Cicero Republic 1.6-7; and Cicero On Divination 1.2; 2.6-7.
-
On Divination
, pp. 12
-
-
Cicero1
-
22
-
-
84876041711
-
-
See, for example, Cicero On Duties 3.23, 3.69.
-
On Duties
, pp. 323
-
-
Cicero1
-
23
-
-
0041197812
-
-
For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
-
On Laws and God the Lawgiver
, pp. 2198
-
-
Cicero1
-
24
-
-
0041197813
-
-
Isidore of Seville
-
For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
-
Of Etymologies or Origins
, pp. 54-57
-
-
-
25
-
-
0041197814
-
-
For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
-
From the Founding of the City
, pp. 24
-
-
Livy1
-
26
-
-
0040010458
-
-
Brussels: C. Muquardt
-
For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
-
(1882)
Le Droit de la Guerre et les Précurseurs de Grotius
, pp. 9-13
-
-
Ernest, N.1
-
27
-
-
0039418323
-
-
2 vols.; London: Macmillan
-
For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
-
(1911)
The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome
, Issue.1
, pp. 57-58
-
-
Phillipson, C.1
-
28
-
-
0041073778
-
-
1368b7-9
-
For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
-
Rhetoric
-
-
Aristotle1
-
29
-
-
84886617346
-
-
Plutarch, in what is probably a deliberate rhetorical exaggeration, goes so far as to suggest that there is a link between Zeno of Citium's Republic and Alexander the Great's cosmopolitan imperial vision (On the Fortune or Virtue of Alexander the Great 329a-b), and Philo Judaeus (On the Creation of the World 3 and 142-43) contends that the biblical account of creation in Genesis is meant to teach the Stoic notion of cosmopolitan natural law and world citizenship (in other words, the principles of Stoicism are in fact the principles of the biblical God).
-
On the Fortune or Virtue of Alexander the Great
-
-
Plutarch1
-
30
-
-
84867806019
-
-
Plutarch, in what is probably a deliberate rhetorical exaggeration, goes so far as to suggest that there is a link between Zeno of Citium's Republic and Alexander the Great's cosmopolitan imperial vision (On the Fortune or Virtue of Alexander the Great 329a-b), and Philo Judaeus (On the Creation of the World 3 and 142-43) contends that the biblical account of creation in Genesis is meant to teach the Stoic notion of cosmopolitan natural law and world citizenship (in other words, the principles of Stoicism are in fact the principles of the biblical God).
-
On the Creation of the World
, pp. 3
-
-
Judaeus, P.1
-
31
-
-
0040010475
-
-
Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
-
Symposium
, pp. 29-113
-
-
Xenophon1
-
32
-
-
0003548526
-
-
Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104
-
Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
-
Lives of the Eminent Philosophers
-
-
Laertius, D.1
-
33
-
-
0039418328
-
-
Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
-
Outlines of Pyrrhonism
, pp. 3200
-
-
Empiricus, S.1
-
34
-
-
0041197809
-
-
4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis
-
Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
-
(1990)
Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae
, pp. 2139-2509
-
-
Giannantoni, G.1
-
35
-
-
0041197801
-
-
Giannantoni's discussion
-
Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
0003548526
-
-
Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
Lives of the Eminent Philosophers
-
-
Laertius, D.1
-
37
-
-
84883566408
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
Discourses
, pp. 142
-
-
Chrysostom, D.1
-
38
-
-
0040603737
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists)
, vol.5
, pp. 22-27
-
-
Empiricus, S.1
-
39
-
-
0039418326
-
-
H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner), frags. 190, 192, 195
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
(1904)
On Stoic Self-contradictions; of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics
, vol.1
-
-
Plutarch1
-
40
-
-
0039418330
-
-
frags. 528, 1195
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
On Stoic Self-contradictions; of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics
, vol.2
-
-
-
41
-
-
0039418327
-
-
frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
On Stoic Self-contradictions; of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics
, vol.3
-
-
-
42
-
-
0041197804
-
-
Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things
-
-
Cicero1
-
43
-
-
0039418329
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
Academica
, pp. 135-139
-
-
-
44
-
-
0041197815
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
On the Nature of the Gods
, pp. 116
-
-
-
45
-
-
0041197817
-
-
Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
On Divination
-
-
-
46
-
-
0040010473
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
Of Leisure
, pp. 4
-
-
Seneca1
-
47
-
-
25444451744
-
-
"On the Cynic Calling."
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
-
Discourses of Epictetus
, pp. 322
-
-
Arrian1
-
48
-
-
0003548526
-
-
Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
Lives of the Eminent Philosophers
-
-
Laertius, D.1
-
49
-
-
0041197799
-
-
frags. 216, 228
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta
, vol.1
-
-
-
50
-
-
0041197807
-
-
frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta
, vol.3
-
-
-
51
-
-
0039418322
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
Oration in Defense of L. Murena
, pp. 61
-
-
Cicero1
-
52
-
-
0039418319
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things
, pp. 348
-
-
-
53
-
-
0040010459
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
Laws
, pp. 314
-
-
-
54
-
-
0040603734
-
-
Bk. 2
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
Lucullus (or Academica)
, pp. 136-137
-
-
-
55
-
-
0039418325
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
On Duties
, pp. 1128
-
-
-
56
-
-
84870792806
-
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
Tusculan Disputations
, pp. 454
-
-
-
57
-
-
0040010461
-
Zeno's republic and the origins of natural law
-
Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., Ithaca: Cornell University Press
-
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
-
(1994)
The Socratic Movement
-
-
Waerdt, P.A.V.1
-
58
-
-
0040010468
-
-
On Duties 1.7-8, 13-14, 148; 2.35, 3.14-17.
-
On Duties
, pp. 17-18
-
-
-
59
-
-
84876041711
-
-
"natura, id est iure gentium".
-
See especially ibid., 3.23 ("natura, id est iure gentium"). On the origins of the term ius gentium see Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.70-83, and, more authoritatively, Fritz Schulz, A History of Roman Legal Science (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1946), 73 and 137.
-
On Duties
, pp. 323
-
-
-
60
-
-
0040446617
-
-
See especially ibid., 3.23 ("natura, id est iure gentium"). On the origins of the term ius gentium see Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.70-83, and, more authoritatively, Fritz Schulz, A History of Roman Legal Science (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1946), 73 and 137.
-
International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome
, pp. 170-183
-
-
Phillipson1
-
61
-
-
0040010462
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
See especially ibid., 3.23 ("natura, id est iure gentium"). On the origins of the term ius gentium see Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.70-83, and, more authoritatively, Fritz Schulz, A History of Roman Legal Science (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1946), 73 and 137.
-
(1946)
A History of Roman Legal Science
, pp. 73
-
-
Schulz, F.1
-
62
-
-
84872421184
-
-
Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
-
Rhetoric
-
-
-
63
-
-
0004346640
-
-
Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
-
Memorabilia
, pp. 4419-4421
-
-
Xenophon1
-
64
-
-
0003617369
-
-
Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
-
Histories
, pp. 7136
-
-
Herodotus1
-
65
-
-
0040603735
-
-
Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
-
Against Aristocrates
, pp. 61
-
-
-
66
-
-
0040446617
-
-
Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
-
International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome
, pp. 153-154
-
-
Phillipson1
-
68
-
-
0039418321
-
-
cf. von Arnim 1903-24, frag. 640
-
Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61-64; cf. von Arnim 1903-24, frag. 640.
-
-
-
-
70
-
-
0041197815
-
-
On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.64; and On the Nature of the Gods 2.154; see also 2.78-79; Laws 1.23 and 1.32.
-
On the Nature of the Gods
, pp. 2154
-
-
-
71
-
-
0041197815
-
-
On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.64; and On the Nature of the Gods 2.154; see also 2.78-79; Laws 1.23 and 1.32.
-
On the Nature of the Gods
, pp. 278-279
-
-
-
72
-
-
0041197794
-
-
On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.64; and On the Nature of the Gods 2.154; see also 2.78-79; Laws 1.23 and 1.32.
-
Laws
, pp. 123
-
-
-
73
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Laelius is Cicero's advocate of natural law in the Republic, speaking at 3.33-35.
-
Republic
, pp. 333-335
-
-
-
74
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Republic 2.4-5, 2.12-13, 2.14, 2.15, 2.22, 2.26, 2.33, 2.44, 3.24; cf. 2.10, 2.25, 2.27, 2.31, 2.38, 3.16, 3.28,3.42; cf. On Duties 3.41.
-
Republic
, pp. 24-25
-
-
-
75
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Republic 2.4-5, 2.12-13, 2.14, 2.15, 2.22, 2.26, 2.33, 2.44, 3.24; cf. 2.10, 2.25, 2.27, 2.31, 2.38, 3.16, 3.28,3.42; cf. On Duties 3.41.
-
Republic
, pp. 210
-
-
-
76
-
-
0039418318
-
-
Republic 2.4-5, 2.12-13, 2.14, 2.15, 2.22, 2.26, 2.33, 2.44, 3.24; cf. 2.10, 2.25, 2.27, 2.31, 2.38, 3.16, 3.28,3.42; cf. On Duties 3.41.
-
On Duties
, pp. 341
-
-
-
77
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Republic 2.18; see also 2.19-20.
-
Republic
, pp. 218
-
-
-
78
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Republic 2.18; see also 2.19-20.
-
Republic
, pp. 219-220
-
-
-
79
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Ibid., 2.4, 2.5, 2.10, 2.12, 2.16-17, 2.20, 2.26-27;
-
Republic
, pp. 24
-
-
-
80
-
-
84871294606
-
-
cf. 2.45, 3.26.
-
Republic
, pp. 245
-
-
-
81
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Ibid., 1.19, 1.30-31; 2.21-22 (cf. 2.52); 6.9-end.
-
Republic
, pp. 119
-
-
-
82
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Which Scipio pointedly does not regard as divinely revealed (ibid., 6.10).
-
Republic
, pp. 610
-
-
-
83
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Ibid., 1.12.
-
Republic
, pp. 112
-
-
-
84
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Ibid., 6.15-16, 18-19.
-
Republic
, pp. 615-616
-
-
-
85
-
-
0041197817
-
-
See also On Divination 2.41, 2.148-50.
-
On Divination
, pp. 241
-
-
-
86
-
-
0041197815
-
-
On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
-
On the Nature of the Gods
, pp. 12
-
-
-
87
-
-
84870792806
-
-
On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
-
Tusculan Disputations
, pp. 511
-
-
-
88
-
-
0004010604
-
-
On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
-
The City of God
, pp. 59
-
-
St Augustine1
-
89
-
-
0039418314
-
-
chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers"
-
On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
-
The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire
, vol.1
-
-
Gibbon's, E.1
-
90
-
-
0003964183
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press
-
On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
-
(1977)
The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics
-
-
Bull, H.1
-
91
-
-
0041197817
-
-
On Divination 1.8-10; see Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 3, frag. 654;
-
On Divination
, pp. 18-110
-
-
-
93
-
-
0041197817
-
-
Cicero goes so far as to characterize the Stoics as "those superstitious and nigh fanatic philosophers" (On Divination 2.118),
-
On Divination
, pp. 2118
-
-
-
94
-
-
0041197817
-
-
but contrast On Divination 2.51-62 - Cato did indeed mock the soothsayers, just as Chrysippus ridiculed portents (2. 61-62) and Zeno doubted divination through dreams (2.119).
-
On Divination
, pp. 251-262
-
-
-
95
-
-
0041197815
-
-
On the Nature of the Gods 3.93-95. Commenting on these passages, Peter Brown remarks that Cicero "was far too much of a Roman to attack the established religion of his ancestors" (Augustine of Hippo: A Biography [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967], 80).
-
On the Nature of the Gods
, pp. 393-395
-
-
-
96
-
-
0038014343
-
-
Berkeley: University of California Press
-
On the Nature of the Gods 3.93-95. Commenting on these passages, Peter Brown remarks that Cicero "was far too much of a Roman to attack the established religion of his ancestors" (Augustine of Hippo: A Biography [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967], 80).
-
(1967)
Augustine of Hippo: A Biography
, pp. 80
-
-
Brown, P.1
-
98
-
-
0041197815
-
-
Ibid., 3.66-85. Balbus does not anticipate or resolve these difficulties by reference to an afterlife, perhaps because he has been penetrated by the implications of the Stoic contention that devotion to virtue as the sole highest good compels one to hold that immortality would add nothing to happiness (2.153).
-
On the Nature of the Gods
, pp. 366-385
-
-
-
99
-
-
0041197815
-
-
Ibid., 3.86-88; cf. Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions 1048b-c, 1049f-52b; and On Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics 1075e-76a.
-
On the Nature of the Gods
, pp. 386-388
-
-
-
103
-
-
0041197817
-
-
Compare On the Nature of the Gods 2.6-8, 2.166 with 3.11-17 and with On Divination 1.4.
-
On Divination
, pp. 14
-
-
-
112
-
-
4243277536
-
-
On Duties 1.6ff., 3.7ff., 3.20.
-
On Duties
-
-
-
113
-
-
0041197782
-
-
Ibid., 3.12-17.
-
On Duties
, pp. 312-317
-
-
-
115
-
-
0041197781
-
-
Ibid., 3.19-20.
-
On Duties
, pp. 319-320
-
-
-
116
-
-
0039418309
-
-
Ibid., 3.21-26.
-
On Duties
, pp. 321-326
-
-
-
117
-
-
0041197780
-
-
Ibid., 3.27-28.
-
On Duties
, pp. 327-328
-
-
-
118
-
-
0040603723
-
-
Ibid., 3.34, 3.37, 3.39; cf. 3.102 and 104, and Grotius' criticism of Cicero's teaching on oaths in the name of the divinity (On the Laws of War and Peace 2.13.15.1).
-
On Duties
, pp. 334
-
-
-
119
-
-
0041197778
-
-
Ibid., 3.34, 3.37, 3.39; cf. 3.102 and 104, and Grotius' criticism of Cicero's teaching on oaths in the name of the divinity (On the Laws of War and Peace 2.13.15.1).
-
On Duties
, pp. 3102
-
-
-
120
-
-
0041197779
-
-
Ibid., 3.34, 3.37, 3.39; cf. 3.102 and 104, and Grotius' criticism of Cicero's teaching on oaths in the name of the divinity (On the Laws of War and Peace 2.13.15.1).
-
On the Laws of War and Peace
, pp. 213151
-
-
-
121
-
-
0040010445
-
-
On Duties 3.29-32.
-
On Duties
, pp. 329-332
-
-
-
123
-
-
84871294606
-
-
cf. Republic 1.26-29.
-
Republic
, pp. 126-129
-
-
-
124
-
-
0040010447
-
-
On Duties 1.13;
-
On Duties
, pp. 113
-
-
-
125
-
-
0039418300
-
-
cf. 1.18-19.
-
On Duties
, pp. 118-119
-
-
-
126
-
-
0041197790
-
-
Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
-
On Duties
, pp. 119
-
-
-
127
-
-
0039418319
-
-
Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
-
On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things
, pp. 245
-
-
-
128
-
-
0039418302
-
-
Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
-
Laws
, pp. 137
-
-
-
129
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
-
Republic
, pp. 311
-
-
-
130
-
-
0040603732
-
-
Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
-
On Duties
, pp. 128
-
-
-
131
-
-
0041197788
-
-
Ibid., 1.33; see also 1.88-89, 3.32.
-
On Duties
, pp. 133
-
-
-
132
-
-
0039418303
-
-
Ibid., 1.33; see also 1.88-89, 3.32.
-
On Duties
, pp. 188-189
-
-
-
133
-
-
0040010456
-
-
Ibid., 1.34-35.
-
On Duties
, pp. 134-135
-
-
-
134
-
-
0039418308
-
-
Ibid., 1.33-35; cf. 3.46; contrast Dante On Monarchy 2.5.
-
On Duties
, pp. 133-135
-
-
-
135
-
-
0041197791
-
-
Ibid., 1.33-35; cf. 3.46; contrast Dante On Monarchy 2.5.
-
On Duties
, pp. 346
-
-
-
136
-
-
0039418306
-
-
Ibid., 1.33-35; cf. 3.46; contrast Dante On Monarchy 2.5.
-
On Monarchy
, pp. 25
-
-
Dante1
-
137
-
-
0040010449
-
-
On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
-
On Duties
, pp. 226-229
-
-
-
138
-
-
84903037062
-
-
On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
-
On the Law of War and Peace
, pp. 2111-2112
-
-
-
139
-
-
84903037062
-
-
On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
-
On the Law of War and Peace
, pp. 220433
-
-
-
140
-
-
0012705807
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
-
(1991)
Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria
, pp. 289-290
-
-
Pagden, A.1
Lawrence, J.2
-
141
-
-
0007071223
-
-
On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
-
Histories
, pp. 362
-
-
-
142
-
-
0007071223
-
-
On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
-
Histories
, pp. 1837
-
-
-
143
-
-
0041197777
-
-
On Duties 1.35-37; see also Republic 2.31.
-
On Duties
, pp. 135-137
-
-
-
144
-
-
84871294606
-
-
On Duties 1.35-37; see also Republic 2.31.
-
Republic
, pp. 231
-
-
-
145
-
-
0041197786
-
-
On Duties 3.107-8.
-
On Duties
, pp. 3107-3108
-
-
-
146
-
-
0041197785
-
-
Ibid., 1.31-32.
-
On Duties
, pp. 131-132
-
-
-
149
-
-
0040010451
-
-
On Duties 1.38.
-
On Duties
, pp. 138
-
-
-
150
-
-
0039418305
-
-
Ibid., 2.85; see also 1.26 and Dante On Monarchy 2.5, 2.10-11, as well as Paradiso, cantos 6, 19, and 20.
-
On Duties
, pp. 285
-
-
-
151
-
-
0040010450
-
-
Ibid., 2.85; see also 1.26 and Dante On Monarchy 2.5, 2.10-11, as well as Paradiso, cantos 6, 19, and 20.
-
On Duties
, pp. 126
-
-
-
152
-
-
0039418306
-
-
Ibid., 2.85; see also 1.26 and Dante On Monarchy 2.5, 2.10-11, as well as Paradiso, cantos 6, 19, and 20.
-
On Monarchy
, pp. 25
-
-
Dante1
-
153
-
-
84898511740
-
-
cantos 6, 19, and 20.
-
Ibid., 2.85; see also 1.26 and Dante On Monarchy 2.5, 2.10-11, as well as Paradiso, cantos 6, 19, and 20.
-
Paradiso
-
-
-
154
-
-
0040603726
-
-
Compare On Duties 3.43: "the greatest perplexity with respect to duty arises with regard to friendship."
-
On Duties
, pp. 343
-
-
-
155
-
-
0040603728
-
-
Ibid., 1.50-5 8;
-
On Duties
, pp. 150-158
-
-
-
157
-
-
0039418301
-
-
Ibid., 1.51-52.
-
On Duties
, pp. 151-152
-
-
-
159
-
-
0039418296
-
-
The theological dimension of the contemporary revival of Stoic cosmopolitanism becomes especially visible in Derrida, Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 44-46, 52.
-
Derrida, Cosmopolites de Tous les Pays
, pp. 44-46
-
-
|