메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 31, Issue 2, 1998, Pages 235-262

Socratic cosmopolitanism: Cicero's critique and transformation of the stoic ideal

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0032397384     PISSN: 00084239     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0008423900019788     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (26)

References (159)
  • 1
    • 0040010474 scopus 로고
    • International society: Theoretical promises unfulfilled?
    • Consider Ole Waever, "International Society: Theoretical Promises Unfulfilled?" Cooperation and Conflict 26 (1991), 97-128; and Pierre Hassner, La violence et la paix: De la bombe atomique au nettoyage ethnique (Paris: Éditions Esprit, 1995), 343-54, 385.
    • (1991) Cooperation and Conflict , vol.26 , pp. 97-128
    • Waever, O.1
  • 2
  • 3
    • 84927107254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distant compassion: CNN and Borrioboola-Gha
    • See Clifford Orwin, "Distant Compassion: CNN and Borrioboola-Gha," The National Interest 43 (1996), 42-49.
    • (1996) The National Interest , vol.43 , pp. 42-49
    • Orwin, C.1
  • 4
    • 0003416045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paris: Galilée
    • Jacques Derrida, Cosmopolites de tous les pays, encore un effort! (Paris: Galilée, 1997), 20. Derrida cites Hannah Arendt's discussion in Les origines du totalitarisme. L'impérialisme, trans. by Martine Leiris (Paris: Fayard-Seuil, 1984), 239ff., of the decline of the ancient, fundamental ius gentium right of asylum as a major step on the road to the conditions that made totalitarianism possible. Writing in 1950, Arendt notes in particular that this ancient right finds no expression in written international law or the various United Nations declarations of human rights, since they derive from wholly modern and un-Stoic conceptions of the human community and the cosmopolitan principles of justice.
    • (1997) Cosmopolites de Tous les Pays, Encore Un Effort! , pp. 20
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 5
    • 26144459192 scopus 로고
    • cites Hannah Arendt's discussion trans. by Martine Leiris (Paris: Fayard-Seuil)
    • Jacques Derrida, Cosmopolites de tous les pays, encore un effort! (Paris: Galilée, 1997), 20. Derrida cites Hannah Arendt's discussion in Les origines du totalitarisme. L'impérialisme, trans. by Martine Leiris (Paris: Fayard-Seuil, 1984), 239ff., of the decline of the ancient, fundamental ius gentium right of asylum as a major step on the road to the conditions that made totalitarianism possible. Writing in 1950, Arendt notes in particular that this ancient right finds no expression in written international law or the various United Nations declarations of human rights, since they derive from wholly modern and un-Stoic conceptions of the human community and the cosmopolitan principles of justice.
    • (1984) Les Origines du Totalitarisme. L'Impérialisme
    • Derrida1
  • 6
    • 0002881433 scopus 로고
    • The making of global citizenship
    • Jeremy Brecher, John Brown Childs and Jill Cutler, eds., Boston: South End Press
    • See especially Richard Falk, "The Making of Global Citizenship," in Jeremy Brecher, John Brown Childs and Jill Cutler, eds., Global Visions: Beyond the New World Order (Boston: South End Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Global Visions: Beyond the New World Order
    • Falk, R.1
  • 9
    • 0040603738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the common saying, 'this may be true in theory, but it does not apply in practice
    • Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying, 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice," Part 3 ("On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right"); "Idea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent," Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant's Political Writings, trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), esp. 103, where Grotius is explicitly dismissed as a "sorry comforter"; "Doctrine of Right," Part 2 ("Public Right"), Metaphysics of Morals, secs. 2 and 3. Derrida's invocation of Kant (Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 47-52) seems to indicate an insufficient appreciation of Kant's severe reservations about the sort of cosmopolitanism Derrida is championing; Derrida is eventually forced to recognize that there is at least a considerable tension between his position and that of Kant (53-57).
    • On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right , Issue.3 PART
    • Kant, I.1
  • 10
    • 0003020378 scopus 로고
    • Idea for a universal history with cosmopolitan intent
    • Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," Hans Reiss, ed., trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying, 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice," Part 3 ("On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right"); "Idea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent," Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant's Political Writings, trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), esp. 103, where Grotius is explicitly dismissed as a "sorry comforter"; "Doctrine of Right," Part 2 ("Public Right"), Metaphysics of Morals, secs. 2 and 3. Derrida's invocation of Kant (Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 47-52) seems to indicate an insufficient appreciation of Kant's severe reservations about the sort of cosmopolitanism Derrida is championing; Derrida is eventually forced to recognize that there is at least a considerable tension between his position and that of Kant (53-57).
    • (1970) Kant's Political Writings , pp. 103
  • 11
    • 0041197796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Doctrine of right," part 2 ("Public right")
    • secs. 2 and 3
    • Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying, 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice," Part 3 ("On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right"); "Idea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent," Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant's Political Writings, trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), esp. 103, where Grotius is explicitly dismissed as a "sorry comforter"; "Doctrine of Right," Part 2 ("Public Right"), Metaphysics of Morals, secs. 2 and 3. Derrida's invocation of Kant (Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 47-52) seems to indicate an insufficient appreciation of Kant's severe reservations about the sort of cosmopolitanism Derrida is championing; Derrida is eventually forced to recognize that there is at least a considerable tension between his position and that of Kant (53-57).
    • Metaphysics of Morals
  • 12
    • 0003416045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying, 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice," Part 3 ("On the Relationship of Theory to Practice in International Right"); "Idea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent," Seventh Thesis; and "On Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant's Political Writings, trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), esp. 103, where Grotius is explicitly dismissed as a "sorry comforter"; "Doctrine of Right," Part 2 ("Public Right"), Metaphysics of Morals, secs. 2 and 3. Derrida's invocation of Kant (Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 47-52) seems to indicate an insufficient appreciation of Kant's severe reservations about the sort of cosmopolitanism Derrida is championing; Derrida is eventually forced to recognize that there is at least a considerable tension between his position and that of Kant (53-57).
    • Cosmopolites de Tous les Pays , pp. 47-52
    • Derrida1
  • 13
    • 0004039689 scopus 로고
    • Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press
    • Raymond Aron (who has himself been sometimes identified as a leading "realist" - Michael Joseph Smith, Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger [Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986], 2) has observed that it is the tendency of all contemporary realist thought to "think against" (Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, trans. by Richard Howard and Annette Baker Fox [New York: Praeger, 1967], 596).
    • (1986) Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger , pp. 2
    • Smith, M.J.1
  • 14
    • 0039418299 scopus 로고
    • New York: Praeger
    • Raymond Aron (who has himself been sometimes identified as a leading "realist" - Michael Joseph Smith, Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger [Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986], 2) has observed that it is the tendency of all contemporary realist thought to "think against" (Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, trans. by Richard Howard and Annette Baker Fox [New York: Praeger, 1967], 596).
    • (1967) Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations , pp. 596
    • Howard, R.1    Fox, A.B.2
  • 15
    • 0003700672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Sandel is responding directly to an earlier, more popular, version of the Nussbaum thesis: see Michael J. Sandel, Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996), 338-46; Sandel cites Nussbaum, "Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism," Boston Review (October-November 1994), 3.
    • (1996) Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy , pp. 338-346
    • Sandel, M.J.1
  • 16
    • 0001858860 scopus 로고
    • Patriotism and cosmopolitanism
    • October-November
    • Sandel is responding directly to an earlier, more popular, version of the Nussbaum thesis: see Michael J. Sandel, Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996), 338-46; Sandel cites Nussbaum, "Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism," Boston Review (October-November 1994), 3.
    • (1994) Boston Review , pp. 3
    • Sandel1
  • 17
    • 84876041711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cicero On Duties 3.69, 3.74. I cite the works of Cicero and other classical authors according to standard form, using recognized critical editions; unless otherwise noted, all translations from these and other sources are my own.
    • On Duties , pp. 369
    • Cicero1
  • 18
    • 0041197800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.1-3, 2.2-6, 2.23, 2.29, 2.65, 2.67, 2.75-76, 3.1-4; Cicero On the Nature of the Gods 1.7; Cicero Republic 1.6-7; and Cicero On Divination 1.2; 2.6-7.
    • On Duties , pp. 11-13
  • 19
    • 0041197815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.1-3, 2.2-6, 2.23, 2.29, 2.65, 2.67, 2.75-76, 3.1-4; Cicero On the Nature of the Gods 1.7; Cicero Republic 1.6-7; and Cicero On Divination 1.2; 2.6-7.
    • On the Nature of the Gods , pp. 17
    • Cicero1
  • 20
    • 0040010470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.1-3, 2.2-6, 2.23, 2.29, 2.65, 2.67, 2.75-76, 3.1-4; Cicero On the Nature of the Gods 1.7; Cicero Republic 1.6-7; and Cicero On Divination 1.2; 2.6-7.
    • Cicero Republic , pp. 16-17
  • 21
    • 0041197817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.1-3, 2.2-6, 2.23, 2.29, 2.65, 2.67, 2.75-76, 3.1-4; Cicero On the Nature of the Gods 1.7; Cicero Republic 1.6-7; and Cicero On Divination 1.2; 2.6-7.
    • On Divination , pp. 12
    • Cicero1
  • 22
    • 84876041711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Cicero On Duties 3.23, 3.69.
    • On Duties , pp. 323
    • Cicero1
  • 23
    • 0041197812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
    • On Laws and God the Lawgiver , pp. 2198
    • Cicero1
  • 24
    • 0041197813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Isidore of Seville
    • For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
    • Of Etymologies or Origins , pp. 54-57
  • 25
    • 0041197814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
    • From the Founding of the City , pp. 24
    • Livy1
  • 26
    • 0040010458 scopus 로고
    • Brussels: C. Muquardt
    • For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
    • (1882) Le Droit de la Guerre et les Précurseurs de Grotius , pp. 9-13
    • Ernest, N.1
  • 27
    • 0039418323 scopus 로고
    • 2 vols.; London: Macmillan
    • For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
    • (1911) The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome , Issue.1 , pp. 57-58
    • Phillipson, C.1
  • 28
    • 0041073778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1368b7-9
    • For Cicero, and generally thereafter until Francisco Suarez (On Laws and God the Lawgiver 2.19.8; see also Isidore of Seville Of Etymologies or Origins 5.4-7), the "law of nations" was a term referring not simply or primarily to international law, regulating relations among nations and alien individuals, but more broadly to that law or body of legal principles that seems to be commonly held by all civilized peoples: for example, the principle that theft is a punishable offence. International law - for example, the sanctity of ambassadors and the "laws of war" - would be a major subdivision of the "law of nations" so understood (see, for example, Livy From the Founding of the City 2.4; 5.27, 5.36, 5.51; 6.1). See Ernest Nys, Le droit de la guerre et les précurseurs de Grotius (Brussels: C. Muquardt, 1882), 9-13; and Coleman Phillipson, The International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome (2 vols.; London: Macmillan, 1911), 1: 57-58, 70-85, 89-97. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1368b7-9, on the "common law" as comprising "whatever unwritten matters seem to be agreed on by everyone."
    • Rhetoric
    • Aristotle1
  • 29
    • 84886617346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plutarch, in what is probably a deliberate rhetorical exaggeration, goes so far as to suggest that there is a link between Zeno of Citium's Republic and Alexander the Great's cosmopolitan imperial vision (On the Fortune or Virtue of Alexander the Great 329a-b), and Philo Judaeus (On the Creation of the World 3 and 142-43) contends that the biblical account of creation in Genesis is meant to teach the Stoic notion of cosmopolitan natural law and world citizenship (in other words, the principles of Stoicism are in fact the principles of the biblical God).
    • On the Fortune or Virtue of Alexander the Great
    • Plutarch1
  • 30
    • 84867806019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plutarch, in what is probably a deliberate rhetorical exaggeration, goes so far as to suggest that there is a link between Zeno of Citium's Republic and Alexander the Great's cosmopolitan imperial vision (On the Fortune or Virtue of Alexander the Great 329a-b), and Philo Judaeus (On the Creation of the World 3 and 142-43) contends that the biblical account of creation in Genesis is meant to teach the Stoic notion of cosmopolitan natural law and world citizenship (in other words, the principles of Stoicism are in fact the principles of the biblical God).
    • On the Creation of the World , pp. 3
    • Judaeus, P.1
  • 31
    • 0040010475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
    • Symposium , pp. 29-113
    • Xenophon1
  • 32
    • 0003548526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104
    • Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
    • Lives of the Eminent Philosophers
    • Laertius, D.1
  • 33
    • 0039418328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
    • Outlines of Pyrrhonism , pp. 3200
    • Empiricus, S.1
  • 34
    • 0041197809 scopus 로고
    • 4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis
    • Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
    • (1990) Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae , pp. 2139-2509
    • Giannantoni, G.1
  • 35
    • 0041197801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Giannantoni's discussion
    • Xenophon Symposium 2.9-13, 3.4-12, 4.1-6, 4.34-45, 4.61-64, 6.5, 8.3-7. See Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 7 (on Zeno and other Stoics), secs. 1-3, 19 with Bk. 6 (on the Cynics), secs. 1-2, 14, 19, 85, 104; Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism 3.200 and context; for the best collection of the fragments and testimonials of Antisthenes, the Cynics generally and other Socratic precursors of Stoicism, see Gabriele Giannantoni, Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae (4 vols.; 2d ed.; Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990), 2.139-509, 523-89, 648-52; for the scholarly debate over the reliability of the philosophic genealogy offered by Diogenes Laertius, and over the precise relationship of Antisthenes to Cynicism, see Giannantoni's discussion at 3:223-33 and 3.512-27.
  • 36
    • 0003548526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • Lives of the Eminent Philosophers
    • Laertius, D.1
  • 37
    • 84883566408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • Discourses , pp. 142
    • Chrysostom, D.1
  • 38
    • 0040603737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) , vol.5 , pp. 22-27
    • Empiricus, S.1
  • 39
    • 0039418326 scopus 로고
    • H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner), frags. 190, 192, 195
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • (1904) On Stoic Self-contradictions; of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics , vol.1
    • Plutarch1
  • 40
    • 0039418330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • frags. 528, 1195
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • On Stoic Self-contradictions; of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics , vol.2
  • 41
    • 0039418327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • On Stoic Self-contradictions; of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics , vol.3
  • 42
    • 0041197804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things
    • Cicero1
  • 43
    • 0039418329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • Academica , pp. 135-139
  • 44
    • 0041197815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • On the Nature of the Gods , pp. 116
  • 45
    • 0041197817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • On Divination
  • 46
    • 0040010473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • Of Leisure , pp. 4
    • Seneca1
  • 47
    • 25444451744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "On the Cynic Calling."
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 5, 29, 37, 42, 54, 63-64, 69-74; Bk. 7, secs. 25-26, 52, 86-89, 91, 99-109, 119-25, 128-31, 134-39, 142-43, 147-49, 151, 160, 165; Dio Chrysostom Discourses 1.42; 14.16; 15.31; 36.17-38; 59.4; Sextus Empiricus Against the Dogmatists 5 (= Against the Ethicists) 22-27, 59-67, 73-78, 180-81, 190-94, 200-201; Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions; Of Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics; H. von Arnim, ed., Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (4 vols.; Leipzig: Teubner, 1904-23), Vol. 1, frags. 190, 192, 195; Vol. 2, frags. 528, 1195; Vol. 3, frags. of Chrysippus, etc., 16, 314, 323, 324, 327, 330, 354, 366, 548, 567, 604-605, 611, 632, 638, 650; 654, 656, 690, 694, 729, 746, 750, 764, and frag. 117 of Philodemus at 241-42; Cicero On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things, Bk. 3, esp. secs. 11-14, 21-39, 41-73, and Bk. 4, secs. 14-15, 20, 26-43, 45-60, 68-73; Academica 1.35-39; On the Nature of the Gods 1.16, 1.36-41, 2.1-167; On Divination, Bk. 1, secs. 6, 37, 39, 56-57, 72, 82-84, 118, 125-31; Bk. 2, secs. 35-36, 88, 90, 100-102, 130; Seneca Of Leisure 4, 6, 8; the ethical teachings of Epictetus seem to have been close to those of the original Stoics; for the persistent admiration of Cynicism, see Arrian's Discourses of Epictetus, esp. 3.22, "On the Cynic Calling."
    • Discourses of Epictetus , pp. 322
    • Arrian1
  • 48
    • 0003548526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • Lives of the Eminent Philosophers
    • Laertius, D.1
  • 49
    • 0041197799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • frags. 216, 228
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta , vol.1
  • 50
    • 0041197807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta , vol.3
  • 51
    • 0039418322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • Oration in Defense of L. Murena , pp. 61
    • Cicero1
  • 52
    • 0039418319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things , pp. 348
  • 53
    • 0040010459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • Laws , pp. 314
  • 54
    • 0040603734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bk. 2
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • Lucullus (or Academica) , pp. 136-137
  • 55
    • 0039418325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • On Duties , pp. 1128
  • 56
    • 84870792806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • Tusculan Disputations , pp. 454
  • 57
    • 0040010461 scopus 로고
    • Zeno's republic and the origins of natural law
    • Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Bk. 6, secs. 11, 29, 37, 72, 74; Bk. 7, secs. 33-34, 100, 121-25, 131, 188-89; Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 1, frags. 216, 228; Vol. 3, frags. 54, 332, 544, 560, 563, 587, 589, 598-603, 613-19, 623, 625-26, 640, 658, 660-669, 677; Cicero Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61; On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.48, 3.68, 3.75-76, 4.7, 4.21-23, 4.55-56, 4.74; Laws 3.14; Lucullus (or Academica, Bk. 2) 136-37; On Duties 1.128, 1.148; Tusculan Disputations 4.54. For an instructive discussion of the sources, and an intelligent critique of the contemporary scholarship, see also Paul A. Vander Waerdt, "Zeno's Republic and the Origins of Natural Law," in Paul A. Vander Waerdt, ed., The Socratic Movement (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994). I am in agreement with Vander Waerdt's meticulous critical survey and will therefore not reproduce it here.
    • (1994) The Socratic Movement
    • Waerdt, P.A.V.1
  • 58
    • 0040010468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 1.7-8, 13-14, 148; 2.35, 3.14-17.
    • On Duties , pp. 17-18
  • 59
    • 84876041711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "natura, id est iure gentium".
    • See especially ibid., 3.23 ("natura, id est iure gentium"). On the origins of the term ius gentium see Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.70-83, and, more authoritatively, Fritz Schulz, A History of Roman Legal Science (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1946), 73 and 137.
    • On Duties , pp. 323
  • 60
    • 0040446617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See especially ibid., 3.23 ("natura, id est iure gentium"). On the origins of the term ius gentium see Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.70-83, and, more authoritatively, Fritz Schulz, A History of Roman Legal Science (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1946), 73 and 137.
    • International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome , pp. 170-183
    • Phillipson1
  • 61
    • 0040010462 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See especially ibid., 3.23 ("natura, id est iure gentium"). On the origins of the term ius gentium see Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.70-83, and, more authoritatively, Fritz Schulz, A History of Roman Legal Science (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1946), 73 and 137.
    • (1946) A History of Roman Legal Science , pp. 73
    • Schulz, F.1
  • 62
    • 84872421184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
    • Rhetoric
  • 63
    • 0004346640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
    • Memorabilia , pp. 4419-4421
    • Xenophon1
  • 64
    • 0003617369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
    • Histories , pp. 7136
    • Herodotus1
  • 65
    • 0040603735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
    • Against Aristocrates , pp. 61
  • 66
    • 0040446617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rhetoric 1373b4-18, 1375a27ff.; see also 1368b7-9. For prominent examples of references to unwritten laws common among all men, see Xenophon Memorabilia 4.4.19-21; Herodotus Histories 7.136; Demosthenes Against Aristocrates 61; see also Phillipson, International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome, 1.53-54 and 57-58.
    • International Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome , pp. 153-154
    • Phillipson1
  • 68
    • 0039418321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. von Arnim 1903-24, frag. 640
    • Oration in Defense of L. Murena 61-64; cf. von Arnim 1903-24, frag. 640.
  • 70
    • 0041197815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.64; and On the Nature of the Gods 2.154; see also 2.78-79; Laws 1.23 and 1.32.
    • On the Nature of the Gods , pp. 2154
  • 71
    • 0041197815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.64; and On the Nature of the Gods 2.154; see also 2.78-79; Laws 1.23 and 1.32.
    • On the Nature of the Gods , pp. 278-279
  • 72
    • 0041197794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 3.64; and On the Nature of the Gods 2.154; see also 2.78-79; Laws 1.23 and 1.32.
    • Laws , pp. 123
  • 73
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Laelius is Cicero's advocate of natural law in the Republic, speaking at 3.33-35.
    • Republic , pp. 333-335
  • 74
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republic 2.4-5, 2.12-13, 2.14, 2.15, 2.22, 2.26, 2.33, 2.44, 3.24; cf. 2.10, 2.25, 2.27, 2.31, 2.38, 3.16, 3.28,3.42; cf. On Duties 3.41.
    • Republic , pp. 24-25
  • 75
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republic 2.4-5, 2.12-13, 2.14, 2.15, 2.22, 2.26, 2.33, 2.44, 3.24; cf. 2.10, 2.25, 2.27, 2.31, 2.38, 3.16, 3.28,3.42; cf. On Duties 3.41.
    • Republic , pp. 210
  • 76
    • 0039418318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republic 2.4-5, 2.12-13, 2.14, 2.15, 2.22, 2.26, 2.33, 2.44, 3.24; cf. 2.10, 2.25, 2.27, 2.31, 2.38, 3.16, 3.28,3.42; cf. On Duties 3.41.
    • On Duties , pp. 341
  • 77
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republic 2.18; see also 2.19-20.
    • Republic , pp. 218
  • 78
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republic 2.18; see also 2.19-20.
    • Republic , pp. 219-220
  • 79
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 2.4, 2.5, 2.10, 2.12, 2.16-17, 2.20, 2.26-27;
    • Republic , pp. 24
  • 80
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. 2.45, 3.26.
    • Republic , pp. 245
  • 81
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.19, 1.30-31; 2.21-22 (cf. 2.52); 6.9-end.
    • Republic , pp. 119
  • 82
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Which Scipio pointedly does not regard as divinely revealed (ibid., 6.10).
    • Republic , pp. 610
  • 83
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.12.
    • Republic , pp. 112
  • 84
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 6.15-16, 18-19.
    • Republic , pp. 615-616
  • 85
    • 0041197817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also On Divination 2.41, 2.148-50.
    • On Divination , pp. 241
  • 86
    • 0041197815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
    • On the Nature of the Gods , pp. 12
  • 87
    • 84870792806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
    • Tusculan Disputations , pp. 511
  • 88
    • 0004010604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
    • The City of God , pp. 59
    • St Augustine1
  • 89
    • 0039418314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers"
    • On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
    • The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire , vol.1
    • Gibbon's, E.1
  • 90
    • 0003964183 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • On the Nature of the Gods 1.2, 1.10, 1.14, 1.60, 2.2, 2.168, 3.4-5, 3.85; see also especially Tusculan Disputations 5.11. St. Augustine's (The City of God 5.9) and Edward Gibbon's (The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1, chap. 2, sec. "Of Philosophers") radical interpretation of Cicero as an esoteric writer goes beyond anything that can be indubitably established from the texts; but it is fair to say that Cicero recognized, and grasped more profoundly the moral consequences of, the grave problem a leading contemporary has stated as follows: "inquiry has its own morality, and is necessarily subversive of political institutions and movements of all kinds, good as well as bad" (Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics [New York: Columbia University Press, 1977], xv).
    • (1977) The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics
    • Bull, H.1
  • 91
    • 0041197817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Divination 1.8-10; see Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, Vol. 3, frag. 654;
    • On Divination , pp. 18-110
  • 93
    • 0041197817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cicero goes so far as to characterize the Stoics as "those superstitious and nigh fanatic philosophers" (On Divination 2.118),
    • On Divination , pp. 2118
  • 94
    • 0041197817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • but contrast On Divination 2.51-62 - Cato did indeed mock the soothsayers, just as Chrysippus ridiculed portents (2. 61-62) and Zeno doubted divination through dreams (2.119).
    • On Divination , pp. 251-262
  • 95
    • 0041197815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Nature of the Gods 3.93-95. Commenting on these passages, Peter Brown remarks that Cicero "was far too much of a Roman to attack the established religion of his ancestors" (Augustine of Hippo: A Biography [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967], 80).
    • On the Nature of the Gods , pp. 393-395
  • 96
    • 0038014343 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • On the Nature of the Gods 3.93-95. Commenting on these passages, Peter Brown remarks that Cicero "was far too much of a Roman to attack the established religion of his ancestors" (Augustine of Hippo: A Biography [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967], 80).
    • (1967) Augustine of Hippo: A Biography , pp. 80
    • Brown, P.1
  • 98
    • 0041197815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 3.66-85. Balbus does not anticipate or resolve these difficulties by reference to an afterlife, perhaps because he has been penetrated by the implications of the Stoic contention that devotion to virtue as the sole highest good compels one to hold that immortality would add nothing to happiness (2.153).
    • On the Nature of the Gods , pp. 366-385
  • 99
    • 0041197815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 3.86-88; cf. Plutarch On Stoic Self-Contradictions 1048b-c, 1049f-52b; and On Common Conceptions, Against the Stoics 1075e-76a.
    • On the Nature of the Gods , pp. 386-388
  • 100
  • 103
    • 0041197817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare On the Nature of the Gods 2.6-8, 2.166 with 3.11-17 and with On Divination 1.4.
    • On Divination , pp. 14
  • 104
  • 112
    • 4243277536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 1.6ff., 3.7ff., 3.20.
    • On Duties
  • 113
    • 0041197782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 3.12-17.
    • On Duties , pp. 312-317
  • 114
  • 115
    • 0041197781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 3.19-20.
    • On Duties , pp. 319-320
  • 116
    • 0039418309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 3.21-26.
    • On Duties , pp. 321-326
  • 117
    • 0041197780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 3.27-28.
    • On Duties , pp. 327-328
  • 118
    • 0040603723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 3.34, 3.37, 3.39; cf. 3.102 and 104, and Grotius' criticism of Cicero's teaching on oaths in the name of the divinity (On the Laws of War and Peace 2.13.15.1).
    • On Duties , pp. 334
  • 119
    • 0041197778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 3.34, 3.37, 3.39; cf. 3.102 and 104, and Grotius' criticism of Cicero's teaching on oaths in the name of the divinity (On the Laws of War and Peace 2.13.15.1).
    • On Duties , pp. 3102
  • 120
    • 0041197779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 3.34, 3.37, 3.39; cf. 3.102 and 104, and Grotius' criticism of Cicero's teaching on oaths in the name of the divinity (On the Laws of War and Peace 2.13.15.1).
    • On the Laws of War and Peace , pp. 213151
  • 121
    • 0040010445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 3.29-32.
    • On Duties , pp. 329-332
  • 122
  • 123
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Republic 1.26-29.
    • Republic , pp. 126-129
  • 124
  • 125
    • 0039418300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. 1.18-19.
    • On Duties , pp. 118-119
  • 126
    • 0041197790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
    • On Duties , pp. 119
  • 127
    • 0039418319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
    • On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things , pp. 245
  • 128
    • 0039418302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
    • Laws , pp. 137
  • 129
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
    • Republic , pp. 311
  • 130
    • 0040603732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.19, 1.22. As we have seen by now, it is characteristic of Cicero to provoke the reader's thought by combining the exhortation to virtue as the greatest happiness with the insistence that virtue requires self-forgetting devotion to others, together with devotion to virtue for its own sake - which devotion wins for its possessor the greatest glory and in addition the support of the gods, who visit condign punishment on the wicked. Compare, for example, On the Ends of the Good and Bad Things 2.45 with 2.64-65; or Laws 1.37, 1.41, 1.43, 1.48 with 1.58-60; or Republic 3.11 with 6.29; see above all On Duties 1.28 in the light of 1.19, 1.22, 1.70-71, 1.92, 1.153, 3.25, 3.29-31, 3.35, 3.101.
    • On Duties , pp. 128
  • 131
    • 0041197788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.33; see also 1.88-89, 3.32.
    • On Duties , pp. 133
  • 132
    • 0039418303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.33; see also 1.88-89, 3.32.
    • On Duties , pp. 188-189
  • 133
    • 0040010456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.34-35.
    • On Duties , pp. 134-135
  • 134
    • 0039418308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.33-35; cf. 3.46; contrast Dante On Monarchy 2.5.
    • On Duties , pp. 133-135
  • 135
    • 0041197791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.33-35; cf. 3.46; contrast Dante On Monarchy 2.5.
    • On Duties , pp. 346
  • 136
    • 0039418306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.33-35; cf. 3.46; contrast Dante On Monarchy 2.5.
    • On Monarchy , pp. 25
    • Dante1
  • 137
    • 0040010449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
    • On Duties , pp. 226-229
  • 138
    • 84903037062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
    • On the Law of War and Peace , pp. 2111-2112
  • 139
    • 84903037062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
    • On the Law of War and Peace , pp. 220433
  • 140
    • 0012705807 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
    • (1991) Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria , pp. 289-290
    • Pagden, A.1    Lawrence, J.2
  • 141
    • 0007071223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
    • Histories , pp. 362
  • 142
    • 0007071223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 2.26-29. This rather flattering judgment on the concern for morality in the war policy of the Roman republic is seconded by Grotius, at least as regards the Roman attention to the need for a just cause for initiating war. In On the Law of War and Peace 2.1.1.1-2, Grotius says of the Romans: "hardly any race has remained for so long a time scrupulous in examining into the causes of war"; on the other hand, however, Grotius later admits the force in Mithridates' accusation of moral hypocrisy directed against Roman punitive war policy (ibid., 2.20.43.3); see the authorities Grotius collects and cites, as well as Vitoria's favourable remarks on the moral character of Roman imperial foreign policy, in Anthony Pagden and Jeremy Lawrence, eds. and trans., Political Writings of Francisco de Vitoria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 289-90. Polybius is more ironic in his praise of the Roman republic's concern for a just cause of war: on entering into hostilities with Demetrius, the Romans, remarks Polybius, "sought a suitable opportunity and an excuse that would look good to outsiders; for the Romans gave thought to this part of policy, and in doing so thought nobly" (Histories 36.2; but see also 18.37, on Roman generosity to defeated enemies, and in particular to Hannibal and the Carthaginians).
    • Histories , pp. 1837
  • 143
    • 0041197777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 1.35-37; see also Republic 2.31.
    • On Duties , pp. 135-137
  • 144
    • 84871294606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 1.35-37; see also Republic 2.31.
    • Republic , pp. 231
  • 145
    • 0041197786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Duties 3.107-8.
    • On Duties , pp. 3107-3108
  • 146
    • 0041197785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.31-32.
    • On Duties , pp. 131-132
  • 147
  • 149
  • 150
    • 0039418305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 2.85; see also 1.26 and Dante On Monarchy 2.5, 2.10-11, as well as Paradiso, cantos 6, 19, and 20.
    • On Duties , pp. 285
  • 151
    • 0040010450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 2.85; see also 1.26 and Dante On Monarchy 2.5, 2.10-11, as well as Paradiso, cantos 6, 19, and 20.
    • On Duties , pp. 126
  • 152
    • 0039418306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 2.85; see also 1.26 and Dante On Monarchy 2.5, 2.10-11, as well as Paradiso, cantos 6, 19, and 20.
    • On Monarchy , pp. 25
    • Dante1
  • 153
    • 84898511740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cantos 6, 19, and 20.
    • Ibid., 2.85; see also 1.26 and Dante On Monarchy 2.5, 2.10-11, as well as Paradiso, cantos 6, 19, and 20.
    • Paradiso
  • 154
    • 0040603726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare On Duties 3.43: "the greatest perplexity with respect to duty arises with regard to friendship."
    • On Duties , pp. 343
  • 155
    • 0040603728 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.50-5 8;
    • On Duties , pp. 150-158
  • 157
    • 0039418301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 1.51-52.
    • On Duties , pp. 151-152
  • 158
  • 159
    • 0039418296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The theological dimension of the contemporary revival of Stoic cosmopolitanism becomes especially visible in Derrida, Cosmopolites de tous les pays, 44-46, 52.
    • Derrida, Cosmopolites de Tous les Pays , pp. 44-46


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.